Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Infinite time extensions of Kleene’s $${\mathcal{O}}$$.Ansten Mørch Klev - 2009 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 48 (7):691-703.
    Using infinite time Turing machines we define two successive extensions of Kleene’s ${\mathcal{O}}$ and characterize both their height and their complexity. Specifically, we first prove that the one extension—which we will call ${\mathcal{O}^{+}}$ —has height equal to the supremum of the writable ordinals, and that the other extension—which we will call ${\mathcal{O}}^{++}$ —has height equal to the supremum of the eventually writable ordinals. Next we prove that ${\mathcal{O}^+}$ is Turing computably isomorphic to the halting problem of infinite time Turing computability, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Borel ideals vs. Borel sets of countable relations and trees.Samy Zafrany - 1989 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 43 (2):161-195.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The mathematical work of S. C. Kleene.J. R. Shoenfield & S. C. Kleene - 1995 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1 (1):8-43.
    §1. The origins of recursion theory. In dedicating a book to Steve Kleene, I referred to him as the person who made recursion theory into a theory. Recursion theory was begun by Kleene's teacher at Princeton, Alonzo Church, who first defined the class of recursive functions; first maintained that this class was the class of computable functions ; and first used this fact to solve negatively some classical problems on the existence of algorithms. However, it was Kleene who, in his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The weakness of the pigeonhole principle under hyperarithmetical reductions.Benoit Monin & Ludovic Patey - 2020 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 21 (3):2150013.
    The infinite pigeonhole principle for 2-partitions asserts the existence, for every set A, of an infinite subset of A or of its complement. In this paper, we study the infinite pigeonhole pr...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ungroundedness in Tarskian Languages.Saul A. Kripke - 2019 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 48 (3):603-609.
    Several writers have assumed that when in “Outline of a Theory of Truth” I wrote that “the orthodox approach” – that is, Tarski’s account of the truth definition – admits descending chains, I was relying on a simple compactness theorem argument, and that non-standard models must result. However, I was actually relying on a paper on ‘pseudo-well-orderings’ by Harrison. The descending hierarchy of languages I define is a standard model. Yablo’s Paradox later emerged as a key to interpreting the result.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Formal systems for some branches of intuitionistic analysis.G. Kreisel - 1970 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 1 (3):229.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • On the equimorphism types of linear orderings.Antonio Montalbán - 2007 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 13 (1):71-99.
    §1. Introduction. A linear ordering embedsinto another linear ordering if it is isomorphic to a subset of it. Two linear orderings are said to beequimorphicif they can be embedded in each other. This is an equivalence relation, and we call the equivalence classesequimorphism types. We analyze the structure of equimorphism types of linear orderings, which is partially ordered by the embeddability relation. Our analysis is mainly fromthe viewpoints of Computability Theory and Reverse Mathematics. But we also obtain results, as the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Indecomposable linear orderings and hyperarithmetic analysis.Antonio Montalbán - 2006 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 6 (1):89-120.
    A statement of hyperarithmetic analysis is a sentence of second order arithmetic S such that for every Y⊆ω, the minimum ω-model containing Y of RCA0 + S is HYP, the ω-model consisting of the sets hyperarithmetic in Y. We provide an example of a mathematical theorem which is a statement of hyperarithmetic analysis. This statement, that we call INDEC, is due to Jullien [13]. To the author's knowledge, no other already published, purely mathematical statement has been found with this property (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Ordinal Numbers and Predicative Set Theory.Hao Wang - 1959 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 5 (14-24):216-239.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Predicativity.Solomon Feferman - 2005 - In Stewart Shapiro (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 590-624.
    What is predicativity? While the term suggests that there is a single idea involved, what the history will show is that there are a number of ideas of predicativity which may lead to different logical analyses, and I shall uncover these only gradually. A central question will then be what, if anything, unifies them. Though early discussions are often muddy on the concepts and their employment, in a number of important respects they set the stage for the further developments, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • A note on Dasgupta’s Generalism.Joshua Babic & Lorenzo Cocco - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 177 (8):2153-2162.
    Dasgupta :35–67, 2009) has argued that material individuals, such as particles and laptops, are metaphysically objectionable and must be eliminated from our fundamental theories of the world. He proposes to eliminate them by redescribing all the fundamental facts of the world in a variant of predicate functor logic. We study the status, on this theory, of a putative fact particularly recalcitrant to a formulation within predicate functor logic: his own claim that there are no fundamental or primitive material individuals. We (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The next admissible ordinal.Richard Gostanian - 1979 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 17 (1):171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kleene's amazing second recursion theorem.Yiannis N. Moschovakis - 2010 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 16 (2):189 - 239.
    This little gem is stated unbilled and proved in the last two lines of §2 of the short note Kleene [1938]. In modern notation, with all the hypotheses stated explicitly and in a strong form, it reads as follows:Second Recursion Theorem. Fix a set V ⊆ ℕ, and suppose that for each natural number n ϵ ℕ = {0, 1, 2, …}, φn: ℕ1+n ⇀ V is a recursive partial function of arguments with values in V so that the standard (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • On characterizability in L ω1ω0.Per Lindström - 1966 - Theoria 32 (3):165-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A Hierarchy of Computably Enumerable Degrees.Rod Downey & Noam Greenberg - 2018 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 24 (1):53-89.
    We introduce a new hierarchy of computably enumerable degrees. This hierarchy is based on computable ordinal notations measuring complexity of approximation of${\rm{\Delta }}_2^0$functions. The hierarchy unifies and classifies the combinatorics of a number of diverse constructions in computability theory. It does so along the lines of the high degrees (Martin) and the array noncomputable degrees (Downey, Jockusch, and Stob). The hierarchy also gives a number of natural definability results in the c.e. degrees, including a definable antichain.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Notes on Measure and Category in Recursion Theory.Hisao Tanaka - 1970 - Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 3 (5):231-241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Degrees of orderings not isomorphic to recursive linear orderings.Carl G. Jockusch & Robert I. Soare - 1991 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 52 (1-2):39-64.
    It is shown that for every nonzero r.e. degree c there is a linear ordering of degree c which is not isomorphic to any recursive linear ordering. It follows that there is a linear ordering of low degree which is not isomorphic to any recursive linear ordering. It is shown further that there is a linear ordering L such that L is not isomorphic to any recursive linear ordering, and L together with its ‘infinitely far apart’ relation is of low (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Ordinal analysis of partial combinatory algebras.Paul Shafer & Sebastiaan A. Terwijn - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (3):1154-1188.
    For every partial combinatory algebra, we define a hierarchy of extensionality relations using ordinals. We investigate the closure ordinals of pca’s, i.e., the smallest ordinals where these relations become equal. We show that the closure ordinal of Kleene’s first model is ${\omega _1^{\textit {CK}}}$ and that the closure ordinal of Kleene’s second model is $\omega _1$. We calculate the exact complexities of the extensionality relations in Kleene’s first model, showing that they exhaust the hyperarithmetical hierarchy. We also discuss embeddings of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Some applications of forcing to hierarchy problems in arithmetic.Peter G. Hinman - 1969 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 15 (20-22):341-352.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • An Extension of the Hyperprojective Hierarchy.Eliot D. Feldman - 1971 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 17 (1):395-409.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A degree-theoretic definition of the ramified analytical hierarchy.Carl G. Jockusch & Stephen G. Simpson - 1976 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 10 (1):1-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • (1 other version)Arithmetical Sets and Retracing Functions.C. E. M. Yates - 1967 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 13 (13-14):193-204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Small recursive ordinals, many-one degrees, and the arithmetical difference hierarchy.L. Hay - 1975 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 8 (3):297.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A recursion theoretic characterization of the Topological Vaught Conjecture in the Zermelo‐Fraenkel set theory.Vassilios Gregoriades - 2017 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 63 (6):544-551.
    We prove a recursion theoretic characterization of the Topological Vaught Conjecture in the Zermelo‐Fraenkel set theory by using tools from effective descriptive set theory and by revisiting the result of Miller that orbits in Polish G‐spaces are Borel sets.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Recursive well-founded orderings.Keh-Hsun Chen - 1978 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 13 (2):117-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Dyck and the Preiss separation uniformly.Vassilios Gregoriades - 2018 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 169 (10):1082-1116.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Decision Times of Infinite Computations.Merlin Carl, Philipp Schlicht & Philip Welch - 2022 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 63 (2).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On bi-embeddable categoricity of algebraic structures.Nikolay Bazhenov, Dino Rossegger & Maxim Zubkov - 2022 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 173 (3):103060.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • $\Pi ^{0}_{1}$ -Encodability and Omniscient Reductions.Benoit Monin & Ludovic Patey - 2019 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 60 (1):1-12.
    A set of integers A is computably encodable if every infinite set of integers has an infinite subset computing A. By a result of Solovay, the computably encodable sets are exactly the hyperarithmetic ones. In this article, we extend this notion of computable encodability to subsets of the Baire space, and we characterize the Π10-encodable compact sets as those which admit a nonempty Σ11-subset. Thanks to this equivalence, we prove that weak weak König’s lemma is not strongly computably reducible to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark