Switch to: References

Citations of:

Mathematics, the Loss of Certainty

Critica 13 (39):87-91 (1981)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Human understanding in dialogue: Gadamer's recovery of the genuine: Original article.Lindal Binding - 2008 - Nursing Philosophy 9 (2):121-130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Necessity of Exosomatic Knowledge for Civilization and a Revision to our Epistemology.Ray Scott Percival - 2012 - In Norbert-Bertrand Barbe (ed.), LE NÉANT DANS LA PENSÉE CONTEMPORAINE. Publications du Centre Fran. pp. 136-150.
    The traditional conception of knowledge is justified, true belief. If one looks at a modern textbook on epistemology, the great bulk of questions with which it deals are to do with personal knowledge, as embodied in beliefs and the proper experiences that someone ought to have had in order to have the right (or justification) to know. I intend to argue that due to the explosive growth of knowledge whose domain is “outside the head”, this conception has outlived its relevance. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Précis of Behaviorism: A conceptual reconstruction.G. E. Zuriff - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):687-699.
    The conceptual framework of behaviorism is reconstructed in a logical scheme rather than along chronological lines. The resulting reconstruction is faithful to the history of behaviorism and yet meets the contemporary challenges arising from cognitive science, psycholinguistics, and philosophy. In this reconstruction, the fundamental premise is that psychology is to be a natural science, and the major corollaries are that psychology is to be objective and empirical. To a great extent, the reconstruction of behaviorism is an elaboration of behaviorist views (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Conceptual reconstruction: A reconstruction.G. E. Zuriff - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):716-723.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Structuralism in Phylogenetic Systematics.Richard H. Zander - 2010 - Biological Theory 5 (4):383-394.
    Systematics based solely on structuralist principles is non-science because it is derived from first principles that are inconsistent in dealing with both synchronic and diachronic aspects of evolution, and its evolutionary models involve hidden causes, and unnameable and unobservable entities. Structuralist phylogenetics emulates axiomatic mathematics through emphasis on deduction, and “hypotheses” and “mapped trait changes” that are actually lemmas and theorems. Sister-group-only evolutionary trees have no caulistic element of scientific realism. This results in a degenerate systematics based on patterns of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Structuralism in Phylogenetic Systematics.Richard H. Zander - 2010 - Biological Theory 5 (4):383-394.
    Systematics based solely on structuralist principles is non-science because it is derived from first principles that are inconsistent in dealing with both synchronic and diachronic aspects of evolution, and its evolutionary models involve hidden causes, and unnameable and unobservable entities. Structuralist phylogenetics emulates axiomatic mathematics through emphasis on deduction, and “hypotheses” and “mapped trait changes” that are actually lemmas and theorems. Sister-group-only evolutionary trees have no caulistic element of scientific realism. This results in a degenerate systematics based on patterns of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Philosophy of Ambivalence: Sandra Harding onThe Science Question in Feminism.Alison Wylie - 1987 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (sup1):58-73.
    In the past three decades scholars in virtually every humanistic and social scientific research discipline, and in some natural sciences, have drawn attention to quite striking instances of gender bias in the modes of practice and theorizing typical of traditional fields of research. They generally begin by identifying explicit androcentric biases in definitions of the subject domains appropriate to specific scientific fields. Their primary targets, in this connection, have been research that leaves women out altogether, research that ignores women’s contributions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Liar Paradox.Kuang-Ming Wu - 2015 - Open Journal of Philosophy 5 (5):253-260.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Concrete Thinking.Kuang-Ming Wu - 2015 - Open Journal of Philosophy 5 (1):73-86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mathematical naturalism: Origins, guises, and prospects. [REVIEW]Bart Van Kerkhove - 2006 - Foundations of Science 11 (1-2):5-39.
    During the first half of the twentieth century, mainstream answers to the foundational crisis, mainly triggered by Russell and Gödel, remained largely perfectibilist in nature. Along with a general naturalist wave in the philosophy of science, during the second half of that century, this idealist picture was finally challenged and traded in for more realist ones. Next to the necessary preliminaries, the present paper proposes a structured view of various philosophical accounts of mathematics indebted to this general idea, laying the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The NCTM Standards and the Philosophy of Mathematics.Charalampos Toumasis - 1997 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 16 (3):317-330.
    It is argued that the philosophical and epistemological beliefs about the nature of mathematics have a significant influence on the way mathematics is taught at school. In this paper, the philosophy of mathematics of the NCTM's Standards is investigated by examining is explicit assumptions regarding the teaching and learning of school mathematics. The main conceptual tool used for this purpose is the model of two dichotomous philosophies of mathematics-absolutist versus- fallibilist and their relation to mathematics pedagogy. The main conclusion is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The nature and role of intuition in mathematical epistemology.Paul Thompson - 1998 - Philosophia 26 (3-4):279-319.
    Great intuitions are fundamental to conjecture and discovery in mathematics. In this paper, we investigate the role that intuition plays in mathematical thinking. We review key events in the history of mathematics where paradoxes have emerged from mathematicians' most intuitive concepts and convictions, and where the resulting difficulties led to heated controversies and debates. Examples are drawn from Riemannian geometry, set theory and the analytic theory of the continuum, and include the Continuum Hypothesis, the Tarski-Banach Paradox, and several works by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Grasping the Conceptual Difference Between János Bolyai and Lobachevskii’s Notions of Non-Euclidean Parallelism.János Tanács - 2009 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 63 (5):537-552.
    The paper examines the difference between János Bolyai’s and Lobachevskii’s notion of non-Euclidean parallelism. The examination starts with the summary of a widespread view of historians of mathematics on János Bolyai’s notion of non-Euclidean parallelism used in the first paragraph of his Appendix. After this a novel position of the location and meaning of Bolyai’s term “parallela” in his Appendix is put forward. After that János Bolyai’s Hungarian manuscript, the Commentary on Lobachevskii’s Geometrische Untersuchungen is elaborated in order to see (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reconstructing the Unity of Mathematics circa 1900.David J. Stump - 1997 - Perspectives on Science 5 (3):383-417.
    Standard histories of mathematics and of analytic philosophy contend that work on the foundations of mathematics was motivated by a crisis such as the discovery of paradoxes in set theory or the discovery of non-Euclidean geometries. Recent scholarship, however, casts doubt on the standard histories, opening the way for consideration of an alternative motive for the study of the foundations of mathematics—unification. Work on foundations has shown that diverse mathematical practices could be integrated into a single framework of axiomatic systems (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The significance of a non-reductionist ontology for the discipline of mathematics: A historical and systematic analysis. [REVIEW]D. F. M. Strauss - 2010 - Axiomathes 20 (1):19-52.
    A Christian approach to scholarship, directed by the central biblical motive of creation, fall and redemption and guided by the theoretical idea that God subjected all of creation to His Law-Word, delimiting and determining the cohering diversity we experience within reality, in principle safe-guards those in the grip of this ultimate commitment and theoretical orientation from absolutizing or deifying anything within creation. In this article my over-all approach is focused on the one-sided legacy of mathematics, starting with Pythagorean arithmeticism (“everything (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant’s Critique of Leibniz’s Rejection of Real Opposition.Henry Michael Southgate - 2013 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 3 (1):91-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Two Complementary Types of Total Time Derivative in Classical Field Theories and Maxwell’s Equations.R. Smirnov-Rueda - 2005 - Foundations of Physics 35 (10):1695-1723.
    Close insight into mathematical and conceptual structure of classical field theories shows serious inconsistencies in their common basis. In other words, we claim in this work to have come across two severe mathematical blunders in the very foundations of theoretical hydrodynamics. One of the defects concerns the traditional treatment of time derivatives in Eulerian hydrodynamic description. The other one resides in the conventional demonstration of the so-called Convection Theorem. Both approaches are thought to be necessary for cross-verification of the standard (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Is it behaviorism?B. F. Skinner - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):716-716.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Partial realizations of Hilbert's program.Stephen G. Simpson - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (2):349-363.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • “Suspicion,” “fear,” “contamination,” “great dangers,” and behavioral fictions.Charles P. Shimp - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):715-716.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The formal-structural view of logical consequence.Gila Sher - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (2):241-261.
    In a recent paper, “The Concept of Logical Consequence,” W. H. Hanson criticizes a formal-structural characterization of logical consequence in Tarski and Sher. Hanson accepts many principles of the formal-structural view. Relating to Sher 1991 and 1996a, he says.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The Formal-Structural View of Logical Consequence.Gila Sher - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (2):241-261.
    This paper offers a response to William’s Hanson’s criticism of Sher’s formal-structural conception of logical consequence and logical constants.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Theological Underpinnings of the Modern Philosophy of Mathematics.Vladislav Shaposhnikov - 2016 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 44 (1):147-168.
    The study is focused on the relation between theology and mathematics in the situation of increasing secularization. My main concern in the second part of this paper is the early-twentieth-century foundational crisis of mathematics. The hypothesis that pure mathematics partially fulfilled the functions of theology at that time is tested on the views of the leading figures of the three main foundationalist programs: Russell, Hilbert and Brouwer.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowledge of Abstract Objects in Physics and Mathematics.Michael J. Shaffer - 2017 - Acta Analytica 32 (4):397-409.
    In this paper a parallel is drawn between the problem of epistemic access to abstract objects in mathematics and the problem of epistemic access to idealized systems in the physical sciences. On this basis it is argued that some recent and more traditional approaches to solving these problems are problematic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Peano's axioms in their historical context.Michael Segre - 1994 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 48 (3-4):201-342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A Rational Belief: The Method of Discovery in the Complex Variable.Lorena Segura & Juan Matías Sepulcre - 2016 - Foundations of Science 21 (1):189-194.
    The importance of mathematics in the context of the scientific and technological development of humanity is determined by the possibility of creating mathematical models of the objects studied under the different branches of Science and Technology. The arithmetisation process that took place during the nineteenth century consisted of the quest to discover a new mathematical reality in which the validity of logic would stand as something essential and central. Nevertheless, in contrast to this process, the development of mathematical analysis within (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The gentrification of behaviorism.Roger Schnaitter - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):714-715.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Average behaviorism is unedifying.William W. Rozeboom - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):712-714.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Problems with Fallibilism as a Philosophy of Mathematics Education.Stuart Rowlands, Ted Graham & John Berry - 2011 - Science & Education 20 (7-8):625-654.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Christopher Pincock: Mathematics and Scientific Representation.Stuart Rowlands - 2013 - Science & Education 22 (4):867-872.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Temporal molarity in behavior.Howard Rachlin - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):711-712.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is the Uncertainty of Mathematics the Real Source of Its Intellectual Charm?Christopher Ormell - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 27 (1):125-133.
    Christopher Ormell; Is the Uncertainty of Mathematics the Real Source of Its Intellectual Charm?, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 27, Issue 1, 30 May.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Shall I Compare Thee to a Minkowski-Ricardo-Leontief-Metzler Matrix of the Mosak-Hicks Type?: Or, Rhetoric, Mathematics, and the Nature of Neoclassical Economic Theory.Philip Mirowski - 1987 - Economics and Philosophy 3 (1):67-95.
    Is rhetoric just a new and trendy way toépater les bourgeois?Unfortunately, I think that the newfound interest of some economists in rhetoric, and particularly Donald McCloskey in his new book and subsequent responses to critics, gives that impression. After economists have worked so hard for the past five decades to learn their sums, differential calculus, real analysis, and topology, it is a fair bet that one could easily hector them about their woeful ignorance of the conjugation of Latin verbs or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • John Dewey's theory of inquiry. Quantum physics, ecology and the myth of the scientific method.Joaquín Fernández Mateo - 2020 - Agora 40 (1):133-154.
    The modern philosophy of science has not succeeded in defining conclusively what the scientific method consists in. On the contrary, scientific practice seems to consist in a methodological pluralism, a definition that connects with essential fragments of John Dewey's Logic, the Theory of Inquiry. For Dewey, even the forms of logic emerge from the problems defined in indeterminate situations. A historical example was the introduction of the notion of complementarity in physics, which allowed the interpretation of two confusingly paradoxical experiments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The pragmatics of survival and the nobility of defeat.M. Jackson Marr - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):709-710.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neglect of psychology's silent majority makes a molehill out of a mountain: There is more to behaviorism than Hull and Skinner.Melvin H. Marx - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):710-711.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is behaviorism under stimuls control?John C. Marshall - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):710-710.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some naturalistic reflections on set theoretic method.Penelope J. Maddy - 2001 - Topoi 20 (1):17-27.
    My ultimate goal in this paper is to illuminate, from a naturalistic point of view, the significance of the application of mathematics in the natural sciences for the practice of contemporary set theory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Mathematical existence.Penelope Maddy - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (3):351-376.
    Despite some discomfort with this grandly philosophical topic, I do in fact hope to address a venerable pair of philosophical chestnuts: mathematical truth and existence. My plan is to set out three possible stands on these issues, for an exercise in compare and contrast.' A word of warning, though, to philosophical purists (and perhaps of comfort to more mathematical readers): I will explore these philosophical positions with an eye to their interconnections with some concrete issues of set theoretic method.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Про передумови розвитку наукової думки в стародавній греції.Volodymyr M. Kuklin - 2018 - Вісник Харківського Національного Університету Імені В. Н. Каразіна. Серія «Філософія. Філософські Перипетії» 59:160-175.
    У даній роботі обговорюється процес зародження науки як суспільного інституту. Наука пройшла шлях від фрагментарних успіхів у справі усвідомленні світу до формування комплексу уявлень про природу речей і явищ. Мейнстрімом становлення планетарної цивілізації все ж слід визнати еволюцію наукових уявлень саме в Євразії, поблизу теплих морів і в умовах сприятливого клімату. І тут, за загальною думкою, потрібно віддати належне внеску еллінів, які створили соціальної уклад, який сприяв розвитку філософії, що дала змогу побудувати фундамент для науки. Наприклад, елліни Мілетської школи поставили (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The reconstruction of a conceptual reconstruction.Leonard Krasner - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):708-709.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mathematical Naturalism: Origins, Guises, and Prospects.Bart Kerkhove - 2006 - Foundations of Science 11 (1):5-39.
    During the first half of the twentieth century, mainstream answers to the foundational crisis, mainly triggered by Russell and Gödel, remained largely perfectibilist in nature. Along with a general naturalist wave in the philosophy of science, during the second half of that century, this idealist picture was finally challenged and traded in for more realist ones. Next to the necessary preliminaries, the present paper proposes a structured view of various philosophical accounts of mathematics indebted to this general idea, laying the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Zuriff's counterrevolution.Howard H. Kendler - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):707-708.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Zuriff on observability.Max Hocutt - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):706-707.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rebuilding behaviorism: Too many relatives on the construction site?Philip N. Hineline - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):706-706.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Historical Objections Against the Number Line.Albrecht Heeffer - 2011 - Science & Education 20 (9):863-880.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A socially relevant philosophy of science? Resources from standpoint theory's controversiality.Sandra Harding - 2004 - Hypatia 19 (1):25-47.
    : Feminist standpoint theory remains highly controversial: it is widely advocated, used to guide research and justify its results, and yet is also vigorously denounced. This essay argues that three such sites of controversy reveal the value of engaging with standpoint theory as a way of reflecting on and debating some of the most anxiety-producing issues in contemporary Western intellectual and political life. Engaging with standpoint theory enables a socially relevant philosophy of science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • A Socially Relevant Philosophy of Science? Resources from Standpoint Theory's Controversiality.Sandra Harding - 2004 - Hypatia 19 (1):25-47.
    Feminist standpoint theory remains highly controversial: it is widely advocated, used to guide research and justify its results, and yet is also vigorously denounced. This essay argues that three such sites of controversy reveal the value of engaging with standpoint theory as a way of reflecting on and debating some of the most anxiety-producing issues in contemporary Western intellectual and political life. Engaging with standpoint theory enables a socially relevant philosophy of science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • “Higher criticism” of behaviorism.D. W. Hamlyn - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):705-705.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • First-person behaviorism.George Graham - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):704-705.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations