Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Genidentity and Biological Processes.Thomas Pradeu - 2018 - In Daniel J. Nicholson & John Dupré (eds.), Everything Flows: Towards a Processual Philosophy of Biology. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    A crucial question for a process view of life is how to identify a process and how to follow it through time. The genidentity view can contribute decisively to this project. It says that the identity through time of an entity X is given by a well-identified series of continuous states of affairs. Genidentity helps address the problem of diachronic identity in the living world. This chapter describes the centrality of the concept of genidentity for David Hull and proposes an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Natural process – Natural selection.Arto Annila - 2007 - Biophysical Chemistry 127: 123–128.
    Life is supported by a myriad of chemical reactions. To describe the overall process we have formulated entropy for an open system undergoing chemical reactions. The entropy formula allows us to recognize various ways for the system to move towards more probable states. These correspond to the basic processes of life i.e. proliferation, differentiation, expansion, energy intake, adaptation and maturation. We propose that the rate of entropy production by various mechanisms is the fitness criterion of natural selection. The quest for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Some resonances between Eastern thought and Integral Biomathics in the framework of the WLIMES formalism for modelling living systems.Plamen L. Simeonov & Andree C. Ehresmann - forthcoming - Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology 131 (Special).
    Forty-two years ago, Capra published “The Tao of Physics” (Capra, 1975). In this book (page 17) he writes: “The exploration of the atomic and subatomic world in the twentieth century has …. necessitated a radical revision of many of our basic concepts” and that, unlike ‘classical’ physics, the sub-atomic and quantum “modern physics” shows resonances with Eastern thoughts and “leads us to a view of the world which is very similar to the views held by mystics of all ages and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The social brain meets the reactive genome: neuroscience, epigenetics and the new social biology.Maurizio Meloni - 2014 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8.
    The rise of molecular epigenetics over the last few years promises to bring the discourse about the sociality and susceptibility to environmental influences of the brain to an entirely new level. Epigenetics deals with molecular mechanisms such as gene expression, which may embed in the organism “memories” of social experiences and environmental exposures. These changes in gene expression may be transmitted across generations without changes in the DNA sequence. Epigenetics is the most advanced example of the new postgenomic and context-dependent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Intentionally: A problem of multiple reference frames, specificational information, and extraordinary boundary conditions on natural law.M. T. Turvey - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):153-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Information, causality, and intentionality.David Kelley - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):147-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Semantic information: Inference rules + memory.Michael Lebowitz - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):147-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Approaches to the Question, ‘What is Life?’: Reconciling Theoretical Biology with Philosophical Biology.Arran Gare - 2008 - Cosmos and History : The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy 4 (1-2):53-77.
    Philosophical biologists have attempted to define the distinction between life and non-life to more adequately define what it is to be human. They are reacting against idealism, but idealism is their point of departure, and they have embraced the reaction by idealists against the mechanistic notion of humans developed by the scientific materialists. Theoretical biologists also have attempted to develop a more adequate conception of life, but their point of departure has been within science itself. In their case, it has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Gould and Lewontin against the adaptacionist program.Santiago Ginnobili & Daniel Blanco - 2007 - Scientiae Studia 5 (1):35-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • More on how and why: cause and effect in biology revisited.Kevin N. Laland, John Odling-Smee, William Hoppitt & Tobias Uller - 2012 - Biology and Philosophy 28 (5):719-745.
    In 1961, Ernst Mayr published a highly influential article on the nature of causation in biology, in which he distinguished between proximate and ultimate causes. Mayr argued that proximate causes (e.g. physiological factors) and ultimate causes (e.g. natural selection) addressed distinct ‘how’ and ‘why’ questions and were not competing alternatives. That distinction retains explanatory value today. However, the adoption of Mayr’s heuristic led to the widespread belief that ontogenetic processes are irrelevant to evolutionary questions, a belief that has (1) hindered (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Complexity and evolution: What everybody knows.Daniel W. McShea - 1991 - Biology and Philosophy 6 (3):303-324.
    The consensus among evolutionists seems to be that the morphological complexity of organisms increases in evolution, although almost no empirical evidence for such a trend exists. Most studies of complexity have been theoretical, and the few empirical studies have not, with the exception of certain recent ones, been especially rigorous; reviews are presented of both the theoretical and empirical literature. The paucity of evidence raises the question of what sustains the consensus, and a number of suggestions are offered, including the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Intentionality and information processing: An alternative model for cognitive science.Kenneth M. Sayre - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):121-38.
    This article responds to two unresolved and crucial problems of cognitive science: (1) What is actually accomplished by functions of the nervous system that we ordinarily describe in the intentional idiom? and (2) What makes the information processing involved in these functions semantic? It is argued that, contrary to the assumptions of many cognitive theorists, the computational approach does not provide coherent answers to these problems, and that a more promising start would be to fall back on mathematical communication theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • Uncertainty about information.Ian E. Gordon - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):146-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Niche Inheritance: A Possible Basis for Classifying Multiple Inheritance Systems in Evolution.John Odling-Smee - 2007 - Biological Theory 2 (3):276-289.
    The theory of niche construction adds a second general inheritance system, ecological inheritance, to evolution . Ecological inheritance is the inheritance, via an external environment, of one or more natural selection pressures previously modified by niche-constructing organisms. This addition means descendant organisms inherit genes, and biotically transformed selection pressures in their environments, from their ancestors. The combined inheritance is called niche inheritance. Niche inheritance is used as a basis for classifying the multiple genetic and non-genetic, inheritance systems currently being proposed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Functional complexity in organisms: Parts as proxies. [REVIEW]Daniel W. McShea - 2000 - Biology and Philosophy 15 (5):641-668.
    The functional complexity, or the number of functions, of organisms hasfigured prominently in certain theoretical and empirical work inevolutionary biology. Large-scale trends in functional complexity andcorrelations between functional complexity and other variables, such assize, have been proposed. However, the notion of number of functions hasalso been operationally intractable, in that no method has been developedfor counting functions in an organism in a systematic and reliable way.Thus, studies have had to rely on the largely unsupported assumption thatnumber of functions can be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • C.H. Waddington’s differences with the creators of the modern evolutionary synthesis: a tale of two genes.Jonathan B. L. Bard - 2017 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 39 (3):18.
    In 2011, Peterson suggested that the main reason why C.H. Waddington was essentially ignored by the framers of the modern evolutionary synthesis in the 1950s was because they were Cartesian reductionists and mathematical population geneticists while he was a Whiteheadian organicist and experimental geneticist who worked with Drosophila. This paper suggests a further reason that can only be seen now. The former defined genes and their alleles by their selectable phenotypes, essentially the Mendelian view, while Waddington defined a gene through (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Risking Deeper Integration.Werner Callebaut, Linnda R. Caporael, Peter Hammerstein, Manfred D. Laubichler & Gerd B. Müller - 2006 - Biological Theory 1 (1):1-3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Where Does Pattee’s “How Does a Molecule Become a Message?” Belong in the History of Biosemiotics?Jon Umerez - 2009 - Biosemiotics 2 (3):269-290.
    Recalling the title of Yoxen’s classical paper on the influence of Schrödinger’s book, I analyze the role that the work of H. Pattee might have played, if any, in the development of Biosemiotics. I take his 1969 paper “How does a molecule become a message?” (Developmental Biology Supplement) as a first target due to several circumstances that make it especially salient. On the one hand, even if Pattee has obviously developed further his ideas on later papers, the significance of this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Intentionality and communication theory.K. M. Sayre - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):155-165.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Intentionality: No mystery.William T. Powers - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):152-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Intentionality as internality.Don Perlis & Rosalie Hall - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):151-152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A total process approach to perception.Maxine Morphis - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):150-151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Paradigmatology and its Application to Cross‐Disciplinary, Cross‐Professional and Cross‐Cultural Communication.Magoroh Maruyama - 1974 - Dialectica 28 (3‐4):135-196.
    SummaryParadigmatology as a science of structures of reasoning which vary from culture to culture, from profession to profession, and sometimes from individual to individual is outlined, and communication difficulties between paradigms are discussed. Three paradigms are used as examples: hierarchical, unilateral, homogenistic, universalistic, categorical, classificational, deductive, rank‐ordering, competitive paradigm with predetermined universe; individualistic, isolationists, random, nominalistic, atomistic, statistical, probabilistic, egocentric paradigm with thermodynamically and informationally decaying universe; mutualistic, reciprocally interactive, heterogeneity‐creating, network‐structured, relational, contextual, complementary, symbiotic paradigm with self‐generating and self‐organizing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Epistemology of Social Science Research: exploration in inculture researchers.Magoroh Maruyama - 1969 - Dialectica 23 (3‐4):229-280.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Cognitive science and the pragmatics of behavior.Lawrence E. Marks - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):150-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Intrinsic versus contrived intentionality.Donald M. MacKay - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):149-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Contemplating an evolutionary approach to entrepreneurship.Colin Jones - 2006 - World Futures 62 (8):576 – 594.
    This artical explores that application of evolutionary approaches to the study of entrepreneurship. It is argued an evolutionary theory of entrepreneurship must give as much concern to the foundations of evolutionary thought as it does the nature of entrepreneurship. The central point being that we must move beyond a debate or preference of the natural selection and adaptationist viewpoints. Only then can the interrelationships between individuals, firms, populations and the environments within which they interact be better appreciated.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The relationship between information theory, statistical mechanics, evolutionary theory, and cognitive Science.Michael Leyton - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):148-149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intentionality and the explanation of behavior.John Heil - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):146-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On some specific models of intentional behavior.Richard M. Golden - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):144-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Information is in the eye of the beholder.Rhea T. Eskew - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):144-144.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intentionality and information theory.David P. Ellerman - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):143-144.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Stalking intentionality.Fred I. Dretske - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):142-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Engineering's baby.Daniel C. Dennett - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):141-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Communication theory and intentionality.John G. Daugman - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):140-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Semantic content: In defense of a network approach.Paul M. Churchland - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):139-140.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Book reviews. [REVIEW]Roderick M. Chisholm, John Corcoran, Jorge Gracia, L. S. Carrier, T. N. Pelegrinis, Alfred L. Ivry, D. S. Clarke, Leo Rauch, Robert Young, Michael J. Loux, Rita Nolan, Gerald Vision, E. D. Klemke, Ruth Anna Putnam, Edward S. Reed, Maurice Mandelbaum, John Wettersten & Rachel Shihor - 1983 - Philosophia 13 (1-2):81-191.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book reviews. [REVIEW]Roderick M. Chisholm, John Corcoran, Jorge Gracia, L. S. Carrier, T. N. Pelegrinis, Alfred L. Ivry, D. S. Clarke, Leo Rauch, Robert Young, Michael J. Loux, Rita Nolan, Gerald Vision, E. D. Klemke, Ruth Anna Putnam, Edward S. Reed, Maurice Mandelbaum, John Wettersten & Rachel Shihor - 1983 - Philosophia 13 (1-2):359-362.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Not an alternative model for intentionality in vision.R. Brown, D. C. Earle & S. E. G. Lea - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):138-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Reflections on a Biometrics of Organismal Form.Fred L. Bookstein - 2019 - Biological Theory 14 (3):177-211.
    Back in 1987 the physicist/theoretical biologist Walter Elsasser reviewed a range of philosophical issues at the foundation of organismal biology above the molecular level. Two of these are particularly relevant to quantifications of form: the concept of ordered heterogeneity and the principle of nonstructural memory, the truism that typically the forms of organisms substantially resemble the forms of their ancestors. This essay attempts to weave Elsasser’s principles together with morphometrics for one prominent data type, the representation of animal forms by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Artificial life as it could be.Eric Bonabeau & Paul Bourgine - 1994 - World Futures 40 (4):227-249.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Whitehead and science education.Charles Birch - 1988 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 20 (2):33–41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The problem of form in molecular biology.Laura Nuño de la Rosa & Fernando M. Pérez Herranz - 2009 - In José Luis González Recio (ed.), Philosophical essays on physics and biology. New York: G. Olms.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark