Switch to: References

Citations of:

Aristotle's Physics

Mind 45 (179):378-383 (1936)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Aristotle and supervenience.Victor Caston - 1993 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 31 (S1):107-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Aristotle and Supervenience.Victor Caston - 1993 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 31 (S1):107-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Embryology and Ackrill’s Problem.Nicola Carraro - 2017 - Phronesis 62 (3):274-304.
    Ackrill’s Problem is a tension between Aristotle’s alleged view that the matter of a living being is a body that is essentially ensouled, and his view that the matter of a substance preexists its generation. Most interpreters solve the tension by claiming that the subject of substantial generation is not the organic body of the living being, but its non-organic matter. I defend a different solution by showing that the embryological theory ofOn the Generation of Animalsimplies that the organic body (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • La version α du livre VII de la Physique d’Aristote et son rapport aux familles byzantines a et b.Mai-Lan Boureau - 2018 - Elenchos: Rivista di Studi Sul Pensiero Antico 39 (1):99-148.
    This paper focuses on the relation between version α of the seventh book of Aristotle’s Physics and the two byzantine families which shape the transmission lineage of most Aristotelian texts. To this end, it establishes a stemma codicum of all known manuscripts of version α. The first step reexamines Simplicius’ testimony in order to overcome the stemmatic problem arising from it: Simplicius’ statement that there was a version β for chapters 4 and 5 seems to be mere speculation on his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pseudo Justino y la recepción de la Física aristotélica en la antigüedad tardía.Marcelo D. Boeri - 1998 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 14 (1):9-30.
    Este artículo se concentra en la discusión crítica que Pseudo Justino dirigió hacia ciertos principios básicos de la filosofía de la naturaleza de Aristóteles. Pseudo Justino dirige su crítica a la doctrina aristotélica de la eternidad del movimiento, del tiempo y del mundo. También argumenta contra Aristóteles para mostrar la no-eternidad del éter, implicando una unificación de los reinos terrestre y celestial.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristóteles contra Parménides: El problema del cambio y la posibilidad de una ciencia física.Marcelo D. Boeri - 2006 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 30:45-68.
    Este ensayo se propone presentar una lectura de las críticas de Aristóteles a Parménides en la Física. El autor sugiere que algunas importantes cuestiones que Aristóteles tiene en cuenta cuando determina los principios básicos de la ciencia de la naturaleza surgen de esas críticas. Boeri argumenta que, a pesar del fuerte desacuerdo declarado por Aristóteles en Física I 2-3 respecto de las posiciones eleáticas en general y la posición de Parménides en particular, Aristóteles aprovecha su discusión con Parménides de un (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • John Dewey and Daoist thought.James Behuniak - 2019 - Albany: SUNY Press, State University of New York.
    In this expansive and highly original two-volume work, Jim Behuniak reformulates John Dewey's late-period "Cultural turn" and proposes that its next logical step is an "intra-Cultural philosophy" that goes beyond what is commonly known as "comparative philosophy." Each volume models itself on this new approach, arguing that early Chinese thought is poised to join forces with Dewey in meeting an urgent cultural need: namely, helping the Western tradition to correct its outdated Greek-medieval assumptions, especially where these result in pre-Darwinian inferences (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Time, Count and Soul in Aristotle. An Interpretation of Physica IV.14, 223a25-26.Sergio Javier Barrionuevo - 2017 - Agora 36 (1).
    El estudio del tiempo en Physica IV.10-14 presenta grandes dificultades, una de ellas es el vínculo entre tiempo y alma realizada en 223a21-28. Este pasaje fue discutido por varios especialistas modernos durante el siglo XX. Si bien no hay consenso unánime, la “interpretación realista” estuvo muy extendida durante el siglo pasado. En este trabajo me propongo discutir un pasaje de la premisa 223a25-26 en el argumento de Aristóteles respecto de este vínculo. En primer lugar, rechazo la “interpretación realista” según la (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • La distinción entre acto y movimiento en Metafísica IX 6.Trinidad Avaria Decombe - 2015 - Estudios de Filosofía (Universidad de Antioquia) 51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle’s Method of Understanding the First Principles of Natural Things in the Physics I.1.Melina G. Mouzala - 2012 - Peitho 3 (1):31-50.
    This paper presents Aristotle’s method of understanding the first principles of natural things in the Physics I.1 and analyzes the three stages of which this method consists. In the Physics I.1, Aristotle suggests that the natural proper route which one has to follow in order to find out the first principles of natural things is to proceed from what is clearer and more knowable to us to what is more knowable and clear by nature. In the Physics I.1, the terms (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Alexandre d'Aphrodise vs Jean Philopon: Notes sur quelques traités d'Alexandre “perdus” en grec, conservés en arabe.Ahmad Hasnawi - 1994 - Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 4 (1):53-109.
    Dans cet article, l'auteur fait état de nouvelles données à propos de trois traités attribués a Alexandre d'Aphrodise en arabe et dont on pensait qu'ils n'avaient pas de correspondant grec. II montre que le premier (D.8a) est une version adaptée – selon les normes du “cercle d'al-Kindi’ – deQuaestioI 21, à côte de la traduction plus tardive et plus exacte de cette mêmeQuaestiodue à Abù ‘Uṭmān al-Dimašqī (m. 900). II montre que les deux autres traités (D.9 et D.16), en revanche, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Aristotle’s solution for Parmenides’ inconclusive argument in Physics I.3.Lucas Angioni - 2021 - Peitho 12 (1):41-67.
    I discuss the argument Aristotle ascribes to Parmenides at Physics 186a23-32. I discuss (i) the reasons why Aristotle considers it as eristic and inconclusive and (i) the solution (lusis) Aristotle proposes against it.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Aristóteles e a necessidade do conhecimento científico.Lucas Angioni - 2020 - Discurso 50 (2):193-238.
    I discuss the exact meaning of the thesis according to which the object of scientific knowledge is necessary. The thesis is expressed by Aristotle in the Posterior Analytics, in his definition of scientific knowledge. The traditional interpretation understands this definition as depending on two parallel and independent requirements, the causality requirement and the necessity requirement. Against this interpretation, I try to show, through the examination of several passages that refer to the definition of scientific knowledge, that the necessity requirement specifies (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Pseudo-Plato on Names.Francesco Ademollo - 2017 - Phronesis 62 (3):255-273.
    The pseudo-Platonic Definitions seems to ascribe to ὄνοµα, ‘name’, the function of signifying two kinds of predicate. This is problematic, and I propose an emendation of the text, arguing that a definition of ῥῆµα, ‘verb’, has fallen out.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Poiesis del tiempo y del movimiento: Una nueva mirada a la ontología aristotélica.Diana María Acevedo Zapata - 2014 - Universitas Philosophica 31 (63).
    Having in mind the concept of poiesis, as Paul Valéry uses it, time and movement are presented as concepts produced within the project of understanding the natural world. From the idea of philosophy as a way of constructing through concepts the intelligibility of phenomena, I will show the coherence between the construction of the concept of time and that of the concept of movement.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle's Theory of Abstraction.Allan Bäck - 2014 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
    This book investigates Aristotle’s views on abstraction and explores how he uses it. In this work, the author follows Aristotle in focusing on the scientific detail first and then approaches the metaphysical claims, and so creates a reconstructed theory that explains many puzzles of Aristotle’s thought. Understanding the details of his theory of relations and abstraction further illuminates his theory of universals. Some of the features of Aristotle’s theory of abstraction developed in this book include: abstraction is a relation; perception (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Aristotle’s Considered View of the Path to Knowledge.James H. Lesher - 2012 - In Lesher James H. (ed.), El espíritu y la letra: un homenaje a Alfonso Gomez-Lobo. Ediciones Colihue. pp. 127-145.
    I argue that these inconsistencies in wording and practice reflect the existence of two distinct Aristotelian views of inquiry, one peculiar to the Posterior Analytics and the other put forward in the Physics and practiced in the Physics and in other treatises. Although the two views overlap to some degree (e.g. both regard a rudimentary understanding of the subject as an essential first stage), the view of the syllogism as the workhorse of scientific investigation and the related view of inquiry (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle on Non-substantial Particulars, Fundamentality, and Change.Keren Wilson Shatalov - forthcoming - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie.
    There is a debate about whether particular properties are for Aristotle non-recurrent and trope-like individuals or recurrent universals. I argue that Physics I.7 provides evidence that he took non-substantial particulars to be neither; they are instead non-recurrent modes. Physics I.7 also helps show why this matters. Particular properties must be individual modes in order for Aristotle to preserve three key philosophical commitments: that objects of ordinary experience are primary substances, that primary substances undergo genuine change, and that primary substances are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle's Physics II 1 and Cultivated Plants.Errol G. Katayama - 2018 - Science in Context 31 (4):405-419.
    ArgumentThe aim of this paper is two-fold: to offer an interpretation that preserves the natural reading ofPhysicsII 1 – that Aristotle is drawing a stark distinction between what is natural and what is artificial; and to show how there is logical room for atertium quid– a category for things that are products of both nature and art. This aim is attained by highlighting two important qualifications Aristotle makes about the products of art in relation to an innate internal principle of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ars Topica: The Classical Technique of Constructing Arguments From Aristotle to Cicero.Sara Rubinelli - 2009 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Justice as a virtue: An analysis of Aristotle’s virtue of justice.Huang Xianzhong - 2007 - Frontiers of Philosophy in China 2 (2):265-279.
    People currently regard justice as the main principle of institutions and society, while in ancient Greek people took it as the virtue of citizens. This article analyzes Aristotle’s virtue of justice in his method of virtue ethics, discussing the nature of virtue, how justice is the virtue of citizens, what kind of virtue the justice of citizens is, and the prospect of the virtue of justice against a background of institutional justice. Since virtue can be said to be a specific (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How can a line segment with extension be composed of extensionless points?Brian Reese, Michael Vazquez & Scott Weinstein - 2022 - Synthese 200 (2):1-28.
    We provide a new interpretation of Zeno’s Paradox of Measure that begins by giving a substantive account, drawn from Aristotle’s text, of the fact that points lack magnitude. The main elements of this account are (1) the Axiom of Archimedes which states that there are no infinitesimal magnitudes, and (2) the principle that all assignments of magnitude, or lack thereof, must be grounded in the magnitude of line segments, the primary objects to which the notion of linear magnitude applies. Armed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle on Efficient and Final Causes in Plato.Daniel Vázquez - 2022 - Elenchos: Rivista di Studi Sul Pensiero Antico 43 (1):29-54.
    In Metaphysics A 6, Aristotle claims that Plato only recognises formal and material causes. Yet, in various dialogues, Plato seems to use and distinguish efficient and final causes too. Consequently, Harold Cherniss accuses Aristotle of being an unfair, forgetful, or careless reader of Plato. Since then, scholars have tried to defend Aristotle’s exegetical skills. I offer textual evidence and arguments to show that their efforts still fall short of the desired goal. I argue, instead, that we can reject Cherniss’ assertation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Explicación causal y holismo de trasfondo en la filosofía natural de Aristóteles.Alejandro G. Vigo - 2010 - Kriterion: Journal of Philosophy 51 (122):587-615.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aristóteles y la infinitud extensiva del tiempo.Alejandro G. Vigo - 2006 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 30:171-205.
    Este ensayo se centra en un breve pero significativo pasaje de Física, IV 13, 222a28-b7, en el que Aristóteles provee dos argumentos a favor de la infinitud extensiva del tiempo. El primero, argumenta Vigo, presenta su infinitud extensiva como dependiente de la infinitud del movimiento. El segundo argumento, en cambio, procede inmanentemente a partir de la consideración de las propiedades que el ‘ahora’ posee como límite que da cuenta tanto de la posibilidad de la delimitación como de la continuidad del (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Heraclitus, Change and Objective Contradictions in Aristotle’s Metaphysics Γ.Celso Vieira - 2022 - Rhizomata 10 (2):183-214.
    In Metaphysics Γ, Aristotle argues against those who seem to accept contradictions. He distinguishes between the Sophists, who deny the principle of non-contradiction through arguments, and the Natural Philosophers, whose physical investigations lead to the acceptance of objective contradictions. Heraclitus’ name appears throughout the discussion. Usually, he is associated with the discussion against the Sophists. In this paper, I explore how the discussion with the Natural Philosophers may illuminate both the interpretation of Heraclitus by Aristotle and Heraclitus’ own worldview. To (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Negation and Temporal Ontology.Tero Tulenheimo - 2011 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (1):101-114.
    G. H. von Wright proposed that a temporal interval exemplifies a real contradiction if at least one part of any division of this interval involves the presence of contradictorily related (though non-simultaneous) states. In connection with intervals, two negations must be discerned: 'does not hold at an interval' and 'fails throughout an interval'. Von Wright did not distinguish the two. As a consequence, he made a mistake in indicating how to use his logical symbolism to express the notion of real (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aristotle and Linearity in Substance, Measure, and Motion.Paul Taborsky - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (6):1375-1399.
    The model of a closed linear measure space, which can be used to model Aristotle’s treatment of motion (kinesis), can be analogically extended to the qualitative ‘spaces’ implied by his theory of contraries in Physics I and in Metaphysics Iota, and to the dimensionless ‘space’ of the unity of matter and form discussed in book Eta of the Metaphysics. By examining Aristotle’s remarks on contraries, the subject of change, continuity, and the unity of matter and form, Aristotle’s thoughts on motion, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Christian ethics and the concept of creation.Pieter H. Stoker - 2006 - Philosophia Reformata 71 (2):132-144.
    The endeavour of science is to find unity in multitude, relatedness in diversity, continuity in discontinuity. By this way reality is simplified for scientific conception and description. With its reliance on observational data and logic, and with the scientific approach to understand the complexity, functionality, rationality and interrelationship of every aspect of reality, natural sciences do bring forward fascinating new insights on the concealed secrets in natural structures and processes. The crucial position of time in the laws of the universe (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A short notice on Robert Heinaman's account of Aristotle's definition of kinêsis in Physica III.Javier Echeñique Sosa - 2010 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 4 (2):1 - 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • La filosofía de las matemáticas de Aristóteles.Miguel Martí Sánchez - 2016 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 52:43-66.
    La filosofía de las matemáticas de Aristóteles es una investigación acerca de tres asuntos diferentes pero complementarios: el lugar epistemológico de las matemáticas en el organigrama de las ciencias teoréticas o especulativas; el estudio del método usado por el matemático para elaborar sus doctrinas, sobre todo la geometría y la aritmética; y la averiguación del estatuto ontológico de las entidades matemáticas. Para comprender lo peculiar de la doctrina aristotélica es necesario tener en cuenta que su principal interés está en poner (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • II—Christopher Shields: The Peculiar Motion of Aristotelian Souls.Christopher Shields - 2007 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1):139-161.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aristotle on action: The peculiar motion of aristotelian souls.Christopher Shields - 2007 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1):139–161.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • La formulación de los primeros principios en Física I 7 a la luz de la noción de generación.Claudia Marisa Seggiaro - 2021 - Estudios de Filosofía (Universidad de Antioquia) 63:25-46.
    En el presente trabajo nos interesa analizar cómo Aristóteles formula los principios de la física a partir de la noción de generación. Nuestra tesis es que Física I 7 es el “momento” de euporía que cierra un proceso que se inicia en 1-2 con la problematización acerca de la naturaleza y número de los principios. Para demostrar esto, dividiremos el trabajo en dos partes. En la primera intentaremos establecer por qué Aristóteles emprende esta investigación y cuál es el contexto argumentativo (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle Physics I 8.Sean Kelsey - 2006 - Phronesis 51 (4):330 - 361.
    Aristotle's thesis in "Physics" I 8 is that a certain old and familiar problem about coming to be can only be solved with the help of the new account of the "principles" he has developed in "Physics" I 7. This is a strong thesis and the literature on the chapter does not quite do it justice; specifically, as things now stand we are left wondering why Aristotle should have found this problem so compelling in the first place. In this paper (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • What about Plurality? Aristotle’s Discussion of Zeno’s Paradoxes.Barbara M. Sattler - 2021 - Peitho 12 (1):85-106.
    While Aristotle provides the crucial testimonies for the paradoxes of motion, topos, and the falling millet seed, surprisingly he shows almost no interest in the paradoxes of plurality. For Plato, by contrast, the plurality paradoxes seem to be the central paradoxes of Zeno and Simplicius is our primary source for those. This paper investigates why the plurality paradoxes are not examined by Aristotle and argues that a close look at the context in which Aristotle discusses Zeno holds the answer to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Zeno Beach.Jacob Rosen - 2020 - Phronesis 65 (4):467-500.
    On Zeno Beach there are infinitely many grains of sand, each half the size of the last. Supposing Aristotle denied the possibility of Zeno Beach, did he have a good argument for the denial? Three arguments, each of ancient origin, are examined: the beach would be infinitely large; the beach would be impossible to walk across; the beach would contain a part equal to the whole, whereas parts must be lesser. It is attempted to show that none of these arguments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • La defensa aristotélica del uso de explicaciones teleológicas en Física II 8.Alberto Ross - 2006 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 30:127-146.
    Este ensayo intenta ofrecer una reconstrucción de los argumentos de Aristóteles del uso de explicaciones teleológicas en Física II 8. En su exposición de los pasajes seleccionados Ross pone cierto énfasis en el carácter dialógico del discurso para hacer una modesta contribución a la solución de dos acertijos: uno de carácter exegético, y el otro sistemático. Esta lectura permite al autor introducir un nuevo elemento en la discusión concerniente a qué alcances y límites hay de las explicaciones teleológicas en la (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Principio de animismo distributivo.Vicente Llamas Roig - 2023 - Pensamiento 78 (301):1685-1706.
    Disquisiciones sobre la automotricidad equívoca y el contacto en la transmisión de la acción dinámica en la estela del comentario de Roberto Grosseteste al libro VII de la Physica de Aristóteles. El estudio testa un patrón de animismo integral distributivo, no partitivo, postulando la discontinuidad esencial de segunda especie en la concatenación de motores, vestigios de la embrionaria ciencia insular, atenta a la causalidad eficiente que inerva la matriz fenoménica en una apuesta por la ejemplaridad de la medida y el (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-movers and unmoved movers in Aristotle's Physics VII.Thomas M. Olshewsky - 1995 - Classical Quarterly 45 (02):389-.
    Robert Wardy's recent The Chain of Change has again brought to the fore the question of the role of Physics VII in the development of Aristotle's conception of motion. Wardy reads VII in conjunction with VIII, and argues that the former is the precursor of the latter in the development of the conception of a cosmic unmoved mover. He also claims that this account is the only one that can save us from a version of self-motion made unacceptable by Aristotle's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Self-movers and unmoved movers in Aristotle's Physics VII.Thomas M. Olshewsky - 1995 - Classical Quarterly 45 (2):389-406.
    Robert Wardy's recent The Chain of Change has again brought to the fore the question of the role of Physics VII in the development of Aristotle's conception of motion. Wardy reads VII in conjunction with VIII, and argues that the former is the precursor of the latter in the development of the conception of a cosmic unmoved mover. He also claims that this account is the only one that can save us from a version of self-motion made unacceptable by Aristotle's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle’s Uses of ἕνεκα.Takashi Oki - 2021 - Phronesis 67 (1):1-26.
    I argue that Aristotle’s arguments in passages regarding chance in the Physics and in passages about ignorance in action in the Nicomachean and Eudemian Ethics presuppose two different uses of ‘for the sake of something’, which are able to explain respectively the wish or thought of agents and the type or nature of what they actually do. In my view, however, this does not commit Aristotle, in the ‘ignorance’ passages from the two Ethics, to holding that the type or nature (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Subjects of Natural Generations in Aristotle’s Physics I.7.Scott O'Connor - 2015 - Apeiron 48 (1):45-75.
    In 'Physics' I.7, Aristotle claims that plants and animals are generated from sperma. Since most understood sperma to be an ovum, this claim threatens to undermine the standard view that, for Aristotle, the matter natural beings are generated from persists through their generation. By focusing on Aristotle’s discussion of sperma in the first book of the 'Generation of Animals', I show that, for Aristotle, sperma in the female is surplus blood collected in the uterus and not an ovum. I subsequently (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Eleatic Challenge in Aristotle’s Physics I.8.Scott O’Connor - 2017 - Rhizomata 5 (1):25-50.
    In Physics I.8, Aristotle outlines and responds to an Eleatic argument against the reality of change. I defend a new reading according to which the argu- ment assumes Predicational Monism, the claim that each being can possess only one property. In Phys. I.2, Aristotle responds to Predicational Monism, which he attributes to the Eleatics; I argue that he uses this response to distinguish coin- cidental from non-coincidental becoming, a distinction he employs in Phys I.8 to resolve the argument against the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Did Theophrastus Reject Aristotle’s Account of Place?Ben Morison - 2010 - Phronesis 55 (1):68-103.
    It is commonly held that Theophrastus criticized or rejected Aristotle's account of place. The evidence that scholars put forward for this view, from Simplicius' commentary on Aristotle's Physics, comes in two parts: (1) Simplicius reports some aporiai that Theophrastus found for Aristotle's account; (2) Simplicius cites a passage of Theophrastus which is said to 'bear witness' to the theory of place which Simplicius himself adopts (that of his teacher Damascius) — a theory which is utterly different from Aristotle's. But the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Two Traces of Two-Step Eudoxan Proportion Theory in Aristotle: a Tale of Definitions in Aristotle, with a Moral.Henry Mendell - 2007 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 61 (1):3-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Only Half the Truth. Proclus on Aristotle’s Deficient Metaphysics.Rareș Ilie Marinescu - 2023 - Phronesis 68 (4):438-466.
    In this paper I argue that Proclus’ criticism of the causality of Aristotle’s intellect is part of a general attack on Aristotle’s metaphysics. I show how Proclus criticises Aristotle for rejecting the One as a metaphysical principle and the metaphysical confusion that arises from this. Additionally, I claim that for Proclus Aristotle’s understanding of efficient causality differs from Plato’s and I discuss two of his arguments that Aristotle should have accepted the intellect as an efficient cause. As I show throughout, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Another note on Zeno's arrow.Ofra Magidor - 2008 - Phronesis 53 (4-5):359-372.
    In Physics VI.9 Aristotle addresses Zeno's four paradoxes of motion and amongst them the arrow paradox. In his brief remarks on the paradox, Aristotle suggests what he takes to be a solution to the paradox.In two famous papers, both called 'A note on Zeno's arrow', Gregory Vlastos and Jonathan Lear each suggest an interpretation of Aristotle's proposed solution to the arrow paradox. In this paper, I argue that these two interpretations are unsatisfactory, and suggest an alternative interpretation. In particular, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Colloquium 8.Arthur Madigan - 1992 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 8 (1):320-327.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle's definition of anagnorisis.John MacFarlane - 2000 - American Journal of Philology 121 (3):367-383.
    I argue for a new construal of Aristotle’s definition of anagnorisis (recognition) in Poetics 11. Virtually all translators and interpreters of the definition have understood the phrase ton pros eutuchian e dustuchian horismenon as a subjective genitive characterizing the persons involved in the recognition. I argue that it should instead be taken as a partitive genitive characterizing the genus of changes (metabolon) of which recognitions are a species. In addition to being preferable on philogical grounds, the construal I recommend helps (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations