Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Premature closure of controversial issues concerning animal memory representations.William A. Roberts - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):384-385.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evidence for instrumental plasticity in the cardiovascular system is circumstantial.Larry E. Roberts - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):301-302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Doubts about the importance of language training and the abstract code.William A. Roberts - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):154-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Qualities and relations in folk theories of mind.Lance J. Rips - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):75-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Mysticism as a philosophy of artificial intelligence.Martin Ringle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):444-445.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The demands of mental travel: demand characteristics of mental imagery experiments.Charles L. Richman, David B. Mitchell & J. Steven Reznick - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):564-565.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How not to reduce a functional psychology.Robert C. Richardson - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (1):125-37.
    There is often substantial disparity between philosophical ideals and scientific practice. Philosophical reductionism is motivated by a drive for ontological austerity. The vehicle is conceptual parsimony: the fewer our conceptual primitives, the less are our ontological commitments. A general moral to be drawn from my “Functionalism and Reductionism” is that scientific reduction does not, and should not be expected to, facilitate conceptual economy; yet reduction it still is, and in the classical mold. Those who press for the irreducibility of a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Conscious and nonconscious imagery.Alan Richardson - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):563-564.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why presume analyses are on-line?Georges Rey - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):74-75.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Remembering Jerry Fodor and his work.Georges Rey - 2018 - Mind and Language 33 (4):321-341.
    This is a reminiscence and short biographical sketch of the late philosopher and cognitive scientist Jerry Fodor. It includes a summary of his main proposals about the mind: his “Language of Thought” hypothesis; his rejection of analyticity and conceptual role semantics; his “mad dog nativism”; his proposal of mental modules and—by contrast—his skepticism about a computational theory of central cognition; his anti‐reductionist, but still physicalist, views about psychology; and, lastly, his attacks on selectionism. I conclude with some discussion of his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Prospects for a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness.Antti Revonsuo - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):694-695.
    In this commentary, I point out some weaknesses in Gray's target article and, in the light of that discussion, I attempt to delineate the kinds of problem a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness faces on its way to a scientific understanding of subjective experience.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Evaluation of a model's test.Russell Revlin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):547-548.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognitive maps and the language of thought.Michael Rescorla - 2009 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60 (2):377-407.
    Fodor advocates a view of cognitive processes as computations defined over the language of thought (or Mentalese). Even among those who endorse Mentalese, considerable controversy surrounds its representational format. What semantically relevant structure should scientific psychology attribute to Mentalese symbols? Researchers commonly emphasize logical structure, akin to that displayed by predicate calculus sentences. To counteract this tendency, I discuss computational models of navigation drawn from probabilistic robotics. These models involve computations defined over cognitive maps, which have geometric rather than logical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • Response classes, operants, and rules in problem solving.Jan G. Rein - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):602-602.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychiatry and computers: An uneasy synthesis.William H. Reid & John F. Riedler - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):547-547.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is there more than one type of mental algorithm?Ronan G. Reilly - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):489-490.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ways and means.Adam V. Reed - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):488-489.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When is an image hallucinatory?Graham F. Reed - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):530-531.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Unitary consciousness requires distributed comparators and global mappings.George N. Reeke - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):693-694.
    Gray, like other recent authors, seeks a scientific approach to consciousness, but fails to provide a biologically convincing description, partly because he implicitly bases his model on a computationalist foundation that embeds the contents of thought in irreducible symbolic representations. When patterns of neural activity instantiating conscious thought are shorn of homuncular observers, it appears most likely that these patterns and the circuitry that compares them with memories and plans should be found distributed over large regions of neocortex.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Information pickup is the activity of perceiving.Edward S. Reed - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):397-398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Implicit learning and tacit knowledge.Arthur S. Reber - 1989 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 118 (3):219-235.
    I examine the phenomenon of implicit learning, the process by which knowledge about the rule-governed complexities of the stimulus environment is acquired independently of conscious attempts to do so. Our research with the two seemingly disparate experimental paradigms of synthetic grammar learning and probability learning, is reviewed and integrated with other approaches to the general problem of unconscious cognition. The conclusions reached are as follows: Implicit learning produces a tacit knowledge base that is abstract and representative of the structure of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   323 citations  
  • Reverberations of Hebbian thinking.Josef P. Rauschecker - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):642-643.
    Cortical reverberations may induce synaptic changes that underlie developmental plasticity as well as long-term memory. They may be especially important for the consolidation of synaptic changes. Reverberations in cortical networks should have particular significance during development, when large numbers of new representations are formed. This includes the formation of representations across different sensory modalities.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Questions raised by the reinforcement paradigm.Anatol Rapoport - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):601-602.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computers Are Syntax All the Way Down: Reply to Bozşahin.William J. Rapaport - 2019 - Minds and Machines 29 (2):227-237.
    A response to a recent critique by Cem Bozşahin of the theory of syntactic semantics as it applies to Helen Keller, and some applications of the theory to the philosophy of computer science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Time optimality, proprioception, and the triphasic EMG pattern.Constance Ramos, Lawrence Stark & Blake Hannaford - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):231-232.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theories of mind: Some methodological/conceptual problems and an alternative approach.Sam S. Rakover - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):73-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How to decide whether a neural representation is a cognitive concept?Maartje E. J. Raijmakers & Peter C. M. Molenaar - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):641-642.
    A distinction should be made between the formation of stimulus-driven associations and cognitive concepts. To test the learning mode of a neural network, we propose a simple and classic input-output test: the discrimination shift task. Feed-forward PDP models appear to form stimulus-driven associations. A Hopfield network should be extended to apply the test.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theory-theory theory.Howard Rachlin - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):72-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The behaviorist reply.Howard Rachlin - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):444-444.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The elusive quale.Howard Rachlin - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):692-693.
    If sensations were behaviorally conceived, as they should be, as complex functional patterns of interaction between overt behavior and the environment, there would be no point in searching for them as instantaneous psychic elements within the brain or as internal products of the brain.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Minds, pains, and performance.Howard Rachlin - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):341-341.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is there such a thing as a problem situation?Kjell Raaheim - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):600-601.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The ‘causal power’ of machines.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):442-444.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • Imagery theory: not mysterious – just wrong.Zenon Pylyshyn - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):561-563.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Literature from cognitive psychology.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1982 - Artificial Intelligence 19 (3):251-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Psychological explanations and knowledge-dependent processes.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1981 - Cognition 10 (1-3):267-274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Local or transcortical assemblies? Some evidence from cognitive neuroscience.Friedemann Pulvermüller & Hubert Preissl - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):640-641.
    Amit defines cell assemblies aslocal cortical neuron populationswith strong internal connections. However, Hebb himself proposed that cell assemblies are distributed over different cortical areas (nonlocal ortranscortical assemblies). We review evidence from cognitive neuroscience and neuropsychology supporting the assumption that cell assemblies are transcortical.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The chess room: further demythologizing of strong AI.Roland Puccetti - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):441-442.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Animal-environment mutuality and direct perception.Sandra S. Prindle, Claudia Carello & M. T. Turvey - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):395-397.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The codes of man and beasts.David Premack - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):125-136.
    Exposing the chimpanzee to language training appears to enhance the animal's ability to perform some kinds of tasks but not others. The abilities that are enhanced involve abstract judgment, as in analogical reasoning, matching proportions of physically unlike exemplars, and completing incomplete representations of action. The abilities that do not improve concern the location of items in space and the inferences one might make in attempting to obtain them. Representing items in space and making inferences about them could be done (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   191 citations  
  • The abstract code as a translation device.David Premack - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):158-167.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Matching and mental-state ascription.Ian Pratt - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):71-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How wrong is Gibson?K. Prazdny - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):394-395.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intentionality: No mystery.William T. Powers - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):152-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Verbal hallucinations also occur in normals.Thomas B. Posey - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):530-530.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Feature-Specific Event-Related Potential Effects to Action- and Sound-Related Verbs during Visual Word Recognition.Margot Popp, Natalie M. Trumpp & Markus Kiefer - 2016 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • There is no need for (even fully fleshed out) mental models to map onto formal logic.Paul Pollard - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):363-364.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mental models, more or less.Thad A. Polk - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):362-363.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Rising out of the ashes.H. C. Plotkin - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (1):79-80.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The search of “canonical” explanations for the cerebral cortex.Alessio Plebe - 2018 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 40 (3):40.
    This paper addresses a fundamental line of research in neuroscience: the identification of a putative neural processing core of the cerebral cortex, often claimed to be “canonical”. This “canonical” core would be shared by the entire cortex, and would explain why it is so powerful and diversified in tasks and functions, yet so uniform in architecture. The purpose of this paper is to analyze the search for canonical explanations over the past 40 years, discussing the theoretical frameworks informing this research. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations