Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)Semantic networks of english.George A. Miller & Christiane Fellbaum - 1991 - Cognition 41 (1-3):197-229.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Categorical perception of familiar objects.Fiona N. Newell & Heinrich H. Bülthoff - 2002 - Cognition 85 (2):113-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Generative versus nongenerative thought.Michael C. Corballis - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):242-243.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Spatial development.David R. Olson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):249-249.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Salience of visual parts.Donald D. Hoffman & Manish Singh - 1997 - Cognition 63 (1):29-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Different structures for concepts of individuals, stuffs, and real kinds: One mama, more milk, and many mice.Paul Bloom - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (1):66-67.
    Although our concepts of “Mama,” “milk,” and “mice” have much in common, the suggestion that they are identical in structure in the mind of the prelinguistic child is mistaken. Even infants think about objects as different from substances and appreciate the distinction between kinds (e.g., mice) and individuals (e.g., Mama). Such cognitive capacities exist in other animals as well, and have important adaptive consequences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Is the object concept formal?Roberto Casati - 2004 - Dialectica 58 (3):383–394.
    This review article explores several senses in which it can be held that the (actual, psychological) concept of an object is a formal concept, as opposed, here, to being a sortal concept. Some recent positions both from the philosophical and psychological literature are analyzed: Object-sortalism (Xu), quasi-sortalist reductive strategies (Bloom), qualified sortalism (Wiggins), demonstrative theories (Fodor), and anti-sortalism (Ayers).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Transforming temporal knowledge: Conceptual change between event concepts.Xiang Chen - 2005 - Perspectives on Science 13 (1):49-73.
    : This paper offers a preliminary analysis of conceptual change between event concepts. It begins with a brief review of the major findings of cognitive studies on event knowledge. The script model proposed by Schank and Abelson was the first attempt to represent event knowledge. Subsequent cognitive studies indicated that event knowledge is organized in the form of dimensional organizations in which temporally successive actions are related causally. This paper proposes a frame representation to capture and outline the internal structure (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Mental imagery.Nigel J. T. Thomas - 2001 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Mental imagery (varieties of which are sometimes colloquially refered to as “visualizing,” “seeing in the mind's eye,” “hearing in the head,” “imagining the feel of,” etc.) is quasi-perceptual experience; it resembles perceptual experience, but occurs in the absence of the appropriate external stimuli. It is also generally understood to bear intentionality (i.e., mental images are always images of something or other), and thereby to function as a form of mental representation. Traditionally, visual mental imagery, the most discussed variety, was thought (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Concept empiricism: A methodological critique.Edouard Machery - 2006 - Cognition 104 (1):19-46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Perceptual symbol systems.Lawrence W. Barsalou - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (4):577-660.
    Prior to the twentieth century, theories of knowledge were inherently perceptual. Since then, developments in logic, statis- tics, and programming languages have inspired amodal theories that rest on principles fundamentally different from those underlying perception. In addition, perceptual approaches have become widely viewed as untenable because they are assumed to implement record- ing systems, not conceptual systems. A perceptual theory of knowledge is developed here in the context of current cognitive science and neuroscience. During perceptual experience, association areas in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   737 citations  
  • Concepts in Physics: A Comparative Cognitive Analysis of Arabic and French Terminologies.Hicham Lahlou - 2021 - Kuala Lumpur, Federal Territory of Kuala Lumpur, Malaysia: Institut Terjemahan & Buku Malaysia Berhad (ITBM).
    This book offers substantial insight into students’ conceptualization of scientific terminology. The current book explores the commonalities and distinctions between Arabic and French physics terms, and the impact of the language disparities on students’ understanding of physics terms. This book adopts a novel approach to the problem of scientific terminology by exploring physics terms’ polysemy, prototypical meanings, and conceptual metaphor and metonymy, which motivates their extension of meaning. The book also investigates how the linguistic discrepancies and other variables affect the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Concept Appraisal.Sapphira R. Thorne, Jake Quilty-Dunn, Joulia Smortchkova, Nicholas Shea & James A. Hampton - 2021 - Cognitive Science 45 (5):e12978.
    This paper reports the first empirical investigation of the hypothesis that epistemic appraisals form part of the structure of concepts. To date, studies of concepts have focused on the way concepts encode properties of objects and the way those features are used in categorization and in other cognitive tasks. Philosophical considerations show the importance of also considering how a thinker assesses the epistemic value of beliefs and other cognitive resources and, in particular, concepts. We demonstrate that there are multiple, reliably (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Studying Invention: The Hand Tool as a Model System.Antolin M. Llorente, Stacey Dixon & Robert J. Weber - 1993 - Science, Technology and Human Values 18 (4):480-505.
    Invention is an important source of technology, and, to understand invention, one needs a model system or prototype. A candidate model system is the hand tool. Using the hand tool as an example, the authors present a systematic approach to invention, dealing with description, classification, and joining or integrating simpler forms. Heuristics for when to integrate are presented. Finally, the authors introduce a new way of thinking about hand tools: simple spatial transformations applied to an abstract element make possible the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The development of categorisation and conceptual thinking in early childhood: methods and limitations.Nicolás Alessandroni & Cintia Rodríguez - 2020 - Psicologia: Reflexão E Crítica 33.
    We present a systematic and qualitative review of academic literature on early conceptual development (0–24 months of age), with an emphasis on methodological aspects. The final sample of our review included 281 studies reported in 115 articles. The main aims of the article were four: first, to organise studies into sets according to methodological similarities and differences; second, to elaborate on the methodological procedures that characterise each set; third, to circumscribe the empirical indicators that different sets of studies consider as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ontology and geographic objects: An empirical study of cognitive categorization.David M. Mark, Barry Smith & Barbara Tversky - 1999 - In Freksa C. & Mark David M. (eds.), Spatial Information Theory. Cognitive and Computational Foundations of Geographic Information Science (Lecture Notes in Computer Science 1661). pp. 283-298.
    Cognitive categories in the geographic realm appear to manifest certain special features as contrasted with categories for objects at surveyable scales. We have argued that these features reflect specific ontological characteristics of geographic objects. This paper presents hypotheses as to the nature of the features mentioned, reviews previous empirical work on geographic categories, and presents the results of pilot experiments that used English-speaking subjects to test our hypotheses. Our experiments show geographic categories to be similar to their non-geographic counterparts in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Building machines that learn and think like people.Brenden M. Lake, Tomer D. Ullman, Joshua B. Tenenbaum & Samuel J. Gershman - 2017 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 40.
    Recent progress in artificial intelligence has renewed interest in building systems that learn and think like people. Many advances have come from using deep neural networks trained end-to-end in tasks such as object recognition, video games, and board games, achieving performance that equals or even beats that of humans in some respects. Despite their biological inspiration and performance achievements, these systems differ from human intelligence in crucial ways. We review progress in cognitive science suggesting that truly human-like learning and thinking (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • “Robins are a part of birds”: The confusion of semantic relations.Douglas J. Herrmann, Roger Chaffin & Morton E. Winston - 1986 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 24 (6):413-415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Spatial and cognitive vision differentiate at low levels, but not in language.Bruce Bridgeman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):240-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Whence and whither in spatial language and spatial cognition?Barbara Landau & Ray Jackendoff - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):255-265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • From observations on language to theories of visual perception.Johan Wagemans - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):253-254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • There is more to location than prepositions.David C. Bennett - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):239-239.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Semantic networks of English.George A. Miller & Christiane Fellbaum - 1992 - In Beth Levin & Steven Pinker (eds.), Lexical & conceptual semantics. Cambridge, Ma.: Blackwell. pp. 197-229.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Generics and mental representations.Ariel Cohen - 2004 - Linguistics and Philosophy 27 (5):529-556.
    It is widely agreed that generics tolerate exceptions. It turns out, however, that exceptions are tolerated only so long as they do not violate homogeneity: when the exceptions are not concentrated in a salient “chunk” of the domain of the generic. The criterion for salience of a chunk is cognitive: it is dependent on the way in which the domain is mentally represented. Findings of psychological experiments about the ways in which different domains are represented, and the actors affecting such (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • (1 other version)Natural epistemology or evolved metaphysics? Developmental evidence for early-developed, intuitive, category-specific, incomplete, and stubborn metaphysical presumptions.Pascal Boyer - 2000 - Philosophical Psychology 13 (3):277 – 297.
    Cognitive developmental evidence is sometimes conscripted to support ''naturalized epistemology'' arguments to the effect that a general epistemic stance leads children to build theory-like accounts of underlying properties of kinds. A review of the evidence suggests that what prompts conceptual acquisition is not a general epistemic stance but a series of category-specific intuitive principles that constitute an evolved ''natural metaphysics''. This consists in a system of categories and category-specific inferential processes founded on definite biases in prototype formation. Evidence for this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Modular Ontologies for Genetically Modified People and their Bioethical Implications.Derek So, Robert Sladek & Yann Joly - 2024 - NanoEthics 18 (2):1-35.
    Participants in the long-running bioethical debate over human germline genetic modification (HGGM) tend to imagine future people abstractly and on the basis of conventionalized characteristics familiar from science fiction, such as intelligence, disease resistance and height. In order to distinguish these from scientifically meaningful terms like “phenotype” and “trait,” this article proposes the term “persemes” to describe the units of difference for hypothetical people. In the HGGM debate, persemes are frequently conceptualized as similar, modular entities, like building blocks to be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Context Matters: Recovering Human Semantic Structure from Machine Learning Analysis of Large‐Scale Text Corpora.Marius Cătălin Iordan, Tyler Giallanza, Cameron T. Ellis, Nicole M. Beckage & Jonathan D. Cohen - 2022 - Cognitive Science 46 (2):e13085.
    Cognitive Science, Volume 46, Issue 2, February 2022.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Parts beget parts: Bootstrapping hierarchical object representations through visual statistical learning.Alan L. F. Lee, Zili Liu & Hongjing Lu - 2021 - Cognition 209 (C):104515.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The role of functional information for infant categorization.Birgit Träuble & Sabina Pauen - 2007 - Cognition 105 (2):362-379.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Do viewpoint-dependent mechanisms generalize across members of a class?Michael J. Tarr & Isabel Gauthier - 1998 - Cognition 67 (1-2):73-110.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)A Taxonomy of Part‐Whole Relations.Morton E. Winston, Roger Chaffin & Douglas Herrmann - 1987 - Cognitive Science 11 (4):417-444.
    A taxonomy of part‐whole or meronymic relations is developed to explain the ordinary English‐speaker's use of the term “part of” and its cognates. The resulting classification yields six types of meronymic relations: 1. component‐integral object (pedal‐bike), 2. member‐collection (ship‐fleet), 3. portion‐mass (slice‐pie), 4. stuff‐object (steel‐car), 5. feature‐activity (paying‐shopping), and 6. place‐area (Everglades‐Florida). Meronymic relations ore further distinguished from other inclusion relations, such as spatial inclusion, and class inclusion, and from several other semantic relations: attribution, attachment, and ownership. This taxonomy is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Applications and limits of mereology. From the theory of parts to the theory of wholes.Massimo Libardi - 1994 - Axiomathes 5 (1):13-54.
    The discovery of the importance of mereology follows and does not precede the formalisation of the theory. In particular, it was only after the construction of an axiomatic theory of the part-whole relation by the Polish logician Stanisław Leśniewski that any attempt was made to reinterpret some periods in the history of philosophy in the light of the theory of parts and wholes. Secondly, the push for formalisation - and the individuation of mereology as a specific theoretical field - arise (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Context-driven expectations about focus alternatives.Christina S. Kim, Christine Gunlogson, Michael K. Tanenhaus & Jeffrey T. Runner - 2015 - Cognition 139 (C):28-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Prepositions aren't places.Barbara Tversky & Herbert H. Clark - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):252-253.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Talking to yourself about what is where: What is the vocabulary of preattentive vision?Jeremy M. Wolfe - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):254-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does rank have its privilege? Inductive inferences within folkbiological taxonomies.John D. Coley, Douglas L. Medin & Scott Atran - 1997 - Cognition 64 (1):73-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • (1 other version)From Features via Frames to Spaces: Modeling Scientific Conceptual Change Without Incommensurability or Aprioricity.Frank Zenker - 2014 - In T. Gamerschlag, R. Gerland, R. Osswald & W. Petersen (eds.), Frames and Concept Types: Applications in Language and Philosophy. pp. 69-89.
    The frame model, originating in artificial intelligence and cognitive psychology, has recently been applied to change-phenomena traditionally studied within history and philosophy of science. Its application purpose is to account for episodes of conceptual dynamics in the empirical sciences suggestive of incommensurability as evidenced by “ruptures” in the symbolic forms of historically successive empirical theories with similar classes of applications. This article reviews the frame model and traces its development from the feature list model. Drawing on extant literature, examples of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Effects of contextual composition of category triads on semantic interrelatedness among members.Lorraine A. Low - 1988 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 26 (5):403-406.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The role of cerebral lateralization in expression of spatial cognition.Halle D. Brown - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):240-241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conceptual perspective and lexical choice in acquisition.Eve V. Clark - 1997 - Cognition 64 (1):1-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • The development of features in object concepts.Philippe G. Schyns, Robert L. Goldstone & Jean-Pierre Thibaut - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (1):1-17.
    According to one productive and influential approach to cognition, categorization, object recognition, and higher level cognitive processes operate on a set of fixed features, which are the output of lower level perceptual processes. In many situations, however, it is the higher level cognitive process being executed that influences the lower level features that are created. Rather than viewing the repertoire of features as being fixed by low-level processes, we present a theory in which people create features to subserve the representation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • From Sensations to Concepts: a Proposal for Two Learning Processes.Peter Gärdenfors - 2019 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 10 (3):441-464.
    This article presents two learning processes in order to explain how children at an early age can transform a complex sensory input to concepts and categories. The first process constructs the perceptual structures that emerge in children’s cognitive development by detecting invariants in the sensory input. The invariant structures involve a reduction in dimensionality of the sensory information. It is argued that this process generates the primary domains of space, objects and actions and that these domains can be represented as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Is spatial information imprecise or just coarsely coded?P. Bryan Heidorn & Stephen C. Hirtle - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):246-247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “What” and “where” in spatial language and spatial cognition.Barbara Landau & Ray Jackendoff - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):217-238.
    Fundamental to spatial knowledge in all species are the representations underlying object recognition, object search, and navigation through space. But what sets humans apart from other species is our ability to express spatial experience through language. This target article explores the language ofobjectsandplaces, asking what geometric properties are preserved in the representations underlying object nouns and spatial prepositions in English. Evidence from these two aspects of language suggests there are significant differences in the geometric richness with which objects and places (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  • Perceiving, remembering, and communicating structure in events.Jeffrey M. Zacks, Barbara Tversky & Gowri Iyer - 2001 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 130 (1):29.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Evolution and devolution of folkbiological knowledge.Phillip Wolff, Douglas L. Medin & Connie Pankratz - 1999 - Cognition 73 (2):177-204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • On the equivalence of superordinate concepts.Edward J. Wisniewski, Mutsumi Imai & Lyman Casey - 1996 - Cognition 60 (3):269-298.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Evidence for the Role of Shape in Mental Representations of Similes.Lisanne Weelden, Joost Schilperoord & Alfons Maes - 2014 - Cognitive Science 38 (2):303-321.
    People mentally represent the shapes of objects. For instance, the mental representation of an eagle is different when one thinks about a flying or resting eagle. This study examined the role of shape in mental representations of similes (i.e., metaphoric comparisons). We tested the prediction that when people process a simile they will mentally represent the entities of the comparison as having a similar shape. We conducted two experiments in which participants read sentences that either did (experimental sentences) or did (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Towards a dynamic connectionist model of memory.Douglas Vickers & Michael D. Lee - 1997 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (1):40-41.
    Glenberg's account falls short in several respects. Besides requiring clearer explication of basic concepts, his account fails to recognize the autonomous nature of perception. His account of what is remembered, and its description, is too static. His strictures against connectionist modeling might be overcome by combining the notions of psychological space and principled learning in an embodied and situated network.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evidence for the Role of Shape in Mental Representations of Similes.Lisanne van Weelden, Joost Schilperoord & Alfons Maes - 2014 - Cognitive Science 38 (2):303-321.
    People mentally represent the shapes of objects. For instance, the mental representation of an eagle is different when one thinks about a flying or resting eagle. This study examined the role of shape in mental representations of similes (i.e., metaphoric comparisons). We tested the prediction that when people process a simile they will mentally represent the entities of the comparison as having a similar shape. We conducted two experiments in which participants read sentences that either did (experimental sentences) or did (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark