Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A Unified Theory of Truth and Paradox.Lorenzo Rossi - 2019 - Review of Symbolic Logic 12 (2):209-254.
    The sentences employed in semantic paradoxes display a wide range of semantic behaviours. However, the main theories of truth currently available either fail to provide a theory of paradox altogether, or can only account for some paradoxical phenomena by resorting to multiple interpretations of the language. In this paper, I explore the wide range of semantic behaviours displayed by paradoxical sentences, and I develop a unified theory of truth and paradox, that is a theory of truth that also provides a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Adding a Conditional to Kripke’s Theory of Truth.Lorenzo Rossi - 2016 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 45 (5):485-529.
    Kripke’s theory of truth, 690–716; 1975) has been very successful but shows well-known expressive difficulties; recently, Field has proposed to overcome them by adding a new conditional connective to it. In Field’s theories, desirable conditional and truth-theoretic principles are validated that Kripke’s theory does not yield. Some authors, however, are dissatisfied with certain aspects of Field’s theories, in particular the high complexity. I analyze Field’s models and pin down some reasons for discontent with them, focusing on the meaning of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Intrinsically II 11 Relations.Ivan N. Soskov - 1996 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 42 (1):109-126.
    An external characterization of the inductive sets on countable abstract structures is presented. The main result is an abstract version of the classical Suslin-Kleene characterization of the hyperarithmetical sets.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Dimension Versus Number of Variables, and Connectivity, too.Gregory L. McColm - 1995 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 41 (1):111-134.
    We present game-theoretic characterizations of the complexity/expressibility measures “dimension” and “the number of variables” as Least Fixed Point queries. As an example, we use these characterizations to compute the dimension and number of variables of Connectivity and Connectivity.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Levels of implication and type free theories of classifications with approximation operator.Andrea Cantini - 1992 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 38 (1):107-141.
    We investigate a theory of Frege structures extended by the Myhill-Flagg hierarchy of implications. We study its relation to a property theory with an approximation operator and we give a proof theoretical analysis of the basic system involved. MSC: 03F35, 03D60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Finite level borel games and a problem concerning the jump hierarchy.Harold T. Hodes - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (4):1301-1318.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Monotone inductive definitions over the continuum.Douglas Cenzer - 1976 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 41 (1):188-198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The truth is never simple.John P. Burgess - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):663-681.
    The complexity of the set of truths of arithmetic is determined for various theories of truth deriving from Kripke and from Gupta and Herzberger.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Some Notes on Truths and Comprehension.Thomas Schindler - 2018 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 47 (3):449-479.
    In this paper we study several translations that map models and formulae of the language of second-order arithmetic to models and formulae of the language of truth. These translations are useful because they allow us to exploit results from the extensive literature on arithmetic to study the notion of truth. Our purpose is to present these connections in a systematic way, generalize some well-known results in this area, and to provide a number of new results. Sections 3 and 4 contain (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Field’s logic of truth.Vann McGee - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 147 (3):421-432.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • How to develop Proof‐Theoretic Ordinal Functions on the basis of admissible ordinals.Michael Rathjen - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):47-54.
    In ordinal analysis of impredicative theories so-called collapsing functions are of central importance. Unfortunately, the definition procedure of these functions makes essential use of uncountable cardinals whereas the notation system that they call into being corresponds to a recursive ordinal. It has long been claimed that, instead, one should manage to develop such functions directly on the basis of admissible ordinals. This paper is meant to show how this can be done. Interpreting the collapsing functions as operating directly on admissible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • On expandability of models of peano arithmetic to models of the alternative set theory.Athanassios Tzouvaras - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (2):452-460.
    We give a sufficient condition for a countable model M of PA to be expandable to an ω-model of AST with absolute Ω-orderings. The condition is in terms of saturation schemes or, equivalently, in terms of the ability of the model to code sequences which have some kind of definition in (M, ω). We also show that a weaker scheme of saturation leads to the existence of wellorderings of the model with nice properties. Finally, we answer affirmatively the question of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Monotone inductive definitions in explicit mathematics.Michael Rathjen - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (1):125-146.
    The context for this paper is Feferman's theory of explicit mathematics, T 0 . We address a problem that was posed in [6]. Let MID be the principle stating that any monotone operation on classifications has a least fixed point. The main objective of this paper is to show that T 0 + MID, when based on classical logic, also proves the existence of non-monotone inductive definitions that arise from arbitrary extensional operations on classifications. From the latter we deduce that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Ordinals connected with formal theories for transfinitely iterated inductive definitions.W. Pohlers - 1978 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 43 (2):161-182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The mathematical import of zermelo's well-ordering theorem.Akihiro Kanamori - 1997 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 3 (3):281-311.
    Set theory, it has been contended, developed from its beginnings through a progression ofmathematicalmoves, despite being intertwined with pronounced metaphysical attitudes and exaggerated foundational claims that have been held on its behalf. In this paper, the seminal results of set theory are woven together in terms of a unifying mathematical motif, one whose transmutations serve to illuminate the historical development of the subject. The motif is foreshadowed in Cantor's diagonal proof, and emerges in the interstices of the inclusion vs. membership (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Number of variables is equivalent to space.Neil Immerman, Jonathan Buss & David Barrington - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):1217-1230.
    We prove that the set of properties describable by a uniform sequence of first-order sentences using at most k + 1 distinct variables is exactly equal to the set of properties checkable by a Turing machine in DSPACE[n k ] (where n is the size of the universe). This set is also equal to the set of properties describable using an iterative definition for a finite set of relations of arity k. This is a refinement of the theorem PSPACE = (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On characterizing Spector classes.Leo A. Harrington & Alexander S. Kechris - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (1):19-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tarskian and Kripkean truth.Volker Halbach - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (1):69-80.
    A theory of the transfinite Tarskian hierarchy of languages is outlined and compared to a notion of partial truth by Kripke. It is shown that the hierarchy can be embedded into Kripke's minimal fixed point model. From this results on the expressive power of both approaches are obtained.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Coinductive formulas and a many-sorted interpolation theorem.Ursula Gropp - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (3):937-960.
    We use connections between conjunctive game formulas and the theory of inductive definitions to define the notions of a coinductive formula and its approximations. Corresponding to the theory of conjunctive game formulas we develop a theory of coinductive formulas, including a covering theorem and a normal form theorem for many sorted languages. Applying both theorems and the results on "model interpolation" obtained in this paper, we prove a many-sorted interpolation theorem for ω 1 ω-logic, which considers interpolation with respect to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Complete problems for fixed-point logics.Martin Grohe - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (2):517-527.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Some model theory for game logics.Judy Green - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (2):147-152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The logic of choice.Andreas Blass & Yuri Gurevich - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):1264-1310.
    The choice construct (choose x: φ(x)) is useful in software specifications. We study extensions of first-order logic with the choice construct. We prove some results about Hilbert's ε operator, but in the main part of the paper we consider the case when all choices are independent.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Type-free truth.Thomas Schindler - 2015 - Dissertation, Ludwig Maximilians Universität München
    This book is a contribution to the flourishing field of formal and philosophical work on truth and the semantic paradoxes. Our aim is to present several theories of truth, to investigate some of their model-theoretic, recursion-theoretic and proof-theoretic aspects, and to evaluate their philosophical significance. In Part I we first outline some motivations for studying formal theories of truth, fix some terminology, provide some background on Tarski’s and Kripke’s theories of truth, and then discuss the prospects of classical type-free truth. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reaching Transparent Truth.Pablo Cobreros, Paul Égré, David Ripley & Robert van Rooij - 2013 - Mind 122 (488):841-866.
    This paper presents and defends a way to add a transparent truth predicate to classical logic, such that and A are everywhere intersubstitutable, where all T-biconditionals hold, and where truth can be made compositional. A key feature of our framework, called STTT (for Strict-Tolerant Transparent Truth), is that it supports a non-transitive relation of consequence. At the same time, it can be seen that the only failures of transitivity STTT allows for arise in paradoxical cases.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • Axiomatizing Kripke’s Theory of Truth.Volker Halbach & Leon Horsten - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (2):677 - 712.
    We investigate axiomatizations of Kripke's theory of truth based on the Strong Kleene evaluation scheme for treating sentences lacking a truth value. Feferman's axiomatization KF formulated in classical logic is an indirect approach, because it is not sound with respect to Kripke's semantics in the straightforward sense: only the sentences that can be proved to be true in KF are valid in Kripke's partial models. Reinhardt proposed to focus just on the sentences that can be proved to be true in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • Ordinal spectra of first-order theories.John Stewart Schlipf - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (4):492-505.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Completeness of L (P).Philip W. Grant - 1978 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 24 (19-24):357-364.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Minimal predicates, fixed-points, and definability.Johan van Benthem - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (3):696-712.
    Minimal predicates P satisfying a given first-order description φ(P) occur widely in mathematical logic and computer science. We give an explicit first-order syntax for special first-order ‘PIA conditions’ φ(P) which guarantees unique existence of such minimal predicates. Our main technical result is a preservation theorem showing PIA-conditions to be expressively complete for all those first-order formulas that are preserved under a natural model-theoretic operation of ‘predicate intersection’. Next, we show how iterated predicate minimization on PIA-conditions yields a language MIN(FO) equal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Explicit mathematics with the monotone fixed point principle.Michael Rathjen - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (2):509-542.
    The context for this paper is Feferman's theory of explicit mathematics, a formal framework serving many purposes. It is suitable for representing Bishop-style constructive mathematics as well as generalized recursion, including direct expression of structural concepts which admit self-application. The object of investigation here is the theory of explicit mathematics augmented by the monotone fixed point principle, which asserts that any monotone operation on classifications (Feferman's notion of set) possesses a least fixed point. To be more precise, the new axiom (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Uniform inductive definability and infinitary languages.Anders M. Nyberg - 1976 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 41 (1):109-120.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • About the proof-theoretic ordinals of weak fixed point theories.Gerhard Jäger & Barbara Primo - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (3):1108-1119.
    This paper presents several proof-theoretic results concerning weak fixed point theories over second order number theory with arithmetic comprehension and full or restricted induction on the natural numbers. It is also shown that there are natural second order theories which are proof-theoretically equivalent but have different proof-theoretic ordinals.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Refinements of Vaught's normal from theorem.Victor Harnik - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (3):289-306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • How to compute antiderivatives.Chris Freiling - 1995 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1 (3):279-316.
    This isnotabout the symbolic manipulation of functions so popular these days. Rather it is about the more abstract, but infinitely less practical, problem of the primitive. Simply stated:Given a derivativef: ℝ → ℝ, how can we recover its primitive?The roots of this problem go back to the beginnings of calculus and it is even sometimes called “Newton's problem”. Historically, it has played a major role in the development of the theory of the integral. For example, it was Lebesgue's primary motivation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A quantitative analysis of modal logic.Ronald Fagin - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (1):209-252.
    We do a quantitative analysis of modal logic. For example, for each Kripke structure M, we study the least ordinal μ such that for each state of M, the beliefs of up to level μ characterize the agents' beliefs (that is, there is only one way to extend these beliefs to higher levels). As another example, we show the equivalence of three conditions, that on the face of it look quite different, for what it means to say that the agents' (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Necessities and Necessary Truths: A Prolegomenon to the Use of Modal Logic in the Analysis of Intensional Notions.V. Halbach & P. Welch - 2009 - Mind 118 (469):71-100.
    In philosophical logic necessity is usually conceived as a sentential operator rather than as a predicate. An intensional sentential operator does not allow one to express quantified statements such as 'There are necessary a posteriori propositions' or 'All laws of physics are necessary' in first-order logic in a straightforward way, while they are readily formalized if necessity is formalized by a predicate. Replacing the operator conception of necessity by the predicate conception, however, causes various problems and forces one to reject (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Revision Without Revision Sequences: Circular Definitions.Edoardo Rivello - 2019 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 48 (1):57-85.
    The classical theory of definitions bans so-called circular definitions, namely, definitions of a unary predicate P, based on stipulations of the form $$Px =_{\mathsf {Df}} \phi,$$where ϕ is a formula of a fixed first-order language and the definiendumP occurs into the definiensϕ. In their seminal book The Revision Theory of Truth, Gupta and Belnap claim that “General theories of definitions are possible within which circular definitions [...] make logical and semantic sense” [p. IX]. In order to sustain their claim, they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Classifying the computational complexity of problems.Larry Stockmeyer - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (1):1-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Fixed point logics.Anuj Dawar & Yuri Gurevich - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (1):65-88.
    We consider fixed point logics, i.e., extensions of first order predicate logic with operators defining fixed points. A number of such operators, generalizing inductive definitions, have been studied in the context of finite model theory, including nondeterministic and alternating operators. We review results established in finite model theory, and also consider the expressive power of the resulting logics on infinite structures. In particular, we establish the relationship between inflationary and nondeterministic fixed point logics and second order logic, and we consider (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On Moschovakis closure ordinals.Jon Barwise - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (2):292-296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Supervaluation fixed-point logics of truth.Philip Kremer & Alasdair Urquhart - 2008 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 37 (5):407-440.
    Michael Kremer defines fixed-point logics of truth based on Saul Kripke’s fixed point semantics for languages expressing their own truth concepts. Kremer axiomatizes the strong Kleene fixed-point logic of truth and the weak Kleene fixed-point logic of truth, but leaves the axiomatizability question open for the supervaluation fixed-point logic of truth and its variants. We show that the principal supervaluation fixed point logic of truth, when thought of as consequence relation, is highly complex: it is not even analytic. We also (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Invisible Ordinals and Inductive Definitions.Evangelos Kranakis - 1982 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 28 (8‐12):137-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ultimate truth vis- à- vis stable truth.P. D. Welch - 2008 - Review of Symbolic Logic 1 (1):126-142.
    We show that the set of ultimately true sentences in Hartry Field's Revenge-immune solution model to the semantic paradoxes is recursively isomorphic to the set of stably true sentences obtained in Hans Herzberger's revision sequence starting from the null hypothesis. We further remark that this shows that a substantial subsystem of second-order number theory is needed to establish the semantic values of sentences in Field's relative consistency proof of his theory over the ground model of the standard natural numbers: -CA0 (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Some restrictions on simple fixed points of the integers.G. L. McColm - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (4):1324-1345.
    A function is recursive (in given operations) if its values are computed explicitly and uniformly in terms of other "previously computed" values of itself and (perhaps) other "simultaneously computed" recursive functions. Here, "explicitly" includes definition by cases. We investigate those recursive functions on the structure $\mathbf{N} = \langle \omega, 0, \operatorname{succ,pred}\rangle$ that are computed in terms of themselves only, without other simultaneously computed recursive functions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • First Order Theories for Nonmonotone Inductive Definitions: Recursively Inaccessible and Mahlo.Gerhard Jäger - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):1073-1089.
    In this paper first order theories for nonmonotone inductive definitions are introduced, and a proof-theoretic analysis for such theories based on combined operator forms a la Richter with recursively inaccessible and Mahlo closure ordinals is given.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (1 other version)Notes on Formal Theories of Truth.Andrea Cantini - 1989 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 35 (2):97-130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Global inductive definability.Jon Barwise & Yiannis N. Moschovakis - 1978 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 43 (3):521-534.
    We show that several theorems on ordinal bounds in different parts of logic are simple consequences of a basic result in the theory of global inductive definitions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Fixed-point extensions of first-order logic.Yuri Gurevich & Saharon Shelah - 1986 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 32:265-280.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Barwise: Infinitary logic and admissible sets.H. Jerome Keisler & Julia F. Knight - 2004 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 10 (1):4-36.
    §0. Introduction. In [16], Barwise described his graduate study at Stanford. He told of his interactions with Kreisel and Scott, and said how he chose Feferman as his advisor. He began working on admissible fragments of infinitary logic after reading and giving seminar talks on two Ph.D. theses which had recently been completed: that of Lopez-Escobar, at Berkeley, on infinitary logic [46], and that of Platek [58], at Stanford, on admissible sets.Barwise's work on infinitary logic and admissible sets is described (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Infinitary tableau for semantic truth.Toby Meadows - 2015 - Review of Symbolic Logic 8 (2):207-235.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • ŁΠ logic with fixed points.Luca Spada - 2008 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 47 (7-8):741-763.
    We study a system, μŁΠ, obtained by an expansion of ŁΠ logic with fixed points connectives. The first main result of the paper is that μŁΠ is standard complete, i.e., complete with regard to the unit interval of real numbers endowed with a suitable structure. We also prove that the class of algebras which forms algebraic semantics for this logic is generated, as a variety, by its linearly ordered members and that they are precisely the interval algebras of real closed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations