Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. La logique symbolique en débat à Oxford à la fin du XIXe siècle : les disputes logiques de Lewis Carroll et John Cook Wilson.Mathieu Marion & Amirouche Moktefi - 2014 - Revue D’Histoire des Sciences 67 (2):185-205.
    The development of symbolic logic is often presented in terms of a cumulative story of consecutive innovations that led to what is known as modern logic. This narrative hides the difficulties that this new logic faced at first, which shaped its history. Indeed, negative reactions to the emergence of the new logic in the second half of the nineteenth century were numerous and we study here one case, namely logic at Oxford, where one finds Lewis Carroll, a mathematical teacher who (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On the social utility of symbolic logic: Lewis Carroll against ‘The Logicians’.Amirouche Moktefi - 2015 - Studia Metodologiczne 35:133-150.
    Symbolic logic faced great difficulties in its early stage of development in order to acquire recognition of its utility for the needs of science and society. The aim of this paper is to discuss an early attempt by the British logician Lewis Carroll (1832–1898) to promote symbolic logic as a social good. This examination is achieved in three phases: first, Carroll’s belief in the social utility of logic, broadly understood, is demonstrated by his numerous interventions to fight fallacious reasoning in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Critical notices.J. Venn - 1884 - Mind 9 (34):301-304.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Logic of Relatives.Charles S. Peirce - 1897 - The Monist 7 (2):161-217.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Oh the Algebra of Logic.C. S. Peirce - 1880 - American Journal of Mathematics 3 (1):15-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Begriffsschrift.Gottlob Frege - 1967 - In Jean Van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel. Cambridge,: Harvard University Press. pp. 1-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   158 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Principia mathematica.A. N. Whitehead & B. Russell - 1910-1913 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 19 (2):19-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   239 citations  
  • (1 other version)Peirce's axioms for propositional calculus.A. N. Prior - 1958 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 23 (2):135-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Existential graphs as an instrument of logical analysis: Part I. alpha.Francesco Bellucci & Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen - 2016 - Review of Symbolic Logic 9 (2):209-237.
    Peirce considered the principal business of logic to be the analysis of reasoning. He argued that the diagrammatic system of Existential Graphs, which he had invented in 1896, carries the logical analysis of reasoning to the furthest point possible. The present paper investigates the analytic virtues of the Alpha part of the system, which corresponds to the sentential calculus. We examine Peirce’s proposal that the relation of illation is the primitive relation of logic and defend the view that this idea (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Christine Ladd-Franklin's and Victoria Welby's correspondence with Charles Peirce.Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen - 2013 - Semiotica 2013 (196):139-161.
    Journal Name: Semiotica - Journal of the International Association for Semiotic Studies / Revue de l'Association Internationale de Sémiotique Volume: 2013 Issue: 196 Pages: 139-161.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Symbolic reasoning.Hugh MacColl - 1897 - Mind 6 (24):493-510.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • J. N. Keynes, Studies and Exercises in Formal Logic. [REVIEW]J. Venn - 1884 - Mind 9:301.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Significs and the Origins of Analytic Philosophy.Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen - 2009 - Journal of the History of Ideas 70 (3):467-490.
    In this article I bring to light a group of scientific and philosophical ideas and intellectual currents from the early era of the significs movement, contemporaneous with the origins of early analytic philosophy. Significs was a strong candidate for the science of language, meaning, and communication during the new century. Its heyday coincided with the forums of the Vienna Circle, yet its intellectual and cultural climate persisted until fading in the turmoil of the mid-century's analytic thought.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On Frege’s Begriffsschrift Notation for Propositional Logic: Design Principles and Trade-Offs.Dirk Schlimm - 2017 - History and Philosophy of Logic 39 (1):53-79.
    Well over a century after its introduction, Frege's two-dimensional Begriffsschrift notation is still considered mainly a curiosity that stands out more for its clumsiness than anything else. This paper focuses mainly on the propositional fragment of the Begriffsschrift, because it embodies the characteristic features that distinguish it from other expressively equivalent notations. In the first part, I argue for the perspicuity and readability of the Begriffsschrift by discussing several idiosyncrasies of the notation, which allow an easy conversion of logically equivalent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • (1 other version)Prolegomena to an Apology for Pragmaticism.Charles S. Peirce - 1906 - The Monist 16 (4):492-546.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Exploring the beta quadrant.Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen - 2015 - Synthese 192 (4):941-970.
    The theory of existential graphs, which Peirce ultimately divided into four quadrants , is a rich method of analysis in the philosophy of logic. Its $$\upbeta $$ β -part boasts a diagrammatic theory of quantification, which by 1902 Peirce had used in the logical analysis of natural-language expressions such as complex donkey-type anaphora, quantificational patterns describing new mathematical concepts, and cognitive information processing. In the $$\upbeta $$ β -quadrant, he came close to inventing independence-friendly logic, the idea of which he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • No scope for scope?Jaakko Hintikka - 1997 - Linguistics and Philosophy 20 (5):515-544.
    The notion of scope as it relates to a model of logical form is discussed. The inability of the accepted definition of scope to account for the contrast between priority scope - the logical priority of different quantifiers & other logical notions via rule ordering - & binding scope - the identification of the connection between variables of quantification & a particular quantifier - is demonstrated. The semantic ambiguity of this dichotomy of scope is explored via examination of donkey sentences. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • From Mitchell to Carus: Fourteen Years of Logical Graphs in the Making.Francesco Bellucci & Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen - 2016 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 52 (4):539.
    It is well-known that by 1882, Peirce, influenced by Cayley’s, Clifford’s and Sylvester’s works on algebraic invariants and by the chemical analogy, had already achieved something like a diagrammatic treatment of quantificational logic of relatives. The details of that discovery and its implications to some wider issues in logical theory merit further investigation, however. This paper provides a reconstruction of the genesis of Peirce’s logical graphs from the early 1880s until 1896, covering the period of time during which he already (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Charles S. Peirce and the Medieval Doctrine of consequentiae.Francesco Bellucci - 2016 - History and Philosophy of Logic 37 (3):244-268.
    In 1898 C. S. Peirce declares that the medieval doctrine of consequences had been the starting point of his logical investigations in the 1860s. This paper shows that Peirce studied the scholastic theory of consequentiae as early as 1866–67, that he adopted the scholastics’ terminology, and that that theory constituted a source of logical doctrine that sustained Peirce for a lifetime of creative and original work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy.Gottlob Frege - 1991 - Wiley-Blackwell. Edited by Brian McGuinness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   172 citations  
  • Peirce’s Propositional Logic.Randall R. Dipert - 1981 - Review of Metaphysics 34 (3):569 - 595.
    BEFORE Frege’s Begriffsschrift, propositional logic was submerged in the often murky theory of the "hypothetical syllogism." With the exception of the Stoa, a handful of astute mediaeval logicians, Leibniz, and Bolzano, one might well obtain the impression from studying the history of logic that Frege created his theory ex nihilo—which is substantially true, since Frege was apparently little influenced by previous work. One might also obtain the impression, especially by reading Frege himself, that very little was being done on propositional (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Combinatory Logic.Haskell B. Curry, J. Roger Hindley & Jonathan P. Seldin - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (1):109-110.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Schönfinkel-type Operators for Classical Logic.Katalin Bimbó - 2010 - Studia Logica 95 (3):355-378.
    We briefly overview some of the historical landmarks on the path leading to the reduction of the number of logical connectives in classical logic. Relying on the duality inherent in Boolean algebras, we introduce a new operator ( Nallor ) that is the dual of Schönfinkel’s operator. We outline the proof that this operator by itself is sufficient to define all the connectives and operators of classical first-order logic ( Fol ). Having scrutinized the proof, we pinpoint the theorems of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy. [REVIEW]P. Cortois - 1988 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 50 (3):558-559.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Nachgelassene Schriften und wissenschaftlicher Briefwechsel.Gottlob Frege - 1983
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • III.—Symbolic reasoning.Hugh Maccoll - 1897 - Mind 6 (4):493-510.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Sense and reference in Frege's logic.Christian Thiel - 1968 - Dordrecht,: D. Reidel.
    The present study of sense and reference in the logic of Frege represents the first fruits of several years of dealing with the work of this great German logician. In the preparation of this work, which was presented as a dissertation to the Faculty of Philosophy of the Friedrich-Alexander University in Erlangen/Nuremberg, assistance came from many quarters. lowe most to Professor R. Zocher, who directed this dissertation with understanding counsel and unflagging interest. I must also thank Professor P. Lorenzen, whose (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Frege - Begriffschrift, eine der Arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens. [REVIEW]Paul Tannery - 1879 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 8:108-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   239 citations  
  • Posthumous Writings by Gottlob Frege, Peter Long, Roger White. [REVIEW]Stanley Rosen - 1981 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 14 (3):196-197.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • (1 other version)An Investigation of the Laws of Thought.George Boole - 1854 - [New York]: Dover Publications.
    AN INVESTIGATION OF THE LAWS OF THOUGHT. CHAPTER I. NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS WORK. . HPHE design of the following treatise is to investigate the ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • Studies and Exercises in Formal Logic. [REVIEW]A. Cornelius Benjamin - 1930 - Journal of Philosophy 27 (6):161-164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Hugh MacColl and the German algebra of logic.Volker Peckhaus - 1998 - Nordic Journal of Philosophical Logic 3:17-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Peano. Life and Works of Giuseppe Peano.Hubert C. Kennedy - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (2):503-504.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • [Omnibus Review].Robert Feys - 1956 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 21 (4):374-377.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Peirce’s Triadic Logic Revisited.Robert Lane - 1999 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 35 (2):284 - 311.
    This is a discussion of a three-valued logic in Peirce's writings.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Symbolic Reasoning.H. Maccoll - 1905 - Mind 14:390.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • "Logica ideografica", I.Alessandro Padoa - 1933 - Rivista di Filosofia Neo-Scolastica 25:75.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations