Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Choosing a patient-reported outcome measure.Leah M. McClimans & John Browne - 2011 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 32 (1):47-60.
    There has been much philosophical interest regarding the ‘hierarchy of evidence’ used to determine which study designs are of most value for reporting on questions of effectiveness, prognosis, and so on. There has been much less philosophical interest in the choice of outcome measures with which the results of, say, an RCT or a cohort study are presented. In this paper, we examine the FDA’s recently published guidelines for assessing the psychometric adequacy of patient-reported outcome measures. We focus on their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Universities as Social Background in “Trading Zone” Creation.Evgeny Maslanov - 2019 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 49 (6):493-509.
    The article analyzes the conception of a trading zone as a space of action and belief coordination. P. Galison proposed the conception based on anthropological and linguistic analogies. The article reviews the anthropological analogies aimed at building up the conception and the legitimacy of their use. The conclusion is that the analogies used are not accurate enough. If the tribes interacting in trading zones have a common history, material culture, and practices, they can hardly have significant differences. If they are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein on rules: Implications for authority and discipline in education.James D. Marshall - 1985 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 19 (1):3–11.
    James D Marshall; Wittgenstein on Rules: implications for authority and discipline in education, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 19, Issue 1, 30 May.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • On the Artist's Privileged Status.Mark Roskill - 1979 - Philosophy 54 (208):187 - 198.
    The topic of this paper is one more alluded to than actually studied, both in current philosophy of art and in the theory of criticism. There is a reason for this, which both clarifies the issue and suggests how it is to be approached. To suppose that the person responsible for a work of art has at least something interesting to say about it is only natural, and even commonplace. But granted this, the qualifications to be put on that assumption (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Can One Recognize Kinds of Private Objects?Charles E. Marks - 1975 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 (sup2):215-228.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein's scepticism' in on certainty.Norman Malcolm - 1988 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 31 (3):277 – 293.
    This paper compares Wittgenstein's conception of ?objective certainty? with Descartes's ?metaphysical certainty?. According to both conceptions if you are certain of something in these senses, then it is inconceivable that you are mistaken. But a striking difference is that for Descartes, if you are metaphysically certain of something it follows both that the something is so and that you know it is so; whereas on Wittgenstein's conception neither thing follows. I try to show that there is a form of ?scepticism? (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Normative Revisionism about Student Cheating.Odysseus Makridis & Fred Englander - 2020 - Journal of Academic Ethics 19 (1):1-23.
    This paper considers characteristic views advanced in the past fifteen years that may be considered relatively sympathetic to student practices of cheating on graded assignments or exams. We detect and analyze typical fallacies that are recurrent in articles that promote a revisionist view of cheating as morally permissible. We offer a general, deontological argument that cheating is immoral. The efforts to justify student cheating take several forms. For example, it has been argued that cheating may be tolerated if the student (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Synthetic Pattern: Figural and Narrative Identity.Giovanni Maddalena - 2013 - Contemporary Pragmatism 10 (1):145-165.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reasoning and logic.Jim Mackenzie - 1989 - Synthese 79 (1):99 - 117.
    Gilbert Harman, in Logic and Reasoning (Synthese 60 (1984), 107–127) describes an unsuccessful attempt ... to develop a theory which would give logic a special role in reasoning. Here reasoning is psychological, a procedure for revising one''s beliefs. In the present paper, I construe reasoning sociologically, as a process of linguistic interaction; and show how both reasoning in the psychologistic sense and logic are related to that process.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Logical constants.John MacFarlane - 2008 - Mind.
    Logic is usually thought to concern itself only with features that sentences and arguments possess in virtue of their logical structures or forms. The logical form of a sentence or argument is determined by its syntactic or semantic structure and by the placement of certain expressions called “logical constants.”[1] Thus, for example, the sentences Every boy loves some girl. and Some boy loves every girl. are thought to differ in logical form, even though they share a common syntactic and semantic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • The State Space of Artificial Intelligence.Holger Lyre - 2020 - Minds and Machines 30 (3):325-347.
    The goal of the paper is to develop and propose a general model of the state space of AI. Given the breathtaking progress in AI research and technologies in recent years, such conceptual work is of substantial theoretical interest. The present AI hype is mainly driven by the triumph of deep learning neural networks. As the distinguishing feature of such networks is the ability to self-learn, self-learning is identified as one important dimension of the AI state space. Another dimension is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Let me go and try.Kirk Ludwig - 2021 - Philosophical Explorations 24 (3):340-358.
    This paper argues for a deflationary account of trying on which ‘x tried to ϕ’ abbreviates ‘x did something with the intention of ϕ-ing’, where ‘did something’ is treated as a schematic verb. On this account, tryings are not a distinctive sort of episode present in some or all cases of acting. ‘x tried to ϕ’ simply relates some doing of x’s to a further aim x had, which may or may not have been achieved. Consequently, the analysis of ‘x (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Wittgenstein, Tolstoy, and the “Apocalyptic View”.Sabina Lovibond - 2016 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 46 (6):565-583.
    Some aspects of Wittgenstein’s thought are considered in the light of a remark he makes about the “apocalyptic” view of the world. The influence of Tolstoy on Wittgenstein is discussed and elaborated with reference to the idea of a “form of life” as a locus of order, and also to that of “exceptionality” in an unfolding course of events—the latter setting up a connection with the “apocalyptic” theme. This imaginative backdrop remains discernible in Wittgenstein’s later philosophy, which draws upon it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thinking and being: Heidegger and Wittgenstein on machination and lived-experience.Paul Livingston - 2003 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 46 (3):324 – 345.
    Heidegger's treatment of 'machination' in the Beiträge zur Philosophie begins the critique of technological thinking that would centrally characterize his later work. Unlike later discussions of technology, the critique of machination in Beiträge connects its arising to the predominance of 'lived-experience' ( Erlebnis ) as the concealed basis for the possibility of a pre-delineated, rule-based metaphysical understanding of the world. In this essay I explore this connection. The unity of machination and lived-experience becomes intelligible when both are traced to their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Referring and Reporting: The Use of Selfing Language in the Zhuangzi.Ronnie Littlejohn - 2018 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 17 (4):547-558.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Living Paradoxes: On Agamben, Taylor, and Human Subjectivity.King-Ho Leung - 2019 - Télos 187:85-106.
    Over the last two decades, Giorgio Agamben and Charles Taylor have produced important and influential genealogical works on the philosophical and political conceptions of secularity. Yet in their recent work, both of these thinkers have respectively returned to a prominent theme in their earlier works: Human life. This essay offers a parallel reading of Agamben and Taylor as post-Heideggerian critics of the modern conception of human subjectivity. Through examining these their respective characterizations of modern subjectivity — namely Taylor’s account of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A localist solution to the regress of epistemic justification.Adam Leite - 2005 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 83 (3):395 – 421.
    Guided by an account of the norms governing justificatory conversations, I propose that person-level epistemic justification is a matter of possessing a certain ability: the ability to provide objectively good reasons for one's belief by drawing upon considerations which one responsibly and correctly takes there to be no reason to doubt. On this view, justification requires responsible belief and is also objectively truth-conducive. The foundationalist doctrine of immediately justified beliefs is rejected, but so too is the thought that coherence in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Embodied Action, Enacted Bodies: the Example of Hypoglycaemia.John Law & Annemarie Mol - 2004 - Body and Society 10 (2-3):43-62.
    We all know that we have and are our bodies. But might it be possible to leave this common place? In the present article we try to do this by attending to the way we do our bodies. The site where we look for such action is that of handling the hypoglycaemias that sometimes happen to people with diabetes. In this site it appears that the body, active in measuring, feeling and countering hypoglycaemias is not a bounded whole: its boundaries (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • The world of instruction: undertaking the impossible.Megan J. Laverty - 2014 - Ethics and Education 9 (1):42-53.
    Throughout history, philosophers have reflected on educational questions. Some of their ideas emerged in defense of, or opposition to, skepticism about the possibility of formal teaching and learning. These philosophers include Plato, Augustine, St Thomas Aquinas, Søren Kierkegaard, Martin Heidegger, and Ludwig Wittgenstein. Together, they comprise a tradition that establishes the impossibility of instruction and the imperative to undertake it. The value of this tradition for contemporary education is that it redirects attention away from performance assessments and learning outcomes to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Action as a form of temporal unity: on Anscombe’s Intention.Douglas Lavin - 2015 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 45 (5):609-629.
    The aim of this paper is to display an alternative to the familiar decompositional approach in action theory, one that resists the demand for an explanation of action in non-agential terms, while not simply treating the notion of intentional agency as an unexplained primitive. On this Anscombean alternative, action is not a worldly event with certain psychological causes, but a distinctive form of material process, one that is not simply caused by an exercise of reason but is itself a productive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Global Justice as Process: Applying Normative Ideals of Indigenous African Governance.Helen Lauer - 2017 - Philosophical Papers 46 (1):163-189.
    This contribution explores correctives to several errors that Thomas Nagel seems to presuppose in his seminal defence of scepticism about global justice. I rely on lessons learned and conventions surviving in West African contemporary social and moral contexts, where people engage as a matter of course in divergent, historically antagonistic cultural and political traditions. On this view, global justice is a work in progress—not a fixed univocal formula but an on-going collaborative effort, a project in perpetual renovation and inter-cultural reconsideration (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book Review: Wittgenstein on Rules and NatureDrommKeithWittgenstein on Rules and NatureLondon: Continuum, 2008. 124 pp. $130/£65. [REVIEW]Oskari Kuusela - 2013 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 43 (3):400-405.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • If It Only Had a Brain: What “Neuro” Means for Science and Ethics.Thomasine Kushner & James Giordano - 2018 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 27 (4):540-543.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Understanding conative phenomenology: lessons from Ricœur.Uriah Kriegel - 2013 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 12 (3):537-557.
    I discuss Ricoeur's intriguing account of the phenomenology of the will, which focuses on deciding rather than desiring as the experientially paradigmatic exercise of the will.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Perspectives on Context and Contextualism.Monika Kopytowska & Piotr Stalmaszczyk - 2011 - Lodz Papers in Pragmatics 7 (2):181-187.
    Perspectives on Context and Contextualism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Realism, Reliabilism, and the 'Strong Programme' in the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge.Jeff Kochan - 2008 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 22 (1):21 – 38.
    In this essay, I respond to Tim Lewens's proposal that realists and Strong Programme theorists can find common ground in reliabilism. I agree with Lewens, but point to difficulties in his argument. Chief among these is his assumption that reliabilism is incompatible with the Strong Programme's principle of symmetry. I argue that the two are, in fact, compatible, and that Lewens misses this fact because he wrongly supposes that reliabilism entails naturalism. The Strong Programme can fully accommodate a reliabilism which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Bodily feeling in emotion.Philip J. Koch - 1987 - Dialogue 26 (1):59-75.
    One might imagine that this remark of James was too obvious to be denied, but in fact current philosophical orthodoxy runs against it. Since the renewal of interest in the emotions produced by Anthony Kenny's Action Emotion and Will in 1963, philosophers have focussed primarily on the cognitive aspects of emotions—the judgments, evaluations, beliefs, presuppositions which they contain. Bodily feelings have been, on the whole, slighted. Sometimes they are dismissed outright, as by Robert Solomon: “feelings no more constitute or define (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Plurality and Indeterminacy: Revising Castoriadis’s overly homogeneous conception of society.Jeff Klooger - 2012 - European Journal of Social Theory 15 (4):488-504.
    Despite its ground-breaking character, Castoriadis’s theory of society remains, in some respects, caught up in conceptual difficulties common to social theory generally, particularly the problem of conceptualizing social unity without resort to an understanding of society that downplays heterogeneity and over-emphasizes the homogeneous. Unlike many other theoretical approaches and traditions, Castoriadis’s work also offers a possible path out of this dilemma in the form of philosophical innovations which could enable us to conceptualize social unity without flattening the heterogeneous characteristics of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Burrowing a way: Plato’s cave and the labyrinth of creation.Jeff Klooger - 2020 - Thesis Eleven 161 (1):89-100.
    Plato’s simile of the cave has for over two millennia been the model for a particular understanding of the limitated nature of human knowledge. Castoriadis’s understanding of human knowledge differs from Plato’s in that the artificiality of knowledge, and by extension of culture and society in general, is seen not as a barrier to true knowledge but as a necessary precondition for any knowledge whatsoever. Plato dreams of leaving the cave and encountering the world in the clear light of day; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The burden of ideological masks in ideologiekritik: On trying to view faith scientifically.Kai Nielsen - 1992 - Metaphilosophy 23 (3):251-267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The concept of practice in Wittgenstein's later philosophy.Kjell S. Johannessen - 1988 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 31 (3):357 – 369.
    It is argued in this article that the concept of practice is one of the key concepts in Wittgenstein's later philosophy. It partly replaces his earlier talk about the inexpressible. ?The practice has to speak for itself, as Wittgenstein succinctly puts it. The concept of practice not only points to the ways in which the unity of our concepts are underpinned, as Gordon Baker has it, it also comprises the skills involved in handling the conceptualized phenomena, our prereflective familiarity with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Control of Perception and the Construction of Reality.Ernst von Glasersfeld John Richards - 1979 - Dialectica 33 (1):37-58.
    SummaryThis paper explicates a Constructivist Epistemology which underlies cybernetic models of perceiving and knowing. We focus on the recent work of W. T. Powers . Powers' model consists of hierarchially arranged negative feedback systems, is based on the claim that living organisms behave to control perceptions, and thus suggests that organisms construct their experiential world. We argue that this provides a basis for a modified scientific scepticism, a scepticism with a positive dimension gained by adding the notion of cognitive construction. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • "I am scared too": Children's Literature for an Ethics beyond Moral Concepts.Viktor Johansson - 2013 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 47 (4):80-109.
    This essay explores how moral discourse can have dogmatic tendencies. In exemplifying how it is possible to move beyond such tendencies, this essay turns to the Norwegian picture book Garmann's Summer. The essay not only suggests a vision of moral thinking, but also aims to demonstrate the role that literature, and particularly children's literature, can play in moral discourse, particularly in philosophy. The picture book's elaborations on the difficulties children can face when starting school show both what ethics beyond moral (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Gale in Reference and Religious Experience.Andrew V. Jeffrey - 1996 - Faith and Philosophy 13 (1):91-112.
    Richard Gale, in On the Nature and Existence of God, offers several reasons why an “historical-cum-indexical” theory of reference cannot be appropriate in explaining how people refer to God. The present paper identifies five distinct lines of argument in Gale, attempts to clarify several important desiderata for a successful theory of reference, and argues that Gale fails to discharge the burden of proof he has assumed, leaving the most important features of Alston’s “direct reference” theory untouched. Nevertheless, it is conceded (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The "given" and how to take it: Some reflections on phenomenal ontology.Jay F. Rosenberg - 1975 - Metaphilosophy 6 (3-4):303-337.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Premeditation and happenstance: The social construction of intention, action and knowledge. [REVIEW]Lena Jayyusi - 1993 - Human Studies 16 (4):435 - 454.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • What is a concept, that a person may grasp it?Ray Jackendoff - 1989 - Mind and Language 4 (1-2):68-102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Research as Affect-Sphere: Towards Spherogenics.Rick Iedema & Katherine Carroll - 2015 - Emotion Review 7 (1):67-72.
    This article outlines the main tenets of affect theory and links these to Sloterdijk’s spherology. Where affect foregrounds prepersonal energies and posthuman impulses, spherology provides a lens for considering how humans congregate in constantly reconfiguring socialities in their pursuit of legitimacy and immunity. The article then explores the relevance of “affective spheres” for contemporary social science research. The article’s main argument here is that research of contemporary organisational and professional practices must increasingly be spherogenic, or seeking to build “affective spheres.” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Basic Knowledge First.Jonathan Jenkins Ichikawa - 2017 - Episteme 14 (3):343-361.
    An infuential twenty-first century philosophical project posits a central role for knowledge: knowledge is more fundamental than epistemic states like belief and justification. So-called “knowledge first” theorists find support for this thought in identifying central theoretical roles for knowledge. I argue that a similar methodology supports a privileged role for more specific category of basic knowledge. Some of the roles that knowledge first theorists have posited for knowledge generally are better suited for basic knowledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. [REVIEW]Daniel D. Hutto - 2016 - Topoi 35 (2):617-626.
    Readers beware! This book is other than it first seems. Ludwig Wittgenstein’s latest philosophical offering is unlike anything that we have had from him to date. Its preface warns that the Tractatus is no textbook. This is an extreme understatement; really it is a deep puzzle—one that must be handled with great care. As the first lines signal there has been a radical change in the author’s characteristic style. Gone are the ingenious, probing explorations of topics undertaken in his highly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Klossowski and Wittgenstein on Sensation and Privacy.Conor Husbands - 2020 - Axiomathes 31 (4):529-548.
    This paper compares the treatment of private sensations in the works of Wittgenstein and Klossowski. Its aim is to show that, despite the differences between their traditions and methods, they align in at least one important respect: rejecting relations of reference between signs and private sensations. The paper briefly contextualises their lines of attack on these relations, situating the two thinkers’ commonalities amidst what are undeniably divergent wider purposes. It proceeds to argue for two more specific conclusions. Firstly, Klossowski’s own (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Relief and the Structure of Intentions in Late Palaeolithic Cave Art.Fiona Hughes - 2021 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 79 (3):285-300.
    Artworks at Lascaux and other late Palaeolithic caves integrate geological features or “relief” of the cave wall in a way that suggests a symbiotic relation between nature and culture. I argue this qualifies as “receptivity to a situation,” which is neither fully active nor merely passive and emerges as a necessary element of the intentions made apparent by such cave art. I argue against prominent interpretations of cave art, including the shamanist account and propose a structural interpretation attentive to particular (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Emotion as Personal Relatedness.R. Peter Hobson - 2012 - Emotion Review 4 (2):169-175.
    In this article, I consider the structure of interpersonal emotional relations. I argue that current cognitive-developmental theory has overestimated the role of conceptual thinking, and underestimated the role of intrinsic social-emotional organization, in the early development of such feelings as jealousy, shame, and concern. I suggest that human forms of social experience are shaped by a process through which one individual identifies with the bodily expressed attitudes of other people, and stress the diversity of self–other relational states. I draw on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Lying, Misleading, and the Argument from Cultural Slopes.Lisa Herzog - 2020 - Res Publica 27 (1):77-93.
    This paper discusses a novel kind of argument for assessing the moral significance of acts of lying and misleading. It is based on considerations about valuable social norms that might be eroded by these actions, because these actions function as signals. Given that social norms can play an important role in supporting morality, individuals have a responsibility to preserve such norms and to prevent ‘cultural slopes’ that erode them. Depending on whether there are norms against lying, misleading, or both, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What Kripke's puzzle doesn't tell us about language, meaning or bellief.Patricia Hanna - 2004 - Philosophia 31 (3-4):355-382.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Problem of Other Cultures.F. Allan Hanson & Rex Martin - 1973 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 3 (3):191-208.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Recollecting the Religious: Augustine in Answer to Meno’s Paradox.Ryan Haecker & Daniel Moulin-Stożek - 2021 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 40 (6):567-578.
    Philosophers of education often view the role of religion in education with suspicion, claiming it to be impossible, indoctrinatory or controversial unless reduced to secular premises and aims. The ‘post-secular’ and ‘decolonial’ turns of the new millennium have, however, afforded opportunities to revaluate this predilection. In a social and intellectual context where the arguments of previous generations of philosophers may be challenged on account of positivist assumptions, there may be an opening for the reconsideration of alternative but traditional religious epistemologies. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • III—The Wonder Of Signs.Adrian Haddock - 2021 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 121 (1):45-68.
    Anscombe raises a difficulty for the very idea of quotation. Davidson seeks to dissolve this difficulty. But the difficulty is real. And its lesson is that, in quotation, language takes itself as its topic in a non-objectifying manner. The idea of a non-objectifying manner of being a topic is crucial, not merely for understanding quotation, but for understanding the distinctive form of sensory consciousness in which language is perceived.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Good, the Bad, and the Vacuous: Wittgenstein on Modern and Future Musics.Eran Guter - 2015 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 73 (4):425-439.
    This article explains Wittgenstein's distinction between good, bad, and vacuous modern music which he introduced in a diary entry from January 27, 1931. I situate Wittgenstein's discussion in the context of Oswald Spengler's ideas concerning the decline of Western culture, which informed Wittgenstein's philosophical progress during his middle period, and I argue that the music theory of Heinrich Schenker, and Wittgenstein's critique thereof, served as an immediate link between Spengler's cultural pessimism and Wittgenstein's threefold distinction. I conclude that Wittgenstein's distinction (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Social Inquiry and the Pursuit of Reality: Cora Diamond and the Problem of Criticizing from “Outside”.John G. Gunnell - 2016 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 46 (6):584-603.
    Although social scientists have been devoted to discovering specific realities of social life, many theorists devoted to critical judgment have turned to philosophy in search of universal grounds of truth and reality. They have, however, worried about the problem of relativism. Although Wittgenstein has often been characterized as a relativist, Cora Diamond, inspired by G. E. M Anscombe, argues that his work, despite internal tensions, provides rational grounds for external criticism of social practices. Her argument and her critique of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation