Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A Case for Song: Against an (Exclusively) Recording-Centered Ontology of Rock.Franklin Bruno - 2013 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 71 (1):65-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Experimental philosophy.Joshua Knobe - 2007 - The Philosophers' Magazine 50:72-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   198 citations  
  • Where Philosophical Intuitions Come From.Helen De Cruz - 2015 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93 (2):233-249.
    Little is known about the aetiology of philosophical intuitions, in spite of their central role in analytic philosophy. This paper provides a psychological account of the intuitions that underlie philosophical practice, with a focus on intuitions that underlie the method of cases. I argue that many philosophical intuitions originate from spontaneous, early-developing, cognitive processes that also play a role in other cognitive domains. Additionally, they have a skilled, practiced, component. Philosophers are expert elicitors of intuitions in the dialectical context of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Perfect Compliance in Musical History and Musical Ontology.John Dyck - 2014 - British Journal of Aesthetics 54 (1):31-47.
    There’s a common assumption that Western classical music performance essentially involves an ideal of perfect compliance: to perform a musical work, the performer must intend to play all of the notes in the score of that work, without deviating. Many accounts of musical ontology focus on Western classical music; consequently, they take this assumption to be fundamental to their accounts. However, recent musicological research reveals that this ideal is a relatively recent phenomenon, and doesn’t fit much paradigmatic classical music. I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Judging Covers.Cristyn Magnus, P. D. Magnus & Christy Mag Uidhir - 2013 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 71 (4):361-370.
    Cover versions form a loose but identifiable category of tracks and performances. We distinguish four kinds of covers and argue that they mark important differences in the modes of evaluation that are possible or appropriate for each: mimic covers, which aim merely to echo the canonical track; rendition covers, which change the sound of the canonical track; transformative covers, which diverge so much as to instantiate a distinct, albeit derivative song; and referential covers, which not only instantiate a distinct song, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Experimental Philosophy.Wesley Buckwalter, Joshua Knobe, Shaun Nichols, N. Ángel Pinillos, Philip Robbins, Hagop Sarkissian, Chris Weigel & Jonathan M. Weinberg - 2006 - Oxford Bibliographies Online (1):81-92.
    Bibliography of works in experimental philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   137 citations  
  • An experimental philosophy manifesto.Joshua Knobe & Shaun Nichols - 2008 - In Joshua Michael Knobe & Shaun Nichols (eds.), Experimental Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 3--14.
    It used to be a commonplace that the discipline of philosophy was deeply concerned with questions about the human condition. Philosophers thought about human beings and how their minds worked. They took an interest in reason and passion, culture and innate ideas, the origins of people’s moral and religious beliefs. On this traditional conception, it wasn’t particularly important to keep philosophy clearly distinct from psychology, history, or political science. Philosophers were concerned, in a very general way, with questions about how..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Normativity and epistemic intuitions.Jonathan M. Weinberg, Shaun Nichols & Stephen Stich - 2001 - Philosophical Topics, 29 (1-2):429-460.
    In this paper we propose to argue for two claims. The first is that a sizeable group of epistemological projects – a group which includes much of what has been done in epistemology in the analytic tradition – would be seriously undermined if one or more of a cluster of empirical hypotheses about epistemic intuitions turns out to be true. The basis for this claim will be set out in Section 2. The second claim is that, while the jury is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   531 citations  
  • How to challenge intuitions empirically without risking skepticism.Jonathan M. Weinberg - 2007 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31 (1):318–343.
    Using empirical evidence to attack intuitions can be epistemically dangerous, because various of the complaints that one might raise against them (e.g., that they are fallible; that we possess no non-circular defense of their reliability) can be raised just as easily against perception itself. But the opponents of intuition wish to challenge intuitions without at the same time challenging the rest of our epistemic apparatus. How might this be done? Let us use the term “hopefulness” to refer to the extent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   154 citations  
  • Musical ontology and the argument from creation.Stefano Predelli - 2001 - British Journal of Aesthetics 41 (3):279-292.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Making tracks: The ontology of rock music.Andrew Kania - 2006 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (4):401–414.
    I argue that the work of art in rock music is a track constructed in the studio, that tracks usually manifest songs, which can be performed live, and that a cover version is a track (successfully) intended to manifest the same song as some other track. This ontology reflects the way informed audiences talk about rock. It recognizes not only the centrality of recorded tracks to the tradition, as discussed by Theodore Gracyk, but also the value accorded to live performance (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Defending musical perdurantism.Ben Caplan & Carl Matheson - 2006 - British Journal of Aesthetics 46 (1):59-69.
    If musical works are abstract objects, which cannot enter into causal relations, then how can we refer to musical works or know anything about them? Worse, how can any of our musical experiences be experiences of musical works? It would be nice to be able to sidestep these questions altogether. One way to do that would be to take musical works to be concrete objects. In this paper, we defend a theory according to which musical works are concrete objects. In (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Art as Performance. [REVIEW]Kathleen Stock - 2005 - Philosophical Quarterly 55 (221):694-696.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  • Works and Worlds of Art.Nicholas Wolterstorff - 1983 - Mind 92 (366):306-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • Can a Musical Work Be Created?Ben Caplan & Carl Matheson - 2004 - British Journal of Aesthetics 44 (2):113-134.
    Can a musical work be created? Some say ‘no’. But, we argue, there is no handbook of universally accepted metaphysical truths that they can use to justify their answer. Others say ‘yes’. They have to find abstract objects that can plausibly be identified with musical works, show that abstract objects of this sort can be created, and show that such abstract objects can persist. But, we argue, none of the standard views about what a musical work is allows musical works (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Are musical works discovered?Renee Cox - 1985 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 43 (4):367-374.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Languages of Art.Nelson Goodman - 1970 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 3 (1):62-63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   631 citations  
  • (1 other version)Art as Performance. [REVIEW]A. Kania - 2005 - Mind 114 (453):137-141.
    A review of David Davies, _Art as Performance_ (Blackwell, 2004).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Meanings of Songs and Meanings of Song Performances.Theodore Gracyk - 2013 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 71 (1):23-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Against musical platonism.Stefano Predelli - 1995 - British Journal of Aesthetics 35 (4):338-350.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Musical works as eternal types.Julian Dodd - 2000 - British Journal of Aesthetics 40 (4):424-440.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Works and Worlds of Art.John G. Bennett - 1982 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 40 (4):431-433.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Art and Its Objects.Jeffrey Wieand - 1981 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 40 (1):91-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  • Works and Worlds of Art.Peter Lewis - 1982 - Philosophical Quarterly 32 (127):185-186.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations