Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Fighting human hubris: Intelligence in nonhuman animals and artefacts.Christian Hugo Hoffmann - 2023 - Ethics and Bioethics (in Central Europe) 13 (1-2):1-14.
    100 years ago, the editors of the Journal of Educational Psychology conducted one of the most famous studies of experts’ conceptions of human intelligence. This was reason enough to prompt the question where we stand today with making sense of “intelligence”. In this paper, we argue that we should overcome our anthropocentrism and appreciate the wonders of intelligence in nonhuman and nonbiological animals instead. For that reason, we study two cases of octopus intelligence and intelligence in machine learning systems to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The intelligence left in AI.Denis L. Baggi - 2000 - AI and Society 14 (3-4):348-378.
    In its forty years of existence, Artificial Intelligence has suffered both from the exaggerated claims of those who saw it as the definitive solution of an ancestral dream — that of constructing an intelligent machine-and from its detractors, who described it as the latest fad worthy of quacks. Yet AI is still alive, well and blossoming, and has left a legacy of tools and applications almost unequalled by any other field-probably because, as the heir of Renaissance thought, it represents a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Engineering's baby.Daniel C. Dennett - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):141-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Memory and cognition: An information processing model of man.Kenneth Deffenbacher & Evan Brown - 1973 - Theory and Decision 4 (2):141-178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the need for a computational psychology and the hope for a naturalistic one.Lawrence H. Davis - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):76-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Communication theory and intentionality.John G. Daugman - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):140-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Causes and representation.Robert Cummins - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):76-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Broadbent's Maltese cross memory model: Wisdom, but not especially unconventional.Robert G. Crowder - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (1):72-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Simulating convesations: The communion game. [REVIEW]Stephen J. Cowley & Karl MacDorman - 1995 - AI and Society 9 (2-3):116-137.
    In their enthusiasm for programming, computational linguists have tended to lose sight of what humansdo. They have conceived of conversations as independent of sound and the bodies that produce it. Thus, implicit in their simulations is the assumption that the text is the essence of talk. In fact, unlike electronic mail, conversations are acoustic events. During everyday talk, human understanding depends both on the words spoken and on fine interpersonal vocal coordination. When utterances are analysed into sequences of word-based forms, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Parrying.Kenneth Mark Colby - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):550-560.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Modeling a paranoid mind.Kenneth Mark Colby - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):515-534.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Some defects in Fodor' ‘computational’ theory.L. Jonathan Cohen - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):75-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Modular mind or unitary system: A duck-rabbit effect.Gillian Cohen - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (1):71-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are computational models like HEARSAY psychologically valid?Gillian Cohen - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (3):462-463.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Semantic content: In defense of a network approach.Paul M. Churchland - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):139-140.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • In defense of naturalism.Paul M. Churchland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):74-75.
    History and the modern sciences are characterized by what is sometimes called a “methodological naturalism” that disregards talk of divine agency. Some religious thinkers argue that this reflects a dogmatic materialism: a non-negotiable and a priori commitment to a materialist metaphysics. In response to this charge, I make a sharp distinction between procedural requirements and metaphysical commitments. The procedural requirement of history and the sciences—that proposed explanations appeal to publicly-accessible bodies of evidence—is non-negotiable, but has no metaphysical implications. The metaphysical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Some aspirin for Dasein.Eugene Charniak - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):74-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Passing Markers: A Theory of Contextual Influence in Language Comprehension.Eugene Charniak - 1983 - Cognitive Science 7 (3):171-190.
    Most Artificial Intelligence theories of language either assume a syntactic component which serves as “front end” for the rest of the system, or else reject all attempts at distinguishing modules within the comprehension system. In this paper we will present an alternative which, while keeping modularity, will account for several puzzles for typical “syntax first” theories. The major addition to this theory is a “marker passing” (or “spreading activation”) component, which operates in parallel to the normal syntactic component.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • The Maltese cross: Simplistic yes, new no.Thomas H. Carr & Tracy L. Brown - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (1):69-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Programs, language understanding, and Searle.Lawrence Richard Carleton - 1984 - Synthese 59 (May):219-30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Issues in computer modeling of cognitive phenomena: An artificial intelligence perspective.Jaime G. Carbonell - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):536-537.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Models of mind: Hidden plumbing.Enoch Callaway - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (1):68-69.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Must neurolinguistics be computational?Hugh W. Buckingham - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (3):461-462.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Maltese cross: A new simplistic model for memory.Donald E. Broadbent - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (1):55-68.
    This paper puts forward a general framework for thought about human information processing. It is intended to avoid some of the problems of pipeline or stage models of function. At the same time it avoids the snare of supposing a welter of indefinitely many separate processes. The approach is not particularly original, but rather represents the common elements or presuppositions in a number of modern theories. These presuppositions are not usually explicit, however, and making them so reduces the danger of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Not an alternative model for intentionality in vision.R. Brown, D. C. Earle & S. E. G. Lea - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):138-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Modules in models of memory.Donald E. Broadbent - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (1):86-94.
    This paper puts forward a general framework for thought about human information processing. It is intended to avoid some of the problems of pipeline or stage models of function. At the same time it avoids the snare of supposing a welter of indefinitely many separate processes. The approach is not particularly original, but rather represents the common elements or presuppositions in a number of modern theories. These presuppositions are not usually explicit, however, and making them so reduces the danger of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book reviews. [REVIEW]Baruch Brody, R. G. Swinburne, Alex C. Michalos, Gershon Weiler, Geoffrey Sampson, Marcelo Dascal, Shalom Lappin, Yehuda Melzer, Joseph Horovitz, Haim Marantz, Marcelo Dascal, M. Magidor & Michael Katz - 1974 - Philosophia 4 (2-3):279-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Conceptual Construction of Complexity Levels Theory in Spacetime Categorical Ontology: Non-Abelian Algebraic Topology, Many-Valued Logics and Dynamic Systems.R. Brown, J. F. Glazebrook & I. C. Baianu - 2007 - Axiomathes 17 (3-4):409-493.
    A novel conceptual framework is introduced for the Complexity Levels Theory in a Categorical Ontology of Space and Time. This conceptual and formal construction is intended for ontological studies of Emergent Biosystems, Super-complex Dynamics, Evolution and Human Consciousness. A claim is defended concerning the universal representation of an item’s essence in categorical terms. As an essential example, relational structures of living organisms are well represented by applying the important categorical concept of natural transformations to biomolecular reactions and relational structures that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A conceptual construction of complexity levels theory in spacetime categorical ontology: Non-Abelian algebraic topology, many-valued logics and dynamic systems. [REVIEW]R. Brown, J. F. Glazebrook & I. C. Baianu - 2007 - Axiomathes 17 (3-4):409-493.
    A novel conceptual framework is introduced for the Complexity Levels Theory in a Categorical Ontology of Space and Time. This conceptual and formal construction is intended for ontological studies of Emergent Biosystems, Super-complex Dynamics, Evolution and Human Consciousness. A claim is defended concerning the universal representation of an item’s essence in categorical terms. As an essential example, relational structures of living organisms are well represented by applying the important categorical concept of natural transformations to biomolecular reactions and relational structures that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Human Values in a Mechanistic Universe.Margaret A. Boden - 1977 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 11:135-171.
    The truth can be dangerous. It is because they realise this that the Roman Catholic Church forbid cremation. Cremation is, of course, theologically permissible, and in times of epidemic the Church allows it. But in normal times it is forbidden — Why? The reason is that the Church fears the influence of the image associated with it. It is difficult enough for the faithful to accept the notion of bodily resurrection after having seen a burial. But the image of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Human Values in a Mechanistic Universe.Margaret A. Boden - 1977 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 11:135-171.
    The truth can be dangerous. It is because they realise this that the Roman Catholic Church forbid cremation. Cremation is, of course, theologically permissible, and in times of epidemic the Church allows it. But in normal times it is forbidden — Why? The reason is that the Church fears the influence of the image associated with it. It is difficult enough for the faithful to accept the notion of bodily resurrection after having seen a burial. But the image of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Phrenology, “boxology,” and neurology.Sheila E. Blumstein - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (3):460-461.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • States' rights.Ned Block & Sylvain Bromberger - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):73-74.
    This is a response to Jerry Fodor’s article, Fodor, J. (1980). "Methodological solipsism as a research strategy in cognitive psychology." Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 63-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Expert systems and human knowledge: A view from the sociology of science. [REVIEW]Brian P. Bloomfield - 1988 - AI and Society 2 (1):17-29.
    After the setbacks suffered in the 1970s as a result of the ‘Lighthill Report’ (Lighthill, 1973), the science of Artificial Intelligence (AI) has undergone a dramatic revival of fortunes in the 1980s. But despite the obvious enormity and complexity of the problems tackled by AI, it still remains rather parochial in relation to the import of alternative though potentially fruitful ideas from other disciplines. With this in mind, the aim of the present paper is to utilise ideas from the sociology (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • ‘Naturalizing semantics’: New insight or old folly?Thomas Wheaton Bestor - 1991 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 34 (3-4):285-310.
    Those who naturalize semantics concentrate on avoiding difficulties in getting the right sort of cause for the biological item which is to possess semantic properties (to be ?true of or to be ?about? some physical item). Using an analogy with sense?data, I argue that the real difficulties will be trying to get any proposed neural representation to be the right sort of effect of natural processes. The idea of a biological item which can be a semantic ?primitive? is as bankrupt (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sprachverstehende maschinenLanguage understanding machines.Ansgar Beckermann - 1988 - Erkenntnis 28 (1):65-85.
    In this paper the author tries to disentangle some of the problems tied up in John Searle's famous Chinese-room-argument. In a first step to answer the question what it would be for a system to have not only syntax, but also semantics the author gives a brief account of the functioning of the language understanding systems (LUS) so far developed in the framework of AI research thereby making clear that systems like Winograd's SHRDLU are indeed doing little more than mere (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is mental time travel real time travel?Michael Barkasi & Melanie G. Rosen - 2020 - Philosophy and the Mind Sciences 1 (1):1-27.
    Episodic memory (memories of the personal past) and prospecting the future (anticipating events) are often described as mental time travel (MTT). While most use this description metaphorically, we argue that episodic memory may allow for MTT in at least some robust sense. While episodic memory experiences may not allow us to literally travel through time, they do afford genuine awareness of past-perceived events. This is in contrast to an alternative view on which episodic memory experiences present past-perceived events as mere (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Five Theses on Instrumental Realism.Davis Baird - 1988 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988 (1):164-173.
    Some may find an oxymoron in my title. But, my use of “instrumental” is to focus attention on the real instruments of science-pumps, dynamos and cyclotrons-and not the view that scientific theories are best understood as instruments. In what follows I characterize and argue for a kind of realism strongly wedded to what we do with scientific instruments, and divorced from what our theories may say about the entities manipulated by these instruments. My discussion owes much to Ian Hacking’s “Experimental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Computer Revolution in Philosophy.Martin Atkinson & Aaron Sloman - 1980 - Philosophical Quarterly 30 (119):178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Neurolinguistics must be computational.Michael A. Arbib & David Caplan - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (3):449-460.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   158 citations  
  • Cooperative computation as a concept for brain theory.Michael A. Arbib - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (3):475-483.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Induction of Augmented Transition Networks.John R. Anderson - 1977 - Cognitive Science 1 (2):125-157.
    LAS is a program that acquires augmented transition network (ATN) grammars. It requires as data sentences of the language and semantic network representatives of their meaning. In acquiring the ATN grammars, it induces the word classes of the language, the rules of formation for sentences, and the rules mapping sentences onto meaning. The induced ATN grammar can be used both for sentence generation and sentence comprehension. Critical to the performance of the program are assumptions that it makes about the relation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Simulation?Joseph Agassi - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):535-536.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the order of words.Anthony E. Ades & Mark J. Steedman - 1982 - Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (4):517 - 558.
    There is no doubt that the model presented here is incomplete. Many important categories, particularly negation and the adverbials, have been entirely ignored, and the treatment of Tense and the affixes is certainly inadequate. It also remains to be seen how the many constructions that have been ignored here are to be accommodated within the framework that has been outlined. However, the fact that a standard categorial lexicon, plus the four rule schemata, seems to come close to exhaustively specifying the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Going after PARRY.Robert P. Abelson - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):534-535.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Differences Between Belief and Knowledge Systems.Robert P. Abelson - 1979 - Cognitive Science 3 (4):355-366.
    Seven features which in practice seem to differentiate belief systems from knowledge systems are discussed. These are: nonconsensuality, “existence beliefs,” alternative worlds, evaluative components, episodic material, unboundedness, and variable credences. Each of these features gives rise to challenging representation problems. Progress on any of these problems within artificial intelligence would be helpful in the study of knowledge systems as well as belief systems, inasmuch as the distinction between the two types of systems is not absolute.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Means and Ends in Psycholinguistics.Rebecca M. Frumkina - 1979 - Diogenes 27 (105):116-137.
    At its birth, a new scientific discipline is baptized with the names of the two parent disciplines, Science X and Science Y. Subsequently, usage tends to shorten this compound name by giving preference to one or the other of the constituting terms so that the new term is less disconcerting and novel. Take biophysics, for example. Is it more closely related to physics than to biology, or the other way round? Today this question seems naive but it did not appear (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology.Jerry A. Fodor - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):63-73.
    The paper explores the distinction between two doctrines, both of which inform theory construction in much of modern cognitive psychology: the representational theory of mind and the computational theory of mind. According to the former, propositional attitudes are to be construed as relations that organisms bear to mental representations. According to the latter, mental processes have access only to formal (nonsemantic) properties of the mental representations over which they are defined.The following claims are defended: (1) That the traditional dispute between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   668 citations  
  • Methodological solipsism: replies to commentators.J. A. Fodor - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):99-109.
    The paper explores the distinction between two doctrines, both of which inform theory construction in much of modern cognitive psychology: the representational theory of mind and the computational theory of mind. According to the former, propositional attitudes are to be construed as relations that organisms bear to mental representations. According to the latter, mental processes have access only to formal (nonsemantic) properties of the mental representations over which they are defined.The following claims are defended: (1) That the traditional dispute between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Dynamics of Thought.Peter Gardenfors - 2005 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    This volume is a collection of some of the most important philosophical papers by Peter Gärdenfors. Spanning a period of more than 20 years of his research, they cover a wide ground of topics, from early works on decision theory, belief revision and nonmonotonic logic to more recent work on conceptual spaces, inductive reasoning, semantics and the evolutions of thinking. Many of the papers have only been published in places that are difficult to access. The common theme of all the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations