Switch to: References

Citations of:

Brain stimulation and the threshold of conscious experience

In John C. Eccles (ed.), Brain and Conscious Experience: Study Week September 28 to October 4, 1964, of the Pontificia Academia Scientiarum. Springer. pp. 165--181 (1966)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Experimental Evidence for Subjective Referral of a Sensory Experience Backwards in Time: Reply to P. S. Churchland.Benjamin Libet - 1981 - Philosophy of Science 48 (June):182-197.
    Evidence that led to the hypothesis of a backwards referral of conscious sensory experiences in time, and the experimental tests of its predictions, is summarized. Criticisms of the data and the conclusion by Churchland that this hypothesis is untenable are analysed and found to be based upon misconceptions and faulty evaluations of facts and theory. Subjective referral in time violates no neurophysiological principles or data and is compatible with the theory of "mental" and "physical" correspondence.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   114 citations  
  • Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action.Benjamin Libet - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):529-66.
    Voluntary acts are preceded by electrophysiological (RPs). With spontaneous acts involving no preplanning, the main negative RP shift begins at about200 ms. Control experiments, in which a skin stimulus was timed (S), helped evaluate each subject's error in reporting the clock times for awareness of any perceived event.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   761 citations  
  • On the alleged backward referral of experience and its relevance to the mind-body problem.Patricia Smith Churchland - 1981 - Philosophy of Science 48 (June):165-81.
    A remarkable hypothesis has recently been advanced by Libet and promoted by Eccles which claims that there is standardly a backwards referral of conscious experiences in time, and that this constitutes empirical evidence for the failure of identity of brain states and mental states. Libet's neurophysiological data are critically examined and are found insufficient to support the hypothesis. Additionally, it is argued that even if there is a temporal displacement phenomenon to be explained, a neurophysiological explanation is most likely.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Is human information processing conscious?Max Velmans - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):651-69.
    Investigations of the function of consciousness in human information processing have focused mainly on two questions: (1) where does consciousness enter into the information processing sequence and (2) how does conscious processing differ from preconscious and unconscious processing. Input analysis is thought to be initially "preconscious," "pre-attentive," fast, involuntary, and automatic. This is followed by "conscious," "focal-attentive" analysis which is relatively slow, voluntary, and flexible. It is thought that simple, familiar stimuli can be identified preconsciously, but conscious processing is needed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   348 citations  
  • Epi-arguments for epiphenomenalism.Bruce Mangan - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):689-690.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conscious acts and their objects.Fred Dretske - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):676-677.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evidence against epiphenomenalism.Ned Block - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):670-672.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   140 citations  
  • Consciousness and content in learning: Missing or misconceived?Richard A. Carlson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):673-674.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)A neural correlate of consciousness related to repression.Howard Shevrin, Jess H. Ghannam & Benjamin W. Libet - 2002 - Consciousness and Cognition 11 (2):334-41.
    In previous research Libet discovered that a critical time period for neural activation is necessary in order for a stimulus to become conscious. This necessary time period varies from subject to subject. In this current study, six subjects for whom the time for neural activation of consciousness had been previously determined were administered a battery of psychological tests on the basis of which ratings were made of degree of repressiveness. As hypothesized, repressive subjects had a longer critical time period for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On subjective back-referral and how long it takes to become conscious of a stimulus: A reinterpretation of Libet's data.Susan Pockett - 2002 - Consciousness and Cognition 11 (2):141-61.
    The original data reported by Benjamin Libet and colleagues are reinterpreted, taking into account the facilitation which is experimentally demonstrated in the first of their series of articles. It is shown that the original data equally well or better support a quite different set of conclusions from those drawn by Libet. The new conclusions are that it takes only 80 ms for stimuli to come to consciousness and that “subjective back-referral of sensations in time” to the time of the stimulus (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • On the premature demise of causal functions for consciousness in human information processing.Dale Dagenbach - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):675-675.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Free will and the functions of consciousness.Bruce Bridgeman - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):540-540.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Consciousness and motor control.Arthur C. Danto - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):540-541.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Neural/mental chronometry and chronotheology.Gerald S. Wasserman - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):556-557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Problems with the psychophysics of intention.Bruno G. Breitmeyer - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):539-540.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness-potential). The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act.Benjamin Libet, Curtis A. Gleason, Elwood W. Wright & Dennis K. Pearl - 1983 - Brain 106 (3):623--664.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   326 citations  
  • Brain stimulation and conscious experience.Daniel A. Pollen - 2004 - Consciousness and Cognition 13 (3):626-645.
    Libet discovered that a substantial duration (> 0.5-1.0 s) of direct electrical stimulation of the surface of the somatosensory cortex at threshold currents is required before human subjects can report that a conscious somatosensory experience had occurred. Using a reaction time method we confirm that a similarly long stimulation duration at threshold currents is required for activation of elementary visual experiences (phosphenes) in human subjects following stimulation of the surface of the striate cortex. However, the reaction times for the subject (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Merleau-Ponty on Human Motility and Libet’s Paradox.T. Brian Mooney & Damien Norris - 2007 - Indo-Pacific Journal of Phenomenology 7 (1):1-9.
    In 1979, neuroscientists Libet, Wright, Feinstein and Pearl introduced the “delay-and-antedating” hypothesis/paradox based on the results of an on-going series of experiments dating back to 1964 that measured the neural adequacy [brain wave activity] of “conscious sensory experience”. What is fascinating about the results of this experiment is the implication, especially when considered in the light of Merleau-Ponty’s notions of “intentionality” and the “pre-reflective life of human motility”, that the body, and hence not solely the mind, is a thinking thing. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Developing concepts of consciousness.Aaron Sloman - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):694-695.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Conscious and unconscious processes: Same or different?Philip M. Merikle & Jim Cheesman - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):547-548.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consciousness from a first-person perspective.Max Velmans - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):702-726.
    This paper replies to the first 36 commentaries on my target article on “Is human information processing conscious?” (Behavioral and Brain Sciences,1991, pp.651-669). The target article focused largely on experimental studies of how consciousness relates to human information processing, tracing their relation from input through to output, while discussion of the implications of the findings both for cognitive psychology and philosophy of mind was relatively brief. The commentaries reversed this emphasis, and so, correspondingly, did the reply. The sequence of topics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • Commentary on shevrin, ghannam, and Libet, A Neural Correlate of Consciousness Related to Repression.Susan Pockett - 2002 - Consciousness and Cognition 11 (2):342-344.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)A Neural Correlate of Consciousness Related to Repression.Howard Shevrin, Jess H. Ghannam & Benjamin Libet - 2002 - Consciousness and Cognition 11 (2):334-341.
    In previous research Libet discovered that a critical time period for neural activation is necessary in order for a stimulus to become conscious. This necessary time period varies from subject to subject. In this current study, six subjects for whom the time for neural activation of consciousness had been previously determined were administered a battery of psychological tests on the basis of which ratings were made of degree of repressiveness. As hypothesized, repressive subjects had a longer critical time period for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The great subjective back-referral debate: Do neural responses increase during a train of stimuli?Susan Pockett - 2006 - Consciousness and Cognition 15 (3):551-559.
    Evidence is summarised for and against the hypothesis that potentiation or facilitation of neural responses during a train of threshold-level stimuli occurred in the experiments reported by Libet et al. . It is concluded that such potentiation probably did occur. Since the main arguments for the existence of subjective backwards referral take it as given that such potentiation did not occur, it is further concluded that the main arguments for the existence of subjective backwards referral fail.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Understanding awareness at the neuronal level.Christof Koch & Francis Crick - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):683-685.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Memory with and without recollective experience.John M. Gardiner - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):678-679.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Has consciousness a sharp edge?Robert A. M. Gregson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):679-680.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Limits of preconscious processing.Albrecht Werner Inhoff - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):680-681.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The time course of conscious processing: Vetoes by the uninformed?Robert W. Doty - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):541-542.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • No conscious or co-conscious?Graham F. Wagstaff - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):700-700.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Attention is necessary for word integration.Geoffrey Underwood - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):698-698.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Observing protocol.Judith Economos - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):677-677.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theory and evidence relating cerebral processes to conscious will.Benjamin Libet - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):558-566.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Asynchronous Introspection Theory: The Underpinnings of Phenomenal Consciousness in Temporal Illusion.Shuo Chen, Changle Zhou, Jing Li & Hua Peng - 2017 - Minds and Machines 27 (2):315-330.
    A new theory of the neuropsychological underpinnings of phenomenal consciousness, “asynchronous introspection theory,” is proposed that emphasizes asynchrony between different neurocognitive processes. We provide a detailed explanation of how a mind might arrive at a cognitive structure isomorphic to the cognitive structure that would emerge from experiential qualia. The theory suggests that a temporal illusion is created because of the mismatch between the real physical timeline and the neurally constructed timeline composed inside a person’s brain. This temporal illusion leads to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consciousness may still have a processing role to play.Robert Van Gulick - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):699-700.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Pardon, your dualism is showing.Charles C. Wood - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):557-558.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Consciousness: Limited but consequential.Timothy D. Wilson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):701-701.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Absolute timing of mental activities.Gerald S. Wasserman & King-Leung Kong - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (2):243-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  • Nineteenth-century psychology and twentieth-century electrophysiology do not mix.C. H. Vanderwolf - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):555-555.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Conscious wants and self-awareness.Robert Van Gulick - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):555-556.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Mind before matter?Geoffrey Underwood & Pekka Niemi - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):554-555.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • The uncertainty principle in psychology.John S. Stamm - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):553-554.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Damn! There goes that ghost again!Keith E. Stanovich - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):696-698.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Dissociating consciousness from cognition.David Spiegel - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):695-696.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A lawful first-person psychology involving a causal consciousness: A psychoanalytic solution.Howard Shevrin - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):693-694.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Isn't the first-person perspective a bad third-person perspective?W. Schaeken & G. D'Ydewalle - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):692-693.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conscious intention is a mental fiat.Eckart Scheerer - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):552-553.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Are the origins of any mental process available to introspection?Michael D. Rugg - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):552-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sensory events with variable central latencies provide inaccurate clocks.Gary B. Rollman - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):551-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Timing volition: Questions of what and when about W.James L. Ringo - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):550-551.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations