Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Logique, Raisonnement et Rationalité.Matías Osta-Vélez - 2014 - Dissertation, Université de Paris 1 Panthéon-Sorbonne
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • La physique naïve: un essai d'ontologie.Barry Smith & Roberto Casati - 1993 - Intellectica 17 (2):173--197.
    The project of a naive physics has been the subject of attention in recent years above all in the artificial intelligence field, in connection with work on common-sense reasoning, perceptual representation and robotics. The idea of a theory of the common-sense world is however much older than this, having its roots not least in the work of phenomenologists and Gestalt psychologists such as Kohler, Husserl, Schapp and Gibson. This paper seeks to show how contemporary naive physicists can profit from a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Models, rules and expertise.Rosemary J. Stevenson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):366-366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Gestalt theory, formal models and mathematical modeling.Abraham S. Luchins & Edith H. Luchins - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):355-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Précis of Deduction.Philip N. Johnson-Laird & Ruth M. J. Byrne - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):323-333.
    How do people make deductions? The orthodox view in psychology is that they use formal rules of inference like those of a “natural deduction” system.Deductionargues that their logical competence depends, not on formal rules, but on mental models. They construct models of the situation described by the premises, using their linguistic knowledge and their general knowledge. They try to formulate a conclusion based on these models that maintains semantic information, that expresses it parsimoniously, and that makes explicit something not directly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Making reasoning more reasonable: Event-coherence and assemblies.Günther Palm - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):470-470.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Temporal synchrony and the speed of visual processing.Simon J. Thorpe - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):473-474.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computational and biological constraints in the psychology of reasoning.Mike Oaksford & Mike Malloch - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):468-469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Making a middling mousetrap.Michael R. W. Dawson & Istvan Berkeley - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):454-455.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Time phases, pointers, rules and embedding.John A. Barnden - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):451-452.
    This paper is a commentary on the target article by Lokendra Shastri & Venkat Ajjanagadde [S&A]: “From simple associations to systematic reasoning: A connectionist representation of rules, variables and dynamic bindings using temporal synchrony” in same issue of the journal, pp.417–451. -/- It puts S&A's temporal-synchrony binding method in a broader context, comments on notions of pointing and other ways of associating information - in both computers and connectionist systems - and mentions types of reasoning that are a challenge to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Non-monotonicity and Informal Reasoning: Comment on Ferguson (2003).Mike Oaksford & Ulrike Hahn - 2006 - Argumentation 20 (2):245-251.
    In this paper, it is argued that Ferguson’s (2003, Argumentation 17, 335–346) recent proposal to reconcile monotonic logic with defeasibility has three counterintuitive consequences. First, the conclusions that can be derived from his new rule of inference are vacuous, a point that as already made against default logics when there are conflicting defaults. Second, his proposal requires a procedural “hack” to the break the symmetry between the disjuncts of the tautological conclusions to which his proposal leads. Third, Ferguson’s proposal amounts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A simplicity principle in unsupervised human categorization.Emmanuel M. Pothos & Nick Chater - 2002 - Cognitive Science 26 (3):303-343.
    We address the problem of predicting how people will spontaneously divide into groups a set of novel items. This is a process akin to perceptual organization. We therefore employ the simplicity principle from perceptual organization to propose a simplicity model of unconstrained spontaneous grouping. The simplicity model predicts that people would prefer the categories for a set of novel items that provide the simplest encoding of these items. Classification predictions are derived from the model without information either about the number (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Die Struktur der Common-Sense Welt.Barry Smith - 1994 - Logos. Anales Del Seminario de Metafísica [Universidad Complutense de Madrid, España] 1:422-449.
    Die zeitgenössischen Philosophen haben zwar der Sprache, die wir verwenden, um die Welt der alltäglichen Erfahrung zu beschreiben oder um uns in dieser Welt zurechtzufinden, große Aufmerksamkeit geschenkt, sie haben sich jedoch – von einigen Ausnahmen abgesehen – geweigert, diese Welt selbst als passendes Objekt theoretischer Betrachtungen anzusehen. Im folgenden werde ich versuchen zu zeigen, wie es möglich ist, die Common-Sense-Welt als ontologisch eigenständiges Untersuchungsobjekt zu verstehen. Gleichzeitig werde ich mich bemühen, deutlich zu zeigen, wie eine solch eigenständige Behandlung uns (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Dual processes, probabilities, and cognitive architecture.Mike Oaksford & Nick Chater - 2012 - Mind and Society 11 (1):15-26.
    It has been argued that dual process theories are not consistent with Oaksford and Chater’s probabilistic approach to human reasoning (Oaksford and Chater in Psychol Rev 101:608–631, 1994 , 2007 ; Oaksford et al. 2000 ), which has been characterised as a “single-level probabilistic treatment[s]” (Evans 2007 ). In this paper, it is argued that this characterisation conflates levels of computational explanation. The probabilistic approach is a computational level theory which is consistent with theories of general cognitive architecture that invoke (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Against Logicist Cognitive Science.Mike Oaksford & Nick Chater - 1991 - Mind and Language 6 (1):1-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   172 citations  
  • Naive physics.Barry Smith & Roberto Casati - 1994 - Philosophical Psychology 7 (2):227 – 247.
    The project of a 'naive physics' has been the subject of attention in recent years above all in the artificial intelligence field, in connection with work on common-sense reasoning, perceptual representation and robotics. The idea of a theory of the common-sense world is however much older than this, having its roots not least in the work of phenomenologists and Gestalt psychologists such as K hler, Husserl, Schapp and Gibson. This paper seeks to show how contemporary naive physicists can profit from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • The rational analysis of mind and behavior.Nick Chater & Mike Oaksford - 2000 - Synthese 122 (1-2):93-131.
    Rational analysis (Anderson 1990, 1991a) is an empiricalprogram of attempting to explain why the cognitive system isadaptive, with respect to its goals and the structure of itsenvironment. We argue that rational analysis has two importantimplications for philosophical debate concerning rationality. First,rational analysis provides a model for the relationship betweenformal principles of rationality (such as probability or decisiontheory) and everyday rationality, in the sense of successfulthought and action in daily life. Second, applying the program ofrational analysis to research on human reasoning (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Form and content in semantics.Y. Wilks - 1990 - Synthese 82 (3):329-51.
    This paper continues a strain of intellectual complaint against the presumptions of certain kinds of formal semantics (the qualification is important) and their bad effects on those areas of artificial intelligence concerned with machine understanding of human language. After some discussion of the use of the term epistemology in artificial intelligence, the paper takes as a case study the various positions held by McDermott on these issues and concludes, reluctantly, that, although he has reversed himself on the issue, there was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perceptual symbol systems.Lawrence W. Barsalou - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (4):577-660.
    Prior to the twentieth century, theories of knowledge were inherently perceptual. Since then, developments in logic, statis- tics, and programming languages have inspired amodal theories that rest on principles fundamentally different from those underlying perception. In addition, perceptual approaches have become widely viewed as untenable because they are assumed to implement record- ing systems, not conceptual systems. A perceptual theory of knowledge is developed here in the context of current cognitive science and neuroscience. During perceptual experience, association areas in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   740 citations  
  • Pouring liquids: A study in commonsense physical reasoning.Ernest Davis - 2008 - Artificial Intelligence 172 (12-13):1540-1578.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • M. Shanahan, Solving the Frame Problem☆☆MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 1997. 410 pp. $55.00 (cloth). ISBN 0-262-19384-1. http://mitpress.mit.edu/book-home.tcl?isbn = 0262193841. [REVIEW]Vladimir Lifschitz - 2000 - Artificial Intelligence 123 (1-2):265-268.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Review of Ernest Davis: Representations of Commonsense Knowledge. [REVIEW]Barry Smith - 1994 - Minds and Machines 4 (2):245-249.
    Review of a compendium of alternative formal representations of common-sense knowledge. The book is centered largely on formal representations drawn from first-order logic, and thus lies in the tradition of Kenneth Forbus, Patrick Hayes and Jerry Hobbs.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • There is no need for (even fully fleshed out) mental models to map onto formal logic.Paul Pollard - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):363-364.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The logical content of theories of deduction.Wilfrid Hodges - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):353-354.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Useful ideas for exploiting time to engineer representations.Richard Rohwer - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):471-471.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • S eeingand visualizing: I T' S n otwhaty ou T hink.Zenon Pylyshyn - unknown
    6. Seeing With the Mind’s Eye 1: The Puzzle of Mental Imagery .................................................6-1 6.1 What is the puzzle about mental imagery?..............................................................................6-1 6.2 Content, form and substance of representations ......................................................................6-6 6.3 What is responsible for the pattern of results obtained in imagery studies?.................................6-8..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Introduction: Machine learning as philosophy of science.Kevin B. Korb - 2004 - Minds and Machines 14 (4):433-440.
    I consider three aspects in which machine learning and philosophy of science can illuminate each other: methodology, inductive simplicity and theoretical terms. I examine the relations between the two subjects and conclude by claiming these relations to be very close.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • From simple associations to systematic reasoning: A connectionist representation of rules, variables, and dynamic binding using temporal synchrony.Lokendra Shastri & Venkat Ajjanagadde - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):417-51.
    Human agents draw a variety of inferences effortlessly, spontaneously, and with remarkable efficiency – as though these inferences were a reflexive response of their cognitive apparatus. Furthermore, these inferences are drawn with reference to a large body of background knowledge. This remarkable human ability seems paradoxical given the complexity of reasoning reported by researchers in artificial intelligence. It also poses a challenge for cognitive science and computational neuroscience: How can a system of simple and slow neuronlike elements represent a large (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   124 citations  
  • The frame problem: An AI fairy tale. [REVIEW]Kevin B. Korb - 1998 - Minds and Machines 8 (3):317-351.
    I analyze the frame problem and its relation to other epistemological problems for artificial intelligence, such as the problem of induction, the qualification problem and the "general" AI problem. I dispute the claim that extensions to logic (default logic and circumscriptive logic) will ever offer a viable way out of the problem. In the discussion it will become clear that the original frame problem is really a fairy tale: as originally presented, and as tools for its solution are circumscribed by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Similarity and rules: distinct? exhaustive? empirically distinguishable?Ulrike Hahn & Nick Chater - 1998 - Cognition 65 (2-3):197-230.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Everyday reasoning and logical inference.Jon Barwise - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):337-338.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Deconstruction of neural data yields biologically implausible periodic oscillations.Walter J. Freeman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):458-459.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reasoning, learning and neuropsychological plausibility.Joachim Diederich - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):455-456.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dynamic bindings by real neurons: Arguments from physiology, neural network models and information theory.Reinhard Eckhorn - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):457-458.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The structures of the common-sense world.Barry Smith - 1995 - Acta Philosophica Fennica 58:290–317.
    While contemporary philosophers have devoted vast amounts of attention to the language we use in describing and finding our way about the world of everyday experience, they have, with few exceptions, refused to see this world itself as a fitting object of theoretical concern. In what follows I shall seek to show how the commonsensical world might be treated ontologically as an object of investigation in its own right. At the same time I shall seek to establish how such a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Why cognitive science is not formalized folk psychology.Martin Pickering & Nick Chater - 1995 - Minds and Machines 5 (3):309-337.
    It is often assumed that cognitive science is built upon folk psychology, and that challenges to folk psychology are therefore challenges to cognitive science itself. We argue that, in practice, cognitive science and folk psychology treat entirely non-overlapping domains: cognitive science considers aspects of mental life which do not depend on general knowledge, whereas folk psychology considers aspects of mental life which do depend on general knowledge. We back up our argument on theoretical grounds, and also illustrate the separation between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Plausible inference and implicit representation.Malcolm I. Bauer - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):452-453.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Connectionism and syntactic binding of concepts.Georg Dorffner - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):456-457.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Monotonicity in Practical Reasoning.Kenneth G. Ferguson - 2003 - Argumentation 17 (3):335-346.
    Classic deductive logic entails that once a conclusion is sustained by a valid argument, the argument can never be invalidated, no matter how many new premises are added. This derived property of deductive reasoning is known as monotonicity. Monotonicity is thought to conflict with the defeasibility of reasoning in natural language, where the discovery of new information often leads us to reject conclusions that we once accepted. This perceived failure of monotonic reasoning to observe the defeasibility of natural-language arguments has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mental imagery.Nigel J. T. Thomas - 2001 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Mental imagery (varieties of which are sometimes colloquially refered to as “visualizing,” “seeing in the mind's eye,” “hearing in the head,” “imagining the feel of,” etc.) is quasi-perceptual experience; it resembles perceptual experience, but occurs in the absence of the appropriate external stimuli. It is also generally understood to bear intentionality (i.e., mental images are always images of something or other), and thereby to function as a form of mental representation. Traditionally, visual mental imagery, the most discussed variety, was thought (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • More models just means more difficulty.N. E. Wetherick - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):367-368.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The content of mental models.Paolo Legrenzi & Maria Sonino - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):354-355.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some difficulties about deduction.L. Jonathan Cohen - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):341-342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deductive reasoning: What are taken to be the premises and how are they interpreted?Samuel Fillenbaum - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):348-349.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A number of questions about a question of number.Alan Garnham - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):350-351.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Do simple associations lead to systematic reasoning?Steven Sloman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):471-472.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Self-organizing neural models of categorization, inference and synchrony.Stephen Grossberg - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):460-461.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Do mental models provide an adequate account of syllogistic reasoning performance?Stephen E. Newstead - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):359-360.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Guest editorial — Introduction.Andy Clark & Rudi Lutz - 1990 - AI and Society 4 (1):3-16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Should first-order logic be neurally plausible?David S. Touretzky & Scott E. Fahlman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):474-475.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark