Switch to: References

Citations of:

Natural deduction: a proof-theoretical study

Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications (1965)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A Note on the Relation Between Formal and Informal Proof.Jörgen Sjögren - 2010 - Acta Analytica 25 (4):447-458.
    Using Carnap’s concept explication, we propose a theory of concept formation in mathematics. This theory is then applied to the problem of how to understand the relation between the concepts formal proof and informal, mathematical proof.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Normalization proof for Peano Arithmetic.Annika Siders - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (7-8):921-940.
    A proof of normalization for a classical system of Peano Arithmetic formulated in natural deduction is given. The classical rule of the system is the rule for indirect proof restricted to atomic formulas. This rule does not, due to the restriction, interfere with the standard detour conversions. The convertible detours, numerical inductions and instances of indirect proof concluding falsity are reduced in a way that decreases a vector assigned to the derivation. By interpreting the expressions of the vectors as ordinals (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the explanatory power of truth in logic.Gila Sher - 2018 - Philosophical Issues 28 (1):348-373.
    Philosophers are divided on whether the proof- or truth-theoretic approach to logic is more fruitful. The paper demonstrates the considerable explanatory power of a truth-based approach to logic by showing that and how it can provide (i) an explanatory characterization —both semantic and proof-theoretical—of logical inference, (ii) an explanatory criterion for logical constants and operators, (iii) an explanatory account of logic’s role (function) in knowledge, as well as explanations of (iv) the characteristic features of logic —formality, strong modal force, generality, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Truth-values as labels: a general recipe for labelled deduction.Cristina Sernadas, Luca Viganò, João Rasga & Amílcar Sernadas - 2003 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 13 (3):277-315.
    We introduce a general recipe for presenting non-classical logics in a modular and uniform way as labelled deduction systems. Our recipe is based on a labelling mechanism where labels are general entities that are present, in one way or another, in all logics, namely truth-values. More specifically, the main idea underlying our approach is the use of algebras of truth-values, whose operators reflect the semantics we have in mind, as the labelling algebras of our labelled deduction systems. The “truth-values as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • ML systems: A proof theory for contexts. [REVIEW]Luciano Serafini & Fausto Giunchiglia - 2002 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 11 (4):471-518.
    In the last decade the concept of context has been extensivelyexploited in many research areas, e.g., distributed artificialintelligence, multi agent systems, distributed databases, informationintegration, cognitive science, and epistemology. Three alternative approaches to the formalization of the notion ofcontext have been proposed: Giunchiglia and Serafini's Multi LanguageSystems (ML systems), McCarthy's modal logics of contexts, andGabbay's Labelled Deductive Systems.Previous papers have argued in favor of ML systems with respect to theother approaches. Our aim in this paper is to support these arguments froma (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Normalization and excluded middle. I.Jonathan P. Seldin - 1989 - Studia Logica 48 (2):193 - 217.
    The usual rule used to obtain natural deduction formulations of classical logic from intuitionistic logic, namely.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Arbitrary truth-value functions and natural deduction.Krister Segerberg - 1983 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 29 (11):557-564.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Hyperdoctrines, Natural Deduction and the Beck Condition.Robert A. G. Seely - 1983 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 29 (10):505-542.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Validity Concepts in Proof-theoretic Semantics.Peter Schroeder-Heister - 2006 - Synthese 148 (3):525-571.
    The standard approach to what I call “proof-theoretic semantics”, which is mainly due to Dummett and Prawitz, attempts to give a semantics of proofs by defining what counts as a valid proof. After a discussion of the general aims of proof-theoretic semantics, this paper investigates in detail various notions of proof-theoretic validity and offers certain improvements of the definitions given by Prawitz. Particular emphasis is placed on the relationship between semantic validity concepts and validity concepts used in normalization theory. It (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • The completeness of intuitionistic logic with respect to a validity concept based on an inversion principle.Peter Schroeder-Heister - 1983 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 12 (3):359 - 377.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The categorical and the hypothetical: a critique of some fundamental assumptions of standard semantics.Peter Schroeder-Heister - 2012 - Synthese 187 (3):925-942.
    The hypothetical notion of consequence is normally understood as the transmission of a categorical notion from premisses to conclusion. In model-theoretic semantics this categorical notion is 'truth', in standard proof-theoretic semantics it is 'canonical provability'. Three underlying dogmas, (I) the priority of the categorical over the hypothetical, (II) the transmission view of consequence, and (III) the identification of consequence and correctness of inference are criticized from an alternative view of proof-theoretic semantics. It is argued that consequence is a basic semantical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Proof-Theoretic Semantics, Self-Contradiction, and the Format of Deductive Reasoning.Peter Schroeder-Heister - 2012 - Topoi 31 (1):77-85.
    From the point of view of proof-theoretic semantics, it is argued that the sequent calculus with introduction rules on the assertion and on the assumption side represents deductive reasoning more appropriately than natural deduction. In taking consequence to be conceptually prior to truth, it can cope with non-well-founded phenomena such as contradictory reasoning. The fact that, in its typed variant, the sequent calculus has an explicit and separable substitution schema in form of the cut rule, is seen as a crucial (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Proof-Theoretic Semantics: An Autobiographical Survey.Peter Schroeder-Heister - 2024 - In Thomas Piecha & Kai F. Wehmeier (eds.), Peter Schroeder-Heister on Proof-Theoretic Semantics. Springer. pp. 1-51.
    In this autobiographical sketch, which is followed by a bibliography of my writings, I try to relate my intellectual development to problems, ideas and results in proof-theoretic semantics on which I have worked and to which I have contributed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the syntax of logic and set theory.Lucius T. Schoenbaum - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (4):568-599.
    We introduce an extension of the propositional calculus to include abstracts of predicates and quantifiers, employing a single rule along with a novel comprehension schema and a principle of extensionality, which are substituted for the Bernays postulates for quantifiers and the comprehension schemata of ZF and other set theories. We prove that it is consistent in any finite Boolean subset lattice. We investigate the antinomies of Russell, Cantor, Burali-Forti, and others, and discuss the relationship of the system to other set-theoretic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Implications-as-Rules vs. Implications-as-Links: An Alternative Implication-Left Schema for the Sequent Calculus. [REVIEW]Peter Schroeder-Heister - 2011 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 40 (1):95 - 101.
    The interpretation of implications as rules motivates a different left-introduction schema for implication in the sequent calculus, which is conceptually more basic than the implication-left schema proposed by Gentzen. Corresponding to results obtained for systems with higher-level rules, it enjoys the subformula property and cut elimination in a weak form.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • How to Ekman a Crabbé-Tennant.Peter Schroeder-Heister & Luca Tranchini - 2018 - Synthese 199 (Suppl 3):617-639.
    Developing early results of Prawitz, Tennant proposed a criterion for an expression to count as a paradox in the framework of Gentzen’s natural deduction: paradoxical expressions give rise to non-normalizing derivations. Two distinct kinds of cases, going back to Crabbé and Tennant, show that the criterion overgenerates, that is, there are derivations which are intuitively non-paradoxical but which fail to normalize. Tennant’s proposed solution consists in reformulating natural deduction elimination rules in general form. Developing intuitions of Ekman we show that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Comments on the Contributions.Peter Schroeder-Heister - 2024 - In Thomas Piecha & Kai F. Wehmeier (eds.), Peter Schroeder-Heister on Proof-Theoretic Semantics. Springer. pp. 443-455.
    The contributions to this volume represent a broad range of aspects of proof-theoretic semantics. Some do so in the narrower, and some in the wider sense of the term. Some deal with issues I have been concerned with directly, and some tackle further problems. All of them open interesting new perspectives and develop the field in different directions. I will briefly comment on the significance of each contribution here.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Inversion by definitional reflection and the admissibility of logical rules.Wagner Campos Sanz & Thomas Piecha - 2009 - Review of Symbolic Logic 2 (3):550-569.
    The inversion principle for logical rules expresses a relationship between introduction and elimination rules for logical constants. Hallnäs & Schroeder-Heister proposed the principle of definitional reflection, which embodies basic ideas of inversion in the more general context of clausal definitions. For the context of admissibility statements, this has been further elaborated by Schroeder-Heister . Using the framework of definitional reflection and its admissibility interpretation, we show that, in the sequent calculus of minimal propositional logic, the left introduction rules are admissible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Inversion by definitional reflection and the admissibility of logical rules: Inversion by definitional reflection.Wagner De Campos Sanz - 2009 - Review of Symbolic Logic 2 (3):550-569.
    The inversion principle for logical rules expresses a relationship between introduction and elimination rules for logical constants. Hallnäs & Schroeder-Heister proposed the principle of definitional reflection, which embodies basic ideas of inversion in the more general context of clausal definitions. For the context of admissibility statements, this has been further elaborated by Schroeder-Heister. Using the framework of definitional reflection and its admissibility interpretation, we show that, in the sequent calculus of minimal propositional logic, the left introduction rules are admissible when (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Classical logic without bivalence.Tor Sandqvist - 2009 - Analysis 69 (2):211-218.
    Semantic justifications of the classical rules of logical inference typically make use of a notion of bivalent truth, understood as a property guaranteed to attach to a sentence or its negation regardless of the prospects for speakers to determine it as so doing. For want of a convincing alternative account of classical logic, some philosophers suspicious of such recognition-transcending bivalence have seen no choice but to declare classical deduction unwarranted and settle for a weaker system; intuitionistic logic in particular, buttressed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Semantic theory and necessary truth.Ian Rumfitt - 2001 - Synthese 126 (1-2):283 - 324.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Constantes lógicas y la armonía de las reglas de inferencia.Mariela Rubin - 2017 - Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso 9:103-119.
    All through the literatura, the question about what is a logical constant has recieved many answers, from model-theoretic aproaches,, to answers that focus in the inferential practice as meaning,,. Detractors of the second tradition presented many ineludible incovenients, in particular, the logical constant named ‘tonk’. Inferentialist tryed many solutions, in particular they presented the concept of ‘harmony’. The goal of this paper is to show that the different criteria of ‘harmony’ used in the proof-theoretic semantics to determine what is and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Somehow Things Do Not Relate: On the Interpretation of Polyadic Second-Order Logic.Marcus Rossberg - 2015 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 44 (3):341-350.
    Boolos has suggested a plural interpretation of second-order logic for two purposes: to escape Quine’s allegation that second-order logic is set theory in disguise, and to avoid the paradoxes arising if the second-order variables are given a set-theoretic interpretation in second-order set theory. Since the plural interpretation accounts only for monadic second-order logic, Rayo and Yablo suggest an new interpretation for polyadic second-order logic in a Boolosian spirit. The present paper argues that Rayo and Yablo’s interpretation does not achieve the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Paradoxicality in Kripke’s theory of truth.Lucas Rosenblatt & Camila Gallovich - 2022 - Synthese 200 (2):1-23.
    A lot has been written on solutions to the semantic paradoxes, but very little on the topic of general theories of paradoxicality. The reason for this, we believe, is that it is not easy to disentangle a solution to the paradoxes from a specific conception of what those paradoxes consist in. This paper goes some way towards remedying this situation. We first address the question of what one should expect from an account of paradoxicality. We then present one conception of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Natural deduction and Curry's paradox.Susan Rogerson - 2007 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 36 (2):155 - 179.
    Curry's paradox, sometimes described as a general version of the better known Russell's paradox, has intrigued logicians for some time. This paper examines the paradox in a natural deduction setting and critically examines some proposed restrictions to the logic by Fitch and Prawitz. We then offer a tentative counterexample to a conjecture by Tennant proposing a criterion for what is to count as a genuine paradox.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Expressive Force of Some Fragments of Intuitionistic Propositional Logic with Regard to Kripke Frames.P. H. Rodenburg - 1991 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 37 (23‐24):357-362.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Expressive Force of Some Fragments of Intuitionistic Propositional Logic with Regard to Kripke Frames.P. H. Rodenburg - 1991 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 37 (23-24):357-362.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Anything Goes.David Ripley - 2015 - Topoi 34 (1):25-36.
    This paper consider Prior's connective Tonk from a particular bilateralist perspective. I show that there is a natural perspective from which we can see Tonk and its ilk as perfectly well-defined pieces of vocabulary; there is no need for restrictions to bar things like Tonk.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Proofs and Models in Naive Property Theory: A Response to Hartry Field's ‘Properties, Propositions and Conditionals’.Greg Restall, Rohan French & Shawn Standefer - 2020 - Australasian Philosophical Review 4 (2):162-177.
    ABSTRACT In our response Field's ‘Properties, Propositions and Conditionals’, we explore the methodology of Field's program. We begin by contrasting it with a proof-theoretic approach and then commenting on some of the particular choices made in the development of Field's theory. Then, we look at issues of property identity in connection with different notions of equivalence. We close with some comments relating our discussion to Field's response to Restall’s [2010] ‘What Are We to Accept, and What Are We to Reject, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sheffer’s stroke: A study in proof-theoretic harmony.Stephen Read - 1999 - Danish Yearbook of Philosophy 34 (1):7-23.
    In order to explicate Gentzen’s famous remark that the introduction-rules for logical constants give their meaning, the elimination-rules being simply consequences of the meaning so given, we develop natural deduction rules for Sheffer’s stroke, alternative denial. The first system turns out to lack Double Negation. Strengthening the introduction-rules by allowing the introduction of Sheffer’s stroke into a disjunctive context produces a complete system of classical logic, one which preserves the harmony between the rules which Gentzen wanted: all indirect proof reduces (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • General-Elimination Harmony and the Meaning of the Logical Constants.Stephen Read - 2010 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (5):557-576.
    Inferentialism claims that expressions are meaningful by virtue of rules governing their use. In particular, logical expressions are autonomous if given meaning by their introduction-rules, rules specifying the grounds for assertion of propositions containing them. If the elimination-rules do no more, and no less, than is justified by the introduction-rules, the rules satisfy what Prawitz, following Lorenzen, called an inversion principle. This connection between rules leads to a general form of elimination-rule, and when the rules have this form, they may (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Harmony and autonomy in classical logic.Stephen Read - 2000 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 29 (2):123-154.
    Michael Dummett and Dag Prawitz have argued that a constructivist theory of meaning depends on explicating the meaning of logical constants in terms of the theory of valid inference, imposing a constraint of harmony on acceptable connectives. They argue further that classical logic, in particular, classical negation, breaks these constraints, so that classical negation, if a cogent notion at all, has a meaning going beyond what can be exhibited in its inferential use. I argue that Dummett gives a mistaken elaboration (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • Inferences by Parallel Reasoning in Islamic Jurisprudence: Al-Shīrāzī’s Insights Into the Dialectical Constitution of Meaning and Knowledge.Shahid Rahman, Muhammad Iqbal & Youcef Soufi - 2019 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer Verlag.
    This monograph proposes a new way of studying the different forms of correlational inference, known in the Islamic jurisprudence as qiyās. According to the authors’ view, qiyās represents an innovative and sophisticated form of dialectical reasoning that not only provides new epistemological insights into legal argumentation in general but also furnishes a fine-grained pattern for parallel reasoning which can be deployed in a wide range of problem-solving contexts and does not seem to reduce to the standard forms of analogical reasoning (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Linking Game-Theoretical Approaches with Constructive Type Theory: Dialogical Strategies, Ctt Demonstrations and the Axiom of Choice.Shahid Rahman & Nicolas Clerbout - 2015 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
    We now move to the demonstration of the left-to-right direction of the equivalence result. Let us assume that there is a winning $$\mathbf {P}$$ P -strategy in the dialogical game for $$\varphi $$ φ.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Neo-Logicism and Its Logic.Panu Raatikainen - 2020 - History and Philosophy of Logic 41 (1):82-95.
    The rather unrestrained use of second-order logic in the neo-logicist program is critically examined. It is argued in some detail that it brings with it genuine set-theoretical existence assumptions and that the mathematical power that Hume’s Principle seems to provide, in the derivation of Frege’s Theorem, comes largely from the ‘logic’ assumed rather than from Hume’s Principle. It is shown that Hume’s Principle is in reality not stronger than the very weak Robinson Arithmetic Q. Consequently, only a few rudimentary facts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Discrete tense logic with infinitary inference rules and systematic frame constants: A Hilbert-style axiomatization. [REVIEW]Lennart Åqvist - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 25 (1):45 - 100.
    The paper deals with the problem of axiomatizing a system T1 of discrete tense logic, where one thinks of time as the set Z of all the integers together with the operations +1 ("immediate successor") and-1 ("immediate predecessor"). T1 is like the Segerberg-Sundholm system WI in working with so-called infinitary inference ruldes; on the other hand, it differs from W I with respect to (i) proof-theoretical setting, (ii) presence of past tense operators and a "now" operator, and, most importantly, with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A note on the proof theory the λII-calculus.David J. Pym - 1995 - Studia Logica 54 (2):199 - 230.
    The lambdaPi-calculus, a theory of first-order dependent function types in Curry-Howard-de Bruijn correspondence with a fragment of minimal first-order logic, is defined as a system of (linearized) natural deduction. In this paper, we present a Gentzen-style sequent calculus for the lambdaPi-calculus and prove the cut-elimination theorem. The cut-elimination result builds upon the existence of normal forms for the natural deduction system and can be considered to be analogous to a proof provided by Prawitz for first-order logic. The type-theoretic setting considered (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • To be and not to be: Dialectical tense logic.Graham Priest - 1982 - Studia Logica 41 (2-3):249 - 268.
    The paper concerns time, change and contradiction, and is in three parts. The first is an analysis of the problem of the instant of change. It is argued that some changes are such that at the instant of change the system is in both the prior and the posterior state. In particular there are some changes from p being true to p being true where a contradiction is realized. The second part of the paper specifies a formal logic which accommodates (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Validity of Inference and Argument.Dag Prawitz - 2024 - In Thomas Piecha & Kai F. Wehmeier (eds.), Peter Schroeder-Heister on Proof-Theoretic Semantics. Springer. pp. 135-160.
    It has been common in contemporary logic and philosophy of logic to identify the validity of an inference with its conclusion being a (logical) consequence of its premisses.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The epistemic significance of valid inference.Dag Prawitz - 2012 - Synthese 187 (3):887-898.
    The traditional picture of logic takes it for granted that "valid arguments have a fundamental epistemic significance", but neither model theory nor traditional proof theory dealing with formal system has been able to give an account of this significance. Since valid arguments as usually understood do not in general have any epistemic significance, the problem is to explain how and why we can nevertheless use them sometimes to acquire knowledge. It is suggested that we should distinguish between arguments and acts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Remarks on some approaches to the concept of logical consequence.Dag Prawitz - 1985 - Synthese 62 (2):153 - 171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • On the idea of a general proof theory.Dag Prawitz - 1974 - Synthese 27 (1-2):63 - 77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Completeness and Hauptsatz for second order logic.Dag Prawitz - 1967 - Theoria 33 (3):246-258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • What is a Proof?Reinhard Kahle - 2015 - Axiomathes 25 (1):79-91.
    In this programmatic paper we renew the well-known question “What is a proof?”. Starting from the challenge of the mathematical community by computer assisted theorem provers we discuss in the first part how the experiences from examinations of proofs can help to sharpen the question. In the second part we have a look to the new challenge given by “big proofs”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Conceptual (and Hence Mathematical) Explanation, Conceptual Grounding and Proof.Francesca Poggiolesi & Francesco Genco - 2021 - Erkenntnis:1-27.
    This paper studies the notions of conceptual grounding and conceptual explanation (which includes the notion of mathematical explanation), with an aim of clarifying the links between them. On the one hand, it analyses complex examples of these two notions that bring to the fore features that are easily overlooked otherwise. On the other hand, it provides a formal framework for modeling both conceptual grounding and conceptual explanation, based on the concept of proof. Inspiration and analogies are drawn with the recent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Compositionality and the Prospect of a Pluralistic Semantic Theory.Adam C. Podlaskowski - 2019 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 97 (2):325-339.
    A semantic theory is committed to semantic monism just in case every particular semantic property posited by the theory is a member of the same kind. The commitment to semantic monism appears to draw some support from the need to provide a compositional semantics, since taking a single kind of semantic property as key to a semantic theory affords a uniform pattern on the basis of which the meaning of any given sentence can be compositionally determined. This line of support (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Intensional Harmony as Isomorphism.Paolo Pistone & Luca Tranchini - 2024 - In Thomas Piecha & Kai F. Wehmeier (eds.), Peter Schroeder-Heister on Proof-Theoretic Semantics. Springer. pp. 315-337.
    In the present paper we discuss a recent suggestion of Schroeder-Heister concerning the possibility of defining an intensional notion of harmony using isomorphism in second-order propositional logic. The latter is not an absolute notion, but its definition is relative to the choice of criteria for identity of proofs. In the paper, it is argued that in order to attain a satisfactory account of harmony, one has to consider a notion of identity stronger than the usual one (based on β- and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • An ecumenical notion of entailment.Elaine Pimentel, Luiz Carlos Pereira & Valeria de Paiva - 2019 - Synthese 198 (S22):5391-5413.
    Much has been said about intuitionistic and classical logical systems since Gentzen’s seminal work. Recently, Prawitz and others have been discussing how to put together Gentzen’s systems for classical and intuitionistic logic in a single unified system. We call Prawitz’ proposal the Ecumenical System, following the terminology introduced by Pereira and Rodriguez. In this work we present an Ecumenical sequent calculus, as opposed to the original natural deduction version, and state some proof theoretical properties of the system. We reason that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Peter Schroeder-Heister on Proof-Theoretic Semantics.Thomas Piecha & Kai F. Wehmeier (eds.) - 2024 - Springer.
    This open access book is a superb collection of some fifteen chapters inspired by Schroeder-Heister's groundbreaking work, written by leading experts in the field, plus an extensive autobiography and comments on the various contributions by Schroeder-Heister himself. For several decades, Peter Schroeder-Heister has been a central figure in proof-theoretic semantics, a field of study situated at the interface of logic, theoretical computer science, natural-language semantics, and the philosophy of language. -/- The chapters of which this book is composed discuss the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The placeholder view of assumptions and the Curry–Howard correspondence.Ivo Pezlar - 2020 - Synthese (11):1-17.
    Proofs from assumptions are amongst the most fundamental reasoning techniques. Yet the precise nature of assumptions is still an open topic. One of the most prominent conceptions is the placeholder view of assumptions generally associated with natural deduction for intuitionistic propositional logic. It views assumptions essentially as holes in proofs, either to be filled with closed proofs of the corresponding propositions via substitution or withdrawn as a side effect of some rule, thus in effect making them an auxiliary notion subservient (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations