Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Lived religion: rethinking human nature in a neoliberal age.Beverley Clack - 2018 - International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 79 (4):355-369.
    This article considers the relationship between philosophy of religion and an approach to the study of religion, which prioritises the experience of lived religion. Considering how individuals and communities live out their faith challenges some of the assumptions of analytic philosophers of religion regarding the position the philosopher should adopt when approaching the investigation of religion. If philosophy is understood principally as a means for analysing belief, it will have little space for an engagement with what it feels like to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Emotion, Cognition and Action.David Charles - 2004 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 55:105-136.
    Contemporary philosophers have not, at least until very recently, been much concerned with the study of the emotions. It was not always so. The Stoics thought deeply about this topic. Although they were divided on points of detail, they agreed on the broad outline of an account. In itemotions are valuational judgments and resulting affective states.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Commentary on Sherman.Maud H. Chaplin - 2000 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 16 (1):82-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Envy and resentment.Marguerite La Caze - 2001 - Philosophical Explorations 4 (1):31-45.
    Envy and resentment are generally thought to be unpleasant and unethical emotions which ought to be condemned. I argue that both envy and resentment, in some important forms, are moral emotions connected with concern for justice, understood in terms of desert and entitlement. They enable us to recognise injustice, work as a spur to acting against it and connect us to others. Thus, we should accept these emotions as part of the ethical life.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Death, Betrayal, and a Guardian Angel.Justin A. Capes - 2017 - Philosophical Papers 46 (2):191-210.
    A familiar Epicurean argument for the conclusion that death is not bad for those who die goes like this. The dead cannot experience anything, including being dead and its effects. But something is bad for an individual only if that person can experience it or its effects. Therefore, death is not bad for those who die. In this article, I consider several alleged counterexamples to this argument's second premise, along with some responses to them. The responses are not entirely without (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can an ancient Greek sceptic be eudaimôn (or happy)? And what difference does the answer make to us?Richard Bett - 2012 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 6 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Practical Wisdom, Justice and Human Dignity: Some Comments on the Consensus Statement of the Working Group on Roman Catholic Approaches to Determining Appropriate Critical Care.Gerhold K. Becker - 2001 - Christian Bioethics 7 (2):265-270.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Human Flourishing and Universal Justice.Thomas W. Pogge - 1999 - Social Philosophy and Policy 16 (1):333-361.
    The question of what constitutes human flourishing elicits an extraordinary variety of responses, which suggests that there are not merely differences of opinion at work, but also different understandings of the question itself. So it may help to introduce some clarity into the question before starting work on one answer to it.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The fragility of care.Guy A. M. Widdershoven & Marli Huijer - 2001 - Bijdragen 62 (3):304-316.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Manifesto of the Epicurean Philosophy of Life.Marian Andrzej Wesoły - 2019 - Peitho 10 (1):85-102.
    Epicurus’ philosophy grew out of his life experiences, contacts, polem­ics, journeys and other activities. Apart from such great works as the monumental On nature in 37 books, Epicurus authored also various extracts, principle doctrines, sayings and letters. The letters, while addressed to many students and friends, were for him a very important tool of propagating his own philosophy. Epicurus’ fascinating Letter to Menoeceus can be regarded as a manifesto of his philosophy of life. In historiography, it is often characterized as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Essays in Moral Scepticism, by Richard Joyce. [REVIEW]Kenneth Walden - 2019 - Mind 128 (511):935-944.
    Essays in Moral Scepticism, by JoyceRichard. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016. Pp. xi + 288.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evidence and the end of medicine.Keld Thorgaard & Uffe Juul Jensen - 2011 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 14 (3):273-280.
    Fifty years ago, in 1961, Feinstein published his first path-breaking articles leading to his seminal work Clinical Judgement and to the establishment of clinical epidemiology. Feinstein had an Aristotelian approach to scientific method: methods must be adapted to the material examined. Feinstein died 10 years ago and few years before his death he concluded that efforts to promote a person-oriented medicine had failed. He criticised medicine for not having recognized that only persons can suitably observe, evaluate and rate their own (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In what sense are emotions evaluations?Fabrice Teroni & Julien A. Deonna - 2014 - In Sabine Roeser & Cain Samuel Todd (eds.), Emotion and Value. Oxford University Press UK. pp. 15-31.
    In this chapter, we first introduce the idea that emotions are evaluations. Next, we explore two approaches attempting to account for this idea in terms of attitudes that are alleged to become emotional when taking evaluative contents. According to the first approach, emotions are evaluative judgments. According to the second, emotions are perceptual experiences of evaluative properties. We explain why this theory remains unsatisfactory insofar as it shares with the evaluative judgement theory the idea that emotions are evaluations in virtue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The therapy of desire in early Confucianism: Xunzi.T. C. Kline - 2006 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 5 (2):235-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Philosophy's Folds: Seneca, Cavarero, and the History of Rectitude.Victoria Rimell - 2017 - Hypatia 32 (4):768-783.
    This paper takes as its stimulus Adriana Cavarero’s recent investigation of the postures of rectitude and inclination in the Western philosophical tradition. To showcase how this book might catalyse productive interactions between feminist critics in different areas of the humanities, I will bring Cavarero into dialogue with a thinker she mentions in passing who extensively develops ‘rectitude as a general principle’ : Seneca. I argue that a gendered ontology of rectitude is increasingly put under pressure and transformed in Seneca’s Letters, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Anger and moral judgment.Glen Pettigrove - 2014 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 92 (2):269-286.
    Although theorists disagree about precisely how to characterize the link between anger and moral judgment, that they are linked is routinely taken for granted in contemporary metaethics and philosophy of emotion. One problem with this assumption is that it ignores virtues like patience, which thinkers as different as Cassian, Śāntideva, and Maimonides have argued are characteristic of mature moral agents. The patient neither experience nor plan to experience anger in response to (at least some) wrongs. Nevertheless, we argue, they remain (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Strengthening “Giving Voice to Values” in Business Schools by Reconsidering the “Invisible Hand” Metaphor.Mollie Painter-Morland & Rosa Slegers - 2018 - Journal of Business Ethics 147 (4):807-819.
    The main contention of this paper is that our ability to embed a consideration of values into business school curricula is hampered by certain normative parameters that our students have when entering the classroom. If we don’t understand the processes of valuation that underpin our students’ reasoning, our ethics teaching will inevitably miss its mark. In this paper, we analyze one of the most prevalent metaphors that underpin moral arguments about business, and reveal the beliefs and assumptions that underpin it. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Epicurean Justice.John Armstrong - 1997 - Phronesis 42 (3):324-334.
    Epicurus is one of the first social contract theorists, holding that justice is an agreement neither to harm nor be harmed. He also says that living justly is necessary and sufficient for living pleasantly, which is the Epicurean goal. Some say that there are two accounts of justice in Epicurus -- one as a personal virtue, the other as a virtue of institutions. I argue that the personal virtue derives from compliance with just social institutions, and so we need to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Authoring experience: the significance and performance of storytelling in Socratic dialogue with rehabilitating cancer patients.Jeanette Bresson Ladegaard Knox & Mette Nordahl Svendsen - 2015 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 18 (3):409-420.
    This article examines the storytelling aspect in philosophizing with rehabilitating cancer patients in small Socratic dialogue groups. Recounting an experience to illustrate a philosophical question chosen by the participants is the traditional point of departure for the dialogical exchange. However, narrating is much more than a beginning point or the skeletal framework of events and it deserves more scholarly attention than hitherto given. Storytelling pervades the whole Socratic process and impacts the conceptual analysis in a SDG. In this article we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Lucretius, Symmetry arguments, and fearing death.James Warren - 2001 - Phronesis 46 (4):466-491.
    This paper identifies two possible versions of the Epicurean 'Symmetry argument', both of which claim that post mortem non-existence is relevantly like prenatal non-existence and that therefore our attitude to the former should be the same as that towards the latter. One version addresses the fear of the state of being dead by making it equivalent to the state of not yet being born; the other addresses the prospective fear of dying by relating it to our present retrospective attitude to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Emerson and the “Pale Scholar”.Reza Hosseini - 2018 - Dialogue 57 (1):115-135.
    Le problème de l’inaction des intellectuels est un thème récurrent dans les écrits de Ralph Waldo Emerson. Les commentateurs ont accordé beaucoup d’attention à «l’intellectuel américain», mais moins à ses remarques concernant l’«intellectuel pâle». Dans cet article, je me concentre sur ce dernier point, en montrant qu’une compréhension de la manière dont évoluent les idées d’Emerson sur ce qui compte pour l’action permettrait non seulement d’approfondir notre compréhension de sa philosophie ainsi que son orientation vers la conduite de la vie, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Agency, Scarcity, and Mortality.Luca Ferrero - 2015 - The Journal of Ethics 19 (3-4):349-378.
    It is often argued, most recently by Samuel Scheffler, that we should reconcile with our mortality as constitutive of our existence: as essential to its temporal structure, to the nature of deliberation, and to our basic motivations and values. Against this reconciliatory strategy, I argue that there is a kind of immortal existence that is coherently conceivable and potentially desirable. First, I argue against the claim that our existence has a temporal structure with a trajectory that necessarily culminates in an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Heidegger: Being and Time and the Care for the Self.Jesús Adrián Escudero - 2013 - Open Journal of Philosophy 3 (2):302-307.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Glück Und Ethik.Joachim Schummer - 1998 - Königshausen & Neumann.
    Alle Menschen streben nach Glück. Es dürfte schwierig sein, einen Philosophen zu benennen, der diesen Satz jemals ernsthaft bestritten hat. Auf der Basis eines solchen, fast einzigartigen und mehr als zweitausend Jahre haltenden philosophischen Konsenses, so möchte man meinen, konnte eine konstruktive Philosophie des Glücks gedeihen, die sich in der Ausgestaltung der Begriffe des Glücks und des Strebens differenzierte; eine Philosophie, die Antworten gibt auf die Fragen, ob bzw. auf welche Weise wir das jeweils erstrebte Glück erreichen können, und die (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Health as human nature and critique of culture in Nietzsche and Zhuang zi.Danesh Singh - 2015 - Comparative Philosophy 6 (1):91-110.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hellenistic Philosophy in Greek and Roman Times.Ioanna-Soultana Kotsori - 2019 - Open Journal for Studies in Philosophy 3 (1):1-6.
    The new Hellenistic philosophies that emerged in Athens at the end of the 4th century BC – mainly Stoicism and Epicureanism – were largely non-original and second choice, compared to Plato and Aristotle. Unlike what happened with the works of Plato and Aristotle, the works of early Hellenistic era were lost on a large scale. However, they became the dominant philosophies of the next five centuries, and were extended from Greece to Rome and the distant provinces of the Roman Empire. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Algunas consideraciones sobre el carácter terapéutico de la filosofía en Wittgenstein Y Heidegger.Vicente García-Huidobro Andrews - 2013 - Universitas Philosophica 30 (60):139-160.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Arguing from Reception History for the Viability of Rational Reconstruction: A Case Study Involving The Reception of Cartesian Ethics in an Anglophone Context From 1650.Frits Gåvertsson - unknown
    I argue that Lisa Shapiro’s rational reconstruction of Descartes’s provisional moral code in terms of a broad conception of morality supplies us with an interpretative framework that make historiographical sense of the reception of Descartes’s moral philosophy in an Anglophone context on three occasions: the appeal to Descartes made by Henry More, Henry Sidgwick’s abrupt dismissal, and the ensuing reaction to Sidgwick found in Grace Neal Dolson. This case shows, I maintain, how reception history can be utilized to inform and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark