Switch to: Citations

References in:

The Metaphysics of Perfect Beings

New York: Routledge (2008)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. David Lewis.Daniel Patrick Nolan - 2005 - Chesham: Mcgill-Queen's University Press.
    David Lewis's work is of fundamental importance in many areas of philosophical inquiry and there are few areas of Anglo-American philosophy where his impact has not been felt. Lewis's philosophy also has a rare unity: his views form a comprehensive philosophical system, answering a broad range of questions in metaphysics, philosophy of mind, philosophy of language, philosophy of action and many other areas. This breadth of Lewis's work, however, has meant that it is difficult to know where to start in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Why Only the Best Is Good Enough.Stephen Grover - 1988 - Analysis 48 (4):224 -.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Why Does the Universe Exist?Derek Parfit - 1991 - The Harvard Review of Philosophy 1 (1):4-5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • God and the Best.Bruce Langtry - 1996 - Faith and Philosophy 13 (3):311-328.
    The paper reaches two main conclusions: Firstly, even if there are one or more possible worlds than which there are none better, God cannot actualise any of them. Secondly, if there are possible worlds which God can actualise, and than which God can actualise none better, then God must actualise one of them. The paper is neutral between compatibilist and libertarian views of creaturely freedom. The paper's main ideas have been used, with modifications, in my book "God, the Best, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The moral problem.Michael Smith - 1994 - Cambridge, Mass., USA: Blackwell.
    What is the Moral Problem? NORMATIVE ETHICS VS. META-ETHICS It is a common fact of everyday life that we appraise each others' behaviour and attitudes from ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1125 citations  
  • Luminosity and the safety of knowledge.Ram Neta & Guy Rohrbaugh - 2004 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85 (4):396–406.
    In his recent Knowledge and its Limits, Timothy Williamson argues that no non-trivial mental state is such that being in that state suffices for one to be in a position to know that one is in it. In short, there are no “luminous” mental states. His argument depends on a “safety” requirement on knowledge, that one’s confident belief could not easily have been wrong if it is to count as knowledge. We argue that the safety requirement is ambiguous; on one (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   134 citations  
  • Vagueness without ignorance.Cian Dorr - 2003 - Philosophical Perspectives 17 (1):83–113.
    I motivate and briefly sketch a linguistic theory of vagueness, on which the notion of indeterminacy is understood in terms of the conventions of language: a sentence is indeterminate iff the conventions of language either forbid asserting it and forbid asserting its negation, under the circumstances, or permit asserting either. I then consider an objection that purports to show that if this theory (or, as far as I can see, any other theory of vagueness that deserved the label "linguistic" were (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • The impossibility of defining 'omnipotence'.Richard R. La Croix - 1977 - Philosophical Studies 32 (2):181-190.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Evil and omnipotence.J. L. Mackie - 1955 - Mind 64 (254):200-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   212 citations  
  • Oughts, options, and actualism.Frank Jackson & Robert Pargetter - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (2):233-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   180 citations  
  • Does conceivability entail possibility.David J. Chalmers - 2002 - In Tamar Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 145--200.
    There is a long tradition in philosophy of using a priori methods to draw conclusions about what is possible and what is necessary, and often in turn to draw conclusions about matters of substantive metaphysics. Arguments like this typically have three steps: first an epistemic claim , from there to a modal claim , and from there to a metaphysical claim.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   528 citations  
  • (1 other version)On the Plurality of Worlds.William G. Lycan - 1988 - Journal of Philosophy 85 (1):42-47.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   763 citations  
  • God and Other Minds.Alvin Plantinga - 1967 - Philosophy 44 (167):71-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • Can God Be Free?William L. Rowe - 2003 - Clarendon Press.
    Can God Be Free? is a penetrating study of a central problem in philosophy of religion: can it be right to regard God as free, and as praiseworthy for being perfectly good? Allowing that he has perfect knowledge and perfect goodness, if there is a best world for God to create he would have no choice other than to create it. But if God could not do otherwise than create the best world, he created the world of necessity, not freely, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Some suggestions for divine command theorists.William Alston - 1990 - In Michael D. Beaty (ed.), Christian Theism and the Problems of Philosophy. University of Notre Dame Press. pp. 303--326.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • The Nature of Necessity. [REVIEW]Michael Corrado - 1975 - International Philosophical Quarterly 15 (2):231-234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Real Problem of No Best World.Daniel Howard-Snyder & Frances Howard-Snyder - 1996 - Faith and Philosophy 13 (3):422-425.
    This is a reply to William Rowe, "The Problem of No Best World," Faith and Philosophy (1994).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Evil and Van Inwagen.Jeff Jordan - 2003 - Faith and Philosophy 20 (2):236-239.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Island Universes and the Analysis of Modality.Phillip Bricker - 2001 - In Gerhard Preyer & Frank Siebelt (eds.), Reality and Humean Supervenience: Essays on the Philosophy of David Lewis. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    It follows from Humean principles of plenitude, I argue, that island universes are possible: physical reality might have 'absolutely isolated' parts. This makes trouble for Lewis's modal realism; but the realist has a way out. First, accept absolute actuality, which is defensible, I argue, on independent grounds. Second, revise the standard analysis of modality: modal operators are 'plural', not 'individual', quantifiers over possible worlds. This solves the problem of island universes and confers three additional benefits: an 'unqualified' principle of compossibility (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • The immorality of modal realism, or: How I learned to stop worrying and let the children drown.Mark Heller - 2003 - Philosophical Studies 114 (1-2):1 - 22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Infinite value and finitely additive value theory.Peter Vallentyne & Shelly Kagan - 1997 - Journal of Philosophy 94 (1):5-26.
    000000001. Introduction Call a theory of the good—be it moral or prudential—aggregative just in case (1) it recognizes local (or location-relative) goodness, and (2) the goodness of states of affairs is based on some aggregation of local goodness. The locations for local goodness might be points or regions in time, space, or space-time; or they might be people, or states of nature.1 Any method of aggregation is allowed: totaling, averaging, measuring the equality of the distribution, measuring the minimum, etc.. Call (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • How do you maximize expectation value?John L. Pollock - 1983 - Noûs 17 (3):409-421.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • God and possible worlds: The modal problem of evil.Theodore Guleserian - 1983 - Noûs 17 (2):221-238.
    Using four principles common to several theories about possible worlds, It is argued that the necessary existence of a divine being that is essentially omnipotent, Omniscient, And morally perfect is impossible. The central argument employs the premise that there are possible worlds that any divine being ought not to actualize (because of their evil contents). This premise is then defended on the grounds that the same sort of justification that we give for other modal statements that we accept can be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Evil and omnipotence.J. L. Mackie - 2004 - In Tim Crane & Katalin Farkas (eds.), Metaphysics: a guide and anthology. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • Logic and Theism: Arguments for and Against Beliefs in God.Jordan Howard Sobel - 2003 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Jordan Howard Sobel.
    This is a wide-ranging 2004 book about arguments for and against beliefs in God. The arguments for the belief are analysed in the first six chapters and include ontological arguments from Anselm to Gödel, the cosmological arguments of Aquinas and Leibniz, and arguments from evidence for design and miracles. The next two chapters consider arguments against belief. The last chapter examines Pascalian arguments for and against belief in God. There are discussions of Cantorian problems for omniscience, of challenges to divine (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Self torture and group beneficence.Frank Arntzenius & David McCarthy - 1997 - Erkenntnis 47 (1):129-144.
    Moral puzzles about actions which bring about very small or what are said to be imperceptible harms or benefits for each of a large number of people are well known. Less well known is an argument by Warren Quinn that standard theories of rationality can lead an agent to end up torturing himself or herself in a completely foreseeable way, and that this shows that standard theories of rationality need to be revised. We show where Quinn's argument goes wrong, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Gambling on God. [REVIEW]Joshua L. Golding - 1996 - Faith and Philosophy 13 (3):441-446.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How an Unsurpassable Being Can Create a Surpassable World.Daniel Howard-Snyder & Frances Howard-Snyder - 1994 - Faith and Philosophy 11 (2):260-268.
    Imagine that there exists a good, essentially omniscient and omnipotent being named Jove, and that there exists nothing else. No possible being is more powerful or knowledgable. Out of his goodness, Jove decides to create. Since he is all-powerful, there is nothing but the bounds of possibility to prevent him from getting what he wants. Unfortunately, as he holds before his mind the host of worlds, Jove sees that for each there is a better one. Although he can create any (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • A neglected family of aggregation problems in ethics.Krister Segerberg - 1976 - Noûs 10 (2):221-244.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • States of affairs again.Roderick M. Chisholm - 1971 - Noûs 5 (2):179-189.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • On The Plurality of Worlds.Graeme Forbes - 1988 - Philosophical Quarterly 38 (151):222-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   522 citations  
  • Utilitarian Eschatology.Mark T. Nelson - 1991 - American Philosophical Quarterly 28 (4):339-47.
    Traditional utilitarianism, when applied, implies a surprising prediction about the future, viz., that all experience of pleasure and pain must end once and for all, or infinitely dwindle. Not only is this implication surprising, it should render utilitarianism unacceptable to persons who hold any of the following theses: that evaluative propositions may not imply descriptive, factual propositions; that evaluative propositions may not imply contingent factual propositions about the future; that there will always exist beings who experience pleasure or pain.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Utilitarianism and infinite utility.Peter Vallentyne - 1993 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (2):212 – 217.
    Traditional act utilitarianism judges an action permissible just in case it produces as much aggregate utility as any alternative. It is often supposed that utilitarianism faces a serious problem if the future is infinitely long. For in that case, actions may produce an infinite amount of utility. And if that is so for most actions, then utilitarianism, it appears, loses most of its power to discriminate among actions. For, if most actions produce an infinite amount of utility, then few actions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Introduction.Thomas V. Morris - 1988 - In Divine and Human Action: Essays in the Metaphysics of Theism. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. pp. 1-10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Must God Create the Best Possible World?Bruce R. Reichenbach - 1979 - International Philosophical Quarterly 19 (2):203-212.
    I ARGUE THAT THE NOTION OF THE BEST POSSIBLE WORLD IS MEANINGLESS AND THEREFORE A CHIMERA, BECAUSE FOR ANY WORLD WHICH MIGHT BE SO DESIGNATED, THERE COULD ALWAYS BE ANOTHER WHICH WAS BETTER, EITHER IN BEING POPULATED BY BEINGS WITH BETTER OR A GREATER QUANTITY OF GOOD CHARACTERISTICS, OR ELSE BY BEING MORE OPTIMIFIC.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Providence, Evil and the Openness of God.William Hasker - 2004 - Routledge.
    _Providence, Evil and the Openness of God_ is a timely exploration of the philosophical implications of the rapidly-growing theological movement known as open theism, or the 'openness of God'. William Hasker, one of the philosophers prominently associated with this movement, presents the strengths of this position in comparison with its main competitors: Calvinism, process theism, and the theory of divine middle knowledge, or Molinism. The author develops alternative approaches to the problem of evil and to the problem of divine action (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • A Trilemma for Divine Command Theory.Mark C. Murphy - 2002 - Faith and Philosophy 19 (1):22-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The many-universes solution to the problem of evil.Donald Turner - 2003 - In Richard M. Gale & Alexander R. Pruss (eds.), The Existence of God. Ashgate Pub Limited.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Vagueness and the mind of God.John Hawthorne - 2005 - Philosophical Studies 122 (1):1 - 25.
    This paper examines the mind and language of an omniscient being from a supervaluationist perspective. Two questions hall receive special attention. How ought the supervaluationist explicate the concept of omniscience? And what ought the supervaluationist expect an omniscient speaker to say about a Sorites series?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The modal metaphysics of Alvin Plantinga.John Divers - 2007 - In Deane-Peter Baker (ed.), Alvin Plantinga. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Moral dilemmas, thought experiments, and conflict vagueness.Roy A. Sorensen - 1991 - Philosophical Studies 63 (3):291 - 308.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Basinger on Reichenbach and the Best Possible World.Bruce Reichenbach - 1980 - International Philosophical Quarterly 20 (3):343-345.
    I reply to David Basinger who, in an article printed in the same issue, develops objections to my original argument (IPQ XIX, 203-212) that it makes no sense to inquire whether God could create the best possible world since the concept of a best possible world is a meaningless notion. I argue that if the number of possible worlds is infinite, there cannot be an upper limit to this order, and without an upper limit, there can be no best possible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (5 other versions)Philosophical Explanations. [REVIEW]Robert Nozick - 1981 - Philosophy 58 (223):118-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   877 citations  
  • Evil and God's Freedom in Creation.William Rowe - 1999 - American Philosophical Quarterly 36 (2):101 - 113.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations