Switch to: References

Citations of:

Languages of Art

Philosophy and Rhetoric 3 (1):62-63 (1970)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Benjamin, the Image and the End of History.Chiel van den Akker - 2016 - Journal of Aesthetics and Phenomenology 3 (1):43-54.
    In his famous 1936 essay “The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction” Walter Benjamin tells us that in his time art became valued for its exhibition value instead of what he refers to as its secularised ritual or cult value. This essay makes this bold claim plausible by arguing that it means that a historicising gaze no longer has a function in the reception of art. Although this argument is supported by Benjamin’s use of the concepts of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A cognitive theory of graphical and linguistic reasoning: Logic and implementation. Cognitive science.Keith Stenning & Jon Oberlander - 1995 - Cognitive Science 19 (1):97-140.
    We discuss external and internal graphical and linguistic representational systems. We argue that a cognitive theory of peoples' reasoning performance must account for (a) the logical equivalence of inferences expressed in graphical and linguistic form; and (b) the implementational differences that affect facility of inference. Our theory proposes that graphical representations limit abstraction and thereby aid processibility. We discuss the ideas of specificity and abstraction, and their cognitive relevance. Empirical support comes from tasks (i) involving and (ii) not involving the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Literary Indiscernibles, Referential Forgery, and the Possibility of Allographic Art.Jake Spinella - 2023 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 81 (3):306-316.
    Peter Lamarque, in chapter 4 of his 2010 book Work and Object, argues that certain artworks, like musical scores and literary texts, are such that there can be no forgeries of them that purport to be of an actually existing work—what Lamarque calls “referential forgeries”. Lamarque motivates this claim via appeal to another distinction, first made by Goodman, between “allographic” and “autographic” artworks. This article will evaluate Lamarque’s argument that allographic literary works are unable to be referentially forged and will (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophy of the Performing Arts. A book review. [REVIEW]Jakub Ryszard Matyja - 2014 - Avant: Trends in Interdisciplinary Studies (3):164-166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The psychology of perspective and renaissance art. [REVIEW]Michael Ann Holly - 1989 - History of European Ideas 10 (3):383-384.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The living academies of nature: scientific experiment in learning and communicating the new skills of early nineteenth-century landscape painting.Beryl Hartley - 1996 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 27 (2):149-180.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • E.-j. Marey's Visual Rhetoric And The Graphic Decomposition Of The Body.John W. Douard - 1995 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 26 (2):175-204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aesthetic Negativity and Aisthetic Traits.Jonathan Owen Clark - 2015 - Critical Horizons 16 (1):52-69.
    This article concerns the notion of aesthetic negativity, and related ideas regarding the autonomy of art. After giving some initial definitions and a brief historical sketch of these concepts, we will examine the definition proposed by arguably the greatest thinker of aesthetic negativity, Theodor Adorno, and its recent semiotic reconstruction in the work of Christoph Menke. This reconstruction configures aesthetic negativity and autonomy jointly as the capacity of artworks, and the experiences that they occasion; to processurally negate ‘‘automatic’’ modes of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Metaphor.Ted Cohen - 2003 - In Jerrold Levinson (ed.), The Oxford handbook of aesthetics. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 366-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Real space and represented space: Cross-cultural perspectives.J. B. Deregowski - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):51-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Unicultural psychologists in multicultural space.J. B. Deregowski - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):98-119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Discovery of Linear Perspective and its Limitations.Ton Derksen - 1999 - Philosophica 63 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A remark on the completeness of the computational model of mind.William Demopoulos - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):135-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • First-person Folk Psychology: Mindreading or Mindshaping?Leon De Bruin - 2016 - Studia Philosophica Estonica 9 (1):170-183.
    Proponents of mindshaping argue that third-person folk psychology is not primarily about "reading" mental states for the purpose of behavior prediction and explanation. Instead, they claim that third-person folk psychology is first and foremost a regulative practice -- one that "shapes" mental states in accordance with the norms of a shared folk psychological framework. This paper investigates to what extent the core assumptions behind the mindshaping hypothesis are compatible with an account of first-person folk psychology that is based on the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Images, depth cues, and cross-cultural differences in perception.R. H. Day - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):78-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Works, Texts, and Contexts: Goodman on the Literary Artwork.David Davies - 1991 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (3):331 - 345.
    We have seen that a musical score is in a notation and defines a work; that a sketch or picture is not in a notation but is itself a work; and that a literary script is both in a notation and is itself a work. Thus in the individual arts a work is differently localized. In painting, the work is an individual object; and in etching, a class of objects. In music, the work is the class of performances compliant with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Why One Shouldn't Make an Example of a Brain in a Vat.D. Davies - 1997 - Analysis 57 (1):51-59.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Works and performances in the performing arts.David Davies - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (5):744-755.
    The primary purpose of the performing arts is to prepare and present 'artistic performances', performances that either are themselves the appreciative focuses of works of art or are instances of other things that are works of art. In the latter case, we have performances of what may be termed 'performed works', as is generally taken to be so with performances of classical music and traditional theatrical performances. In the former case, we have what may be termed 'performance-works', as, for example, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Dance Seen and Dance‐Screened.David Davies - 2019 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 44 (1):117-132.
    Midwest Studies In Philosophy, EarlyView.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deduction by children and animals: Does it follow the Johnson-Laird & Byrne model?Hank Davis - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):344-344.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Derrida as philosopher.David Carrier - 1985 - Metaphilosophy 16 (2-3):221-234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Variations in pictorial culture.Arthur C. Danto - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):77-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Dramatic Performance.Charles B. Daniels - 1987 - Dialogue 26 (4):683-.
    What is the difference between a reading of a play and a performance of it? In both, the same text is uttered. Both may occur on stage. In both different people may recite the lines of different characters. But unlike a mere reading, in a performance of a play what happens on stage conforms to the text being pronounced.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A New Perceptual Adverbialism.Justin D'Ambrosio - 2019 - Journal of Philosophy 116 (8):413-446.
    In this paper, I develop and defend a new adverbial theory of perception. I first present a semantics for direct-object perceptual reports that treats their object positions as supplying adverbial modifiers, and I show how this semantics definitively solves the many-property problem for adverbialism. My solution is distinctive in that it articulates adverbialism from within a well-established formal semantic framework and ties adverbialism to a plausible semantics for perceptual reports in English. I then go on to present adverbialism as a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The Non-Arbitrary Link between Feeling and Value: A Psychosemantic Challenge for the Perceptual Theory of Emotion.Brian Scott Ballard - 2024 - Philosophies 9 (2):38.
    This essay raises a challenge for the perceptual theory of emotion. According to the perceptual theory, emotions are perceptual states that represent values. But if emotions represent values, something should explain why. In virtue of what do emotions represent the values they do? A psychosemantics would answer this, and that’s what the perceptual theorist owes us. To date, however, the only perceptual theorist to attempt a psychosemantics for emotion is Jesse Prinz. And Prinz’s theory, I argue, faces an important difficulty: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tractability considerations in deduction.James M. Crawford - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):343-343.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cross-cultural studies of visual illusions: The physiological confound.Stantley Coren - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):76-77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Modeling the mind's eye.Lynn A. Cooper - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):550-551.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Performances and arguments: Bruno Latour: The modern cult of the factish Gods. Durham and London: Duke University Press, 2010, x+157pp, $69.95 HB, $19.95 PB.Harry Collins - 2011 - Metascience 21 (2):409-418.
    Performances and arguments Content Type Journal Article Category Essay Review Pages 1-10 DOI 10.1007/s11016-011-9562-0 Authors Harry Collins, SOCSI, Cardiff University, Cardiff, CF10 3WT UK Journal Metascience Online ISSN 1467-9981 Print ISSN 0815-0796.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • From computational metaphor to consensual algorithms.Kenneth Mark Colby - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):134-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some difficulties about deduction.L. Jonathan Cohen - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):341-342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Formats of Cognitive Representation: A Computational Account.Dimitri Coelho Mollo & Alfredo Vernazzani - 2023 - Philosophy of Science.
    Cognitive representations are typically analysed in terms of content, vehicle and format. While current work on formats appeals to intuitions about external representations, such as words and maps, in this paper we develop a computational view of formats that does not rely on intuitions. In our view, formats are individuated by the computational profiles of vehicles, i.e., the set of constraints that fix the computational transformations vehicles can undergo. The resulting picture is strongly pluralistic, it makes space for a variety (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Three varieties of visual field.Austen Clark - 1996 - Philosophical Psychology 9 (4):477-95.
    The goal of this paper is to challenge the rather insouciant attitude that many investigators seem to adopt when they go about describing the items and events in their " visual fields". There are at least three distinct categories of interpretation of what these reports might mean, and only under one of those categories do those reports have anything resembling an observational character. The others demand substantive revisions in one's beliefs about what one sees. The ur-concept of a " visual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Compositionality and constituent structure in the analogue mind.Sam Clarke - 2023 - Philosophical Perspectives 37 (1):90-118.
    I argue that analogue mental representations possess a canonical decomposition into privileged constituents from which they compose. I motivate this suggestion, and rebut arguments to the contrary, through reflection on the approximate number system, whose representations are widely expected to have an analogue format. I then argue that arguments for the compositionality and constituent structure of these analogue representations generalize to other analogue mental representations posited in the human mind, such as those in early vision and visual imagery.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Plasticity: conceptual and neuronal.Paul M. Churchland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):133-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Neuroscience and psychology: should the labor be divided?Patricia Smith Churchland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):133-133.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From Problems to Structures: the Cousin Problems and the Emergence of the Sheaf Concept.Renaud Chorlay - 2009 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 64 (1):1-73.
    Historical work on the emergence of sheaf theory has mainly concentrated on the topological origins of sheaf cohomology in the period from 1945 to 1950 and on subsequent developments. However, a shift of emphasis both in time-scale and disciplinary context can help gain new insight into the emergence of the sheaf concept. This paper concentrates on Henri Cartan’s work in the theory of analytic functions of several complex variables and the strikingly different roles it played at two stages of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Visual Experience: Cognitive Penetrability and Indeterminacy.Alon Chasid - 2014 - Acta Analytica 29 (1):119-130.
    This paper discusses a counterexample to the thesis that visual experience is cognitively impenetrable. My central claim is that sometimes visual experience is influenced by the perceiver’s beliefs, rendering her experience’s representational content indeterminate. After discussing other examples of cognitive penetrability, I focus on a certain kind of visual experience— that is, an experience that occurs under radically nonstandard conditions—and show that it may have indeterminate content, particularly with respect to low-level properties such as colors and shapes. I then explain (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mental models and nonmonotonic reasoning.Nick Chater - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):340-341.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Imaginatively‐Colored Perception: Walton on Pictorial Experience.Alon Chasid - 2016 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 54 (1):27-47.
    This paper develops Kendall Walton's account of pictorial experience. Walton argues that the key feature of that experience is that it is imaginatively-penetrated experience. I argue that this idea, as put forward by Walton, has various shortcomings. After discussing these limitations, I suggest, on the basis of a more general phenomenon of cognitive penetration, a refinement of Walton's account. I then show how the revised account explains various features of pictorial experience. Specifically, I show that, given the manner in which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Feeling and representing: Computational theory and the modularity of affect.Louis C. Charland - 1995 - Synthese 105 (3):273-301.
    In this paper I review some leading developments in the empirical theory of affect. I argue that (1) affect is a distinct perceptual representation governed system, and (2) that there are significant modular factors in affect. The paper concludes with the observation thatfeeler (affective perceptual system) may be a natural kind within cognitive science. The main purpose of the paper is to explore some hitherto unappreciated connections between the theory of affect and the computational theory of mind.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Emotion as a natural kind: Towards a computational foundation for emotion theory.Louis C. Charland - 1995 - Philosophical Psychology 8 (1):59-84.
    In this paper I link two hitherto disconnected sets of results in the philosophy of emotions and explore their implications for the computational theory of mind. The argument of the paper is that, for just the same reasons that some computationalists have thought that cognition may be a natural kind, so the same can plausibly be argued of emotion. The core of the argument is that emotions are a representation-governed phenomenon and that the explanation of how they figure in behaviour (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Content-Free Pictorial Realism.Alon Chasid - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 135 (3):375-405.
    What is it for a picture to be more realistic, or more depictive, than another? Without committing to any thesis as to what depiction consists in, I show that degrees of depictiveness are grounded in a certain relation between two basic kinds of differences between pictures: configurational differences and content differences. A picture is thus more depictive just in case it is seen as having fewer nondepictive features, whereas a nondepictive feature is individuated through the susceptibility of the picture's configuration (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Aesthetics and the Problem of Evil.Charles Nussbaum - 2003 - Metaphilosophy 34 (3):250-283.
    Abstract:Much of Western speculative metaphysics has subscribed to what has been called “explanatory rationalism,” which holds that there is a reason for everything that is and for the way everything is. Theodicies, or metaphysical attempts to solve the problem of evil, have relied on a special application of this principle of explanatory rationalism, namely, the principle of plenitude, which holds that the evil in the world is a necessary ingredient in the world's overall perfection or degree of reality. This essay (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The nature of representation and the experience of oneself: A critical notice on Gottfried Vosgerau's Mental Representation and Self-Consciousness.Glenn Carruthers - 2011 - Philosophical Psychology 24 (3):411 - 425.
    Philosophical Psychology, Volume 24, Issue 3, Page 411-425, 01Jun2011.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is pictorial space “perceived” as real space?Josiane Caron-Pargue - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):75-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thinking with maps.Elisabeth Camp - 2007 - Philosophical Perspectives 21 (1):145–182.
    Most of us create and use a panoply of non-sentential representations throughout our ordinary lives: we regularly use maps to navigate, charts to keep track of complex patterns of data, and diagrams to visualize logical and causal relations among states of affairs. But philosophers typically pay little attention to such representations, focusing almost exclusively on language instead. In particular, when theorizing about the mind, many philosophers assume that there is a very tight mapping between language and thought. Some analyze utterances (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • Metaphor and that certain 'je ne sais quoi'.Elisabeth Camp - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 129 (1):1 - 25.
    Philosophers have traditionally inclined toward one of two opposite extremes when it comes to metaphor. On the one hand, partisans of metaphor have tended to believe that metaphors do something different in kind from literal utterances; it is a ‘heresy’, they think, either to deny that what metaphors do is genuinely cognitive, or to assume that it can be translated into literal terms. On the other hand, analytic philosophers have typically denied just this: they tend to assume that if metaphors (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • “Semantic procedure” is an oxymoron.Alan Bundy - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):339-340.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Art and Science: A Philosophical Sketch of Their Historical Complexity and Codependence.Nicolas J. Bullot, William P. Seeley & Stephen Davies - 2017 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 75 (4):453-463.
    To analyze the relations between art and science, philosophers and historians have developed different lines of inquiry. A first type of inquiry considers how artistic and scientific practices have interacted over human history. Another project aims to determine the contributions that scientific research can make to our understanding of art, including the contributions that cognitive science can make to philosophical questions about the nature of art. We rely on contributions made to these projects in order to demonstrate that art and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations