Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Christoph Besold on confederation rights and duties of esteem in diplomatic relations.Andreas Blank - 2022 - Intellectual History Review 32 (1):51-70.
    The self-worth of political communities is often understood to be an expression of their position in a hierarchy of power; if so, then the desire for self-worth is a source of competition and conflict in international relations. In early modern German natural law theories, one finds the alternative view, according to which duties of esteem toward political communities should reflect the degree to which they fulfill the functions of civil government. The present article offers a case study, examining the views (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Esteem and self-esteem in early modern ethics and politics. An overview.Andreas Blank - 2022 - Intellectual History Review 32 (1):1-14.
    The self-worth of political communities is often understood to be an expression of their position in a hierarchy of power; if so, then the desire for self-worth is a source of competition and conflict in international relations. In early modern German natural law theories, one finds the alternative view, according to which duties of esteem toward political communities should reflect the degree to which they fulfill the functions of civil government. The present article offers a case study, examining the views (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The influence of classical Stoicism on John Locke’s theory of self-ownership.Lisa Hill & Prasanna Nidumolu - 2021 - History of the Human Sciences 34 (3-4):3-24.
    The most important parent of the idea of property in the person (self-ownership) is undoubtedly John Locke. In this article, we argue that the origins of this idea can be traced back as far as the third century BCE, to classical Stoicism. Stoic cosmopolitanism, with its insistence on impartiality and the moral equality of all persons, lays the foundation for the idea of self-ownership, which is then given support in the doctrine of oikeiosis and the corresponding belief that nature had (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Problem of the Kantian Line.Samuel Kahn - 2019 - International Philosophical Quarterly 59 (2):193-217.
    In this paper I discuss the problem of the Kantian line. The problem arises because the locus of value in Kantian ethics is rationality, which (counterintuitively) seems to entail that there are no duties to groups of beings like children. I argue that recent attempts to solve this problem by Wood and O’Neill overlook an important aspect of it before posing my own solution.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Philosophical Anthropology and the Interpersonal Theory of the Affect of Shame.Matthew Stewart Rukgaber - 2018 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 49 (1):83-112.
    This article argues that shame is fundamentally interpersonal. It is opposed to the leading interpretation of shame in the field of moral psychology, which is the cognitivist, morally rationally, autonomous view of shame as a negative judgment about the self. That view of shame abandons the social and interpersonal essence of shame. I will advance the idea, as developed by the tradition of philosophical anthropology and, in particular, in the works of Helmuth Plessner, Erwin Straus, F. J. J. Buytendijk, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Lasst uns den Weg einer neuen Ontologie einschlagen! (Teil 1).Gianluigi Segalerba - 2017 - Analele Universitatii Din Craiova, Seria Filosofie 40 (2):91-183.
    The present essay is the first part of an analysis regarding aspects of Aristotle’s ontology. Aristotle’s ontology is, in my opinion, a formal ontology that examines the fundamental structures of reality and that investigates the features belonging to entities such as substance, quantity, quality, universals. Aristotle’s ontology investigates, moreover, the reciprocal relations existing between these entities. Aristotle’s interpretation of universals is not, in my opinion, a nominalist interpretation of universals: I do not think Aristotle regards universals as being only mental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A sabedoria humana de Pierre Charron: a ciência e o exercício cético do espírito forte.Estéfano Luís de Sá Winter - 2013 - Filosofia Do Renascimento E Moderna (Encontro Nacional Anpof).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Locke on Toleration.Ingrid Creppell - 1996 - Political Theory 24 (2):200-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Child, philosophy and education:discussing the intellectual sources of Philosophy for Children.Hannu Juuso - unknown
    The study analyzes the theoretical basis of the Philosophy for Children (P4C) program elaborated by Matthew Lipman. The aim is, firstly, to identify the main philosophical and pedagogical principles of P4C based on American pragmatism, and to locate their pedagogization and possible problems in Lipman’s thinking. Here the discussion is especially targeted to the thinking of John Dewey and George H. Mead as well as Lev Vygotsky, whom Lipman himself names as the most pivotal sources for his own thinking. On (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Cudworth on Mind, Body, and Plastic Nature.Keith Allen - 2013 - Philosophy Compass 8 (4):337-347.
    Ralph Cudworth (1617–1688) is a member of the group of philosophers and theologians commonly called ‘the Cambridge Platonists’. Although not part of the canon of great early modern philosophers, Cudworth’s work is of more than merely passing interest. Cudworth was an influential philosopher in the early modern period both for his criticisms of contemporaries like Hobbes, Descartes, and Spinoza, and for his own distinctive philosophical views. This entry focusses on Cudworth’s views on mind and body, considering both his criticisms of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Lockean Social Epistemology.Lisa McNulty - 2013 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 47 (4):524-536.
    Locke's reputation as a sceptic regarding testimony, and the resultant mockery by epistemologists with social inclinations, is well known. In particular Michael Welbourne, in his article ‘The Community of Knowledge’ (1981), depicts Lockean epistemology as fundamentally opposed to a social conception of knowledge, claiming that he ‘could not even conceive of the possibility of a community of knowledge’. This interpretation of Locke is flawed. Whilst Locke does not grant the honorific ‘knowledge’ to anything short of certainty, he nonetheless held what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • In the Shadow of Emile: Pedagogues, Pediatricians, Physical Education, 1686–1762. [REVIEW]Danièle Tosato-Rigo - 2012 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 31 (5):449-463.
    This article takes as its starting point the commonplace that Rousseau’s Emile enabled his contemporaries to discover not only childhood but physical education. Focused on what the pedestal erected for Jean-Jacques somewhat overshadows, a brief historiographic overview and a survey of some major writings on education before Rousseau (by the Abbot Fleury, John Locke, Jean-Pierre de Crousaz and Charles Rollin) will show that the ideas defended by the writer were not innovative in the slightest. But also, and this seems far (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Portrait of the Teacher as Friend and Artist: The example of Jean‐Jacques Rousseau.Hunter Mcewan - 2011 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 43 (5):508-520.
    The following is a reflection on the possibility of teaching by example, and especially as the idea of teaching by example is developed in the work of Jean-Jacques Rousseau. My thesis is that Rousseau created a literary version of himself in his writings as an embodiment of his philosophy, rather in the same way and with the same purpose that Plato created a version of Socrates. This figure of Rousseau—a sort of philosophical portrait of the man of nature—is represented as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Cruelty, Kindness, and Unnecessary Suffering.Tom Regan - 1980 - Philosophy 55 (214):532 - 541.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • John Locke: Optimist or pessimist?1.Peter A. Schouls - 1994 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 2 (2):51 – 73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Testimony and proof in early-modern England.R. W. Serjeantson - 1999 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 30 (2):195-236.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Passions and affections.Amy Schmitter - 2013 - In Peter R. Anstey (ed.), The Oxford handbook of British philosophy in the seventeenth century. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 442-471.
    This chapter examines the views of seventeenth-century British philosophers on passions and affections. It explains that about 8,000 books published during this period mentioned passion and that it started with Thomas Wright's Passions of the Mind in General. The chapter also explores the intellectual basis of the writers who wrote about passion – which includes Augustinianism, Aristotelianism, stoicism, Epicureanism, and medicine – and furthermore, analyzes the relevant works of Francis Bacon, Thomas Hobbes, Henry More, and Lord Shaftesbury.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Locke, anthropology and models of the mind.G. A. J. Rogers - 1993 - History of the Human Sciences 6 (1):73-87.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Locke’s Newtonianism and Lockean Newtonianism.Lisa J. Downing - 1997 - Perspectives on Science 5 (3):285-310.
    I explore Locke’s complex attitude toward the natural philosophy of his day by focusing on Locke’s own treatment of Newton’s theory of gravity and the presence of Lockean themes in defenses of Newtonian attraction/gravity by Maupertuis and other early Newtonians. In doing so, I highlight the inadequacy of an unqualified labeling of Locke as “mechanist” or “Newtonian.”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Popper's Third World: Moral habits, moral habitat and their maintenance.Jānis Ozoliņš - 2010 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 42 (7):742-761.
    If we accept Popper's idea that the human habitat is described in terms of three worlds, and that there are overlaps between these three worlds, our moral actions and values will also be subject to the same kinds of consideration as a repertoire of behaviours exhibited in a physical environment. We will develop moral habits in a moral habitat and our moral behaviours will also be dependent on the kind of moral habitat in which we find ourselves.There are three main (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Should Democracy Grow up? Children and Voting Rights.Steven Lecce - 2009 - Intergenerational Justice Review 4 (4).
    This paper examines whether or not children’s continued electoral exclusion is morally defensible. Ultimately; there is a deep tension between the egalitarian presuppositions of democracy and our apparent unwillingness to grant children voting rights. Unless a plausible distinction can be found; then; between adults and children that also tracks the underlying reasons for endorsing democracy in the first place; the continued political disenfranchisement of our youngest citizens is shown for what it is: social injustice. e paper begins by exploring some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Hobbes and God in Locke’s law of nature.Daniel E. Burns - 2024 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 32 (5):999-1029.
    Locke bases his moral and political philosophy on his doctrine of the ‘law of nature’. Scholars have debated the content and grounding of this law and its relationship to Christian theology. The ambiguities of the Lockean natural law’s content are traceable to an unclear grammatical construction in a crucial passage of the Treatises of Government, which can be resolved by following out a related set of arguments in that work. The ambiguities of the Lockean natural law’s grounding can then be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cultivating a capability for empathy in the Bologna system—the shortcomings of economics and the importance of the civil.Dirk Schuck & Lorenzo Pecchi - 2024 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 58 (1):1-23.
    A central aim of the original Bologna Declaration in 1999 was to give the opportunity of advancement in education to every European citizen. According to the Declaration, this goal is worth achieving not simply in order to provide better-qualified workers within the European Union, rather, the aim of higher education within the European Union is understood in a holistic sense as a prerequisite for the composition of a well-functioning European civil society. How can such an ambitious goal be achieved? In (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Democratizing philosophy for children: of difference and diverse ideas in Gareth Matthews’ Corpus.Sheron Fraser-Burgess - 2023 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 57 (2):592-601.
    Maughn Rollins Gregory and Meghan Jane Laverty’s Gareth B. Matthews, The Child’s Philosopher explores the Philosophy for Children movement, and the way the work of Gareth B. Matthews carried forward its key components. In this paper, I consider the impact of Matthews’ embeddedness within a Western philosophical tradition, even as he strives mightily to propose a broad-minded approach to P4C. I draw upon the work of Amasa Philip Ndofirepi to explore the tensions and possibilities in reconciling Western and non-Western approaches (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Cognitive Goods, Open Futures and the Epistemology of Education.J. Adam Carter - 2020 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 54 (2):449-466.
    What cognitive goods do children plausibly have a right to in an education? In attempting to answer this question, I begin with a puzzle centred around Joel Feinberg's observation that a denial of certain cognitive goods can violate a child's right to an open future. I show that propositionalist, dispositionalist and objectualist characterisations of the kinds of cognitive goods children have a right to, run in to problems. A promising alternative is then proposed and defended, one that is inspired in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Revisiting the Early Modern Philosophical Canon.Lisa Shapiro - 2016 - Journal of the American Philosophical Association 2 (3):365-383.
    ABSTRACT:I reflect critically on the early modern philosophical canon in light of the entrenchment and homogeneity of the lineup of seven core figures: Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, Berkeley, Hume, and Kant. After distinguishing three elements of a philosophical canon—a causal story, a set of core philosophical questions, and a set of distinctively philosophical works—I argue that recent efforts contextualizing the history of philosophy within the history of science subtly shift the central philosophical questions and allow for a greater range of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Dewey as Virtue Epistemologist: Open‐Mindedness and the Training of Thought in Democracy and Education.Ben Kotzee - 2018 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 52 (2):359-373.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Modern Construction of Childhood: What Does It Do to the Paradox of Modernity?Guoping Zhao - 2010 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 30 (3):241-256.
    The examination of the modern construction of subject is not over yet. Although many thinkers have exhausted its conceptual ambiguities and practical consequences, its impact is far from fully understood without an analysis of the construction of childhood for the future subject. In this essay, I problematize five constructions of childhood that emerged in the modern time and scrutinize the impasses of logic or conceptual ambiguities within, along with the practical consequences thereof. I explore how the modern construction of childhood (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The ground of Locke's law of nature.Thomas G. West - 2012 - Social Philosophy and Policy 29 (2):1-50.
    Research Articles Thomas G. West, Social Philosophy and Policy, FirstView Article.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Influence and development: Two basic paradigms of education. [REVIEW]Jürgen Oelkers - 1994 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 13 (2):91-109.
    The article discusses two basic paradigms of western educational theory, namely the concept of “influence” and the concept of “development”. Two historical contextes are analyzed, John Locke's theory of human learning and Jean-Jacques Rousseau's theory of natural development. Both theories are rejected in favour of a position beyond “influence” and “development”. This position of a theory of education ( Erziehung ) is marked with the term “moral communication”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Introduction.Fabio Paglieri - 2005 - Topoi 24 (2):117-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When Loneliness Evolves into Solitude: The Answer to the Self from Within.Kuo Bian - 2021 - Open Journal of Philosophy 11 (4):620-631.
    Loneliness and solitude have similar attributes to individuals, but there is a critical variance between the two regarding the impact on the individual. Loneliness is an unpleasant feeling in a broad sense, while according to some philosophers, solitude is regarded as a joyful necessity when one establishes a deep relationship with the outside world. This article aims to develop a sensible account of the difference between solitude and loneliness by looking at some insightful philosophical viewpoints. Importantly, this article aims to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Reply to My Critics.Anik Waldow - 2023 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 31 (2):253-265.
    In this article, I engage with the queries, comments, and suggestions raised by my commentators. I proceed in the order of the original contributions, which more or less follows the order to the ch...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is all formative influence immoral?John Tillson - 2018 - Ethics and Education 13 (2):208-220.
    Is it true that all formative influence is unethical, and that we ought to avoid influencing children (and indeed anyone at all)? There are more or less defensible versions of this doctrine, and we shall follow some of the strands of argument that lead to this conclusion. It seems that in maintaining that all influence is immoral, one commits oneself to the idea that children have innate teleologies, that these may be frustrated, and that to frustrate a child’s innate teleology (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • To mould or to bring out? Human nature, anthropology and educational utopianism.Marianna Papastephanou - 2014 - Ethics and Education 9 (2):157-175.
    Against narrow understandings of educational research, this article defends the relevance of philosophical anthropology to ethico-political education and contests its lack of space in the philosophy of education. My approximation of this topic begins with comments on philosophical anthropology; proceeds with examples from the history of educational ideas that illustrate what is at stake in placing realism, impossibility and education side by side; and moves to what anthropologically counts as realism or realistic expectations from education. The etymology of the word (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Learning to trust our students.Barbara J. Thayer-Bacon - 2012 - Ethics and Education 7 (2):149-161.
    Thayer-Bacon uses this opportunity to further explore Rancière's ideas concerning equality as described in The Ignorant Schoolmaster and their connection to democracy, as he explains in Hatred of Democracy. For Rancière, intelligence and equality are synonymous terms, just as reason and will are synonymous terms. Rancière recommends the only way to really teach a student is by viewing the student as an equal. Thayer-Bacon learned to view students as equals through her experience as a Montessori teacher, and so she brings (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mechanism, resemblance and secondary qualities: From Descartes to Locke.Keith Allen - 2008 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 16 (2):273 – 291.
    Locke’s argument for the primary-secondary quality distinction is compared with Descartes’s argument (in the Principles of Philosophy) for the distinction between mechanical modifications and sensible qualities. I argue that following Descartes, Locke’s argument for the primary-secondary quality distinction is an essentially a priori argument, based on our conception of substance, and the constraints on intelligible bodily interaction that this conception of substance sets.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Maximal preference utilitarianism as an educational aspiration.Andrew Stables - 2016 - Ethics and Education 11 (3):299-309.
    This paper attempts to square libertarian principles with the reality of formal education by asking how far we should and can allow people to do as they wish in educational settings. The major focus is on children in schools, as the concept ‘childhood’ ipso facto implies restrictions on doing as one wishes, and schools as institutions entail inevitable constraints. Children by definition tend to enjoy stronger protection rights but weaker liberty rights than adults. A local preferential calculus is developed as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Джон лок про мовчання як аргумент і прояв поваги в аргументації.Олена Щербина & Наталія Щербина - 2019 - Sententiae 38 (2):6-18.
    In the article, referring to the method of rational reconstruction described by R. Rorty, an analysis of some works of J. Locke has been made in order to identify new prospects in John Locke's philosophy researches. As a result, it’s been demonstrated the presence of silence as an argument and a manifestation of respect J. Locke’s research of realms of cognition, political philosophy and philosophy of education. This is not covered in modern John Locke's philosophy researches. The authors emphasize that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The philosopher’s family: Plato and Derrida.Sean Gaston - 2021 - Angelaki 26 (6):3-14.
    It appears that a long, monotonous and patriarchal tradition in the history of philosophy has insisted on the absence of the family. Prompted by Derrida’s Glas, this article suggests that any ethic...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Between horror and boredom: fairy tales and moral education.David Lewin - 2020 - Ethics and Education 15 (2):213-231.
    Where do a child’s morals come from? Interactions with other human beings provide arguably the primary contexts for moral development: family, friends, teachers and other people. It is the artistic products of human activity that this essay considers: literature, film, art, music. Specifically, I will consider some philosophical issues concerning the influence of folk and fairy tales on moral development. I will discuss issues of representation and reduction: in particular, how far should stories for children elide the complexities inherent to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • There is no such thing as environmental ethics.P. Aarne Vesilind - 1996 - Science and Engineering Ethics 2 (3):307-318.
    Engineers and scientists, whose professional responsibilities often influence the natural environment, have sought to develop an environmental ethic that will be in tune with their attitudes toward the non-human environment, and that will assist them in decision making regarding questions of environmental quality. In this paper the classical traditions in normative ethics are explored in an attempt to formulate such an environmental ethic. I conclude, however, that because the discipline of ethics is directed at person-person interactions, ethics as a scholarly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Education and society: A plea for a historicised approach.Raf Vanderstraeten - 2004 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 38 (2):195–206.
    In the course of the ‘long’ eighteenth century, ways of thinking in the Western world transformed in fundamental ways; even words that remained the same took on new meanings. In the field of the history of ideas, the period 1700–1850 is also called the ‘saddle-period’. Philosophers of history have argued that the new basic concepts that emerged at this time indicate how social reality has come to be comprehended in the modern era. Various segments of the population relied on them (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Saving Locke from Marx: The labor theory of value in intellectual property theory.Adam Mossoff - 2012 - Social Philosophy and Policy 29 (2):283-317.
    Research Articles Adam Mossoff, Social Philosophy and Policy, FirstView Article.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Silence as an Argument and a Manifestation of Respect in the Argumentation in John Locke's Works.Olena Shcherbyna & Nataliia Shcherbyna - 2019 - Sententiae 38 (2):6-18.
    In the article, referring to the method of rational reconstruction described by R. Rorty, an analysis of some works of J. Locke has been made in order to identify new prospects in John Locke's philosophy researches. As a result, it’s been demonstrated the presence of silence as an argument and a manifestation of respect J. Locke’s research of realms of cognition, political philosophy and philosophy of education. This is not covered in modern John Locke's philosophy researches. The authors emphasize that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • 3.17 John Locke on the Relationship between God and Morality.Peter P. Cvek - 2012 - Ultimate Reality and Meaning 35 (3-4):260-285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Yearning for Wholeness: Spirituality in Educational Philosophy.Angela Hurley - 2012 - Philosophical Studies in Education 43:128 - 137.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark