Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Conceptual role semantics for moral terms.Ralph Wedgwood - 2001 - Philosophical Review 110 (1):1-30.
    This paper outlines a new approach to the task of giving an account of the meaning of moral statements: a sort of "conceptual role semantics", according to which the meaning of moral terms is given by their role in practical reasoning. This role is sufficient both to distinguish the meaning of any moral term from that of other terms, and to determine the property or relation (if any) that the term stands for. The paper ends by suggesting reasons for regarding (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • What was classical genetics?C. Kenneth Waters - 2004 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 35 (4):783-809.
    I present an account of classical genetics to challenge theory-biased approaches in the philosophy of science. Philosophers typically assume that scientific knowledge is ultimately structured by explanatory reasoning and that research programs in well-established sciences are organized around efforts to fill out a central theory and extend its explanatory range. In the case of classical genetics, philosophers assume that the knowledge was structured by T. H. Morgan’s theory of transmission and that research throughout the later 1920s, 30s, and 40s was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Genes made molecular.C. Kenneth Waters - 1994 - Philosophy of Science 61 (2):163-185.
    This paper investigates what molecular biology has done for our understanding of the gene. I base a new account of the gene concept of classical genetics on the classical dogma that gene differences cause phenotypic differences. Although contemporary biologists often think of genes in terms of this concept, molecular biology provides a second way to understand genes. I clarify this second way by articulating a molecular gene concept. This concept unifies our understanding of the molecular basis of a wide variety (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • On a semantic argument against conceptual role semantics.Ted A. Warfield - 1993 - Analysis 53 (4):298-304.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Heroic antireductionism and genetics: A tale of one science.Russell E. Vance - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (3):45.
    In this paper I provide a novel argument against the claim that classical genetics is being reduced to molecular genetics. Specifically, I demonstrate that reductionists must subscribe to the unargued and problematic thesis that molecular genetics is 'independent' of classical genetics. I also argue that several standard antireductionist positions can be faulted for unnecessarily conceding the Independence Thesis to the reductionists. In place of a 'tale of two sciences', I offer a 'heroic' stance that denies classical genetics is being reduced, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The anti-essential Locke and natural kinds.W. L. Uzgalis - 1988 - Philosophical Quarterly 38 (152):330-339.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Can Things of Different Natural Kinds Be Exactly Alike?John Tienson - 1977 - Analysis 37 (4):190 - 197.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Natural Kinds.T. E. Wilkerson - 1988 - Philosophy 63 (243):29 - 42.
    What is a natural kind? As we shall see, the concept of a natural kind has a long history. Many of the interesting doctrines can be detected in Aristotle, were revived by Locke and Leibniz, and have again become fashionable in recent years. Equally there has been agreement about certain paradigm examples: the kinds oak, stickleback and gold are natural kinds, and the kinds table, nation and banknote are not. Sadly agreement does not extend much further. It is impossible to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Synthesizing activities and interactions in the concept of a mechanism.James G. Tabery - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (1):1-15.
    Stuart Glennan, and the team of Peter Machamer, Lindley Darden, and Carl Craver have recently provided two accounts of the concept of a mechanism. The main difference between these two versions rests on how the behavior of the parts of the mechanism is conceptualized. Glennan considers mechanisms to be an interaction of parts, where the interaction between parts can be characterized by direct, invariant, change-relating generalizations. Machamer, Darden, and Craver criticize traditional conceptualizations of mechanisms which are based solely on parts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Conceptual Differences Between Children and Adults.Susan Carey - 1988 - Mind and Language 3 (3):167-181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   140 citations  
  • The Developmental Genetic Toolkit and the Molecular Homology—Analogy Paradox.Stuart A. Newman - 2006 - Biological Theory 1 (1):12-16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Ancient genomes, wise bodies, unhealthy people: limits of a genetic paradigm in biology and medicine.Richard C. Strohman - 1993 - Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 37 (1):112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • How biologists conceptualize genes: an empirical study.Karola Stotz, Paul E. Griffiths & Rob Knight - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 35 (4):647-673.
    Philosophers and historians of biology have argued that genes are conceptualized differently in different fields of biology and that these differences influence both the conduct of research and the interpretation of research by audiences outside the field in which the research was conducted. In this paper we report the results of a questionnaire study of how genes are conceptualized by biological scientists at the University of Sydney, Australia. The results provide tentative support for some hypotheses about conceptual differences between different (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Theory theory to the Max.Stephen Stich & Shaun Nichols - 1998 - Mind and Language 13 (3):421-449.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief.Stephen Stich - 1982 - In a Woodfield (ed.), Philosophical Review. MIT Press. pp. 418-421.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   159 citations  
  • Development, evolution, and adaptation.Kim Sterelny - 2000 - Philosophy of Science 67 (3):387.
    In this paper I develop three conceptions of the relationship between evolutionary and developmental biology. I further argue that: (a) the choice between them largely turns on as yet unresolved empirical considerations; (b) none of these conceptions demand a fundamental conceptual reevaluation of evolutionary biology; and (c) while developmental systems theorists have constructed an important and innovative alternative to the standard view of the genotype/phenotype relations, in considering the general issue of the relationship between evolutionary and developmental biology, we can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Refining the causal theory of reference for natural kind terms.P. Kyle Stanford & Philip Kitcher - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 97 (1):97-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Reference and necessity.Robert Stalnaker - 1997 - In Bob Hale & Crispin Wright (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Language. Chichester, UK: Blackwell. pp. 902–919.
    This chapter aims to resolve some of Nathan Salmon's puzzlement by clarifying the relationship between theses and questions about reference and theses and questions about necessity and possibility. It argues that while Saul Kripke defends metaphysical theses about the descriptive semantics of names, the way the reference relation is determined, and the capacities and dispositions of human beings and physical objects, his most important philosophical accomplishment is in the way he posed and clarified the questions, and not in the particular (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • For pluralism and against realism about species.P. Kyle Stanford - 1995 - Philosophy of Science 62 (1):70-91.
    I argue for accepting a pluralist approach to species, while rejecting the realism about species espoused by P. Kitcher and a number of other philosophers of biology. I develop an alternative view of species concepts as divisions of organisms into groups for study which are relative to the systematic explanatory interests of biologists at a particular time. I also show how this conception resolves a number of difficult puzzles which plague the application of particular species concepts.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Commentary on Alison Gopnik's "the scientist as child".Miriam Solomon - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (4):547-551.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The nature of selection: evolutionary theory in philosophical focus.Elliott Sober - 1984 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    The Nature of Selection is a straightforward, self-contained introduction to philosophical and biological problems in evolutionary theory. It presents a powerful analysis of the evolutionary concepts of natural selection, fitness, and adaptation and clarifies controversial issues concerning altruism, group selection, and the idea that organisms are survival machines built for the good of the genes that inhabit them. "Sober's is the answering philosophical voice, the voice of a first-rate philosopher and a knowledgeable student of contemporary evolutionary theory. His book merits (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   748 citations  
  • Three distinctions about concepts and categorization.Edward E. Smith - 1989 - Mind and Language 4 (1-2):57-61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Meaning holism and intentional content.Arnold Silverberg - 1994 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 75 (1):29-53.
    In this essay I defend meaning holism against certain criticisms that Jerry Fodor has presented against it. In "Psychosemantics" he argued that meaning holism is incompatible with the development of scientific psychology given the ways in which scientific psychology adverts to intentional content. In his recent book "Holism" (co-authored with Ernest Lepore) he indicates that he still upholds this argument. I argue that Fodor's argument fails, and argue in favor of the compatibility of meaning holism with scientific psychology. I also (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reason, reference, and the Quest for knowledge.Dudley Shapere - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (1):1-23.
    This paper examines the "causal theory of reference", according to which science aims at the discovery of "essences" which are the objects of reference of natural kind terms (among others). This theory has been advanced as an alternative to traditional views of "meaning", on which a number of philosophical accounts of science have relied, and which have been criticized earlier by the present author. However, this newer theory of reference is shown to be equally subject to fatal internal difficulties, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Evolution and continuity in scientific change.Dudley Shapere - 1989 - Philosophy of Science 56 (3):419-437.
    The alleged problem of "incommensurability" is examined, and attempts to explain scientific change in terms of concepts of meaning and reference are analyzed and rejected. A way of understanding scientific change through a properly developed concept of "reasons" is presented, and the issues of reasons, meaning, and reference are placed in the context of this broader interpretation of scientific change.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Some Reflections on Language Games.Wilfrid Sellars - 1957 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 22 (4):402-403.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   116 citations  
  • Some reflections on language games.Wilfrid Sellars - 1954 - Philosophy of Science 21 (3):204-228.
    1. It seems plausible to say that a language is a system of expressions the use of which is subject to certain rules. It would seem, thus, that learning to use a language is learning to obey the rules for the use of its expressions. However, taken as it stands, this thesis is subject to an obvious and devastating refutation. After formulating this refutation, I shall turn to the constructive task of attempting to restate the thesis in a way which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   187 citations  
  • Meaning as functional classification.Wilfrid Sellars - 1974 - Synthese 27 (3-4):417 - 437.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   134 citations  
  • Language as thought and as communication.Wilfrid Sellars - 1969 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 29 (4):506-527.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   104 citations  
  • Language as Thought and as Communication.Wilfrid Sellars - 2011 - In Robert B. Talisse & Scott F. Aikin (eds.), The Pragmatism Reader: From Peirce Through the Present. Princeton University Press. pp. 265-285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Inference and meaning.Wilfrid Sellars - 1953 - Mind 62 (247):313-338.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   178 citations  
  • Inference and Meaning.Wilfrid Sellars - 1956 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 21 (2):203-204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • Concepts as Involving Laws and Inconceivable Without Them.Wilfrid Sellars - 1949 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 14 (1):59-60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Concepts as involving laws and inconceivable without them.Wilfrid Sellars - 1948 - Philosophy of Science 15 (October):287-313.
    Formal implication is usually represented by symbolization such as ‘ φx ⊃ Ψx,’ which may be read, “for all values of ‘x’, φx implies Ψx.” If the values of the variable ‘x’, in ‘φx’ and ‘Ψx’ be ‘x1’ ‘x2’ ‘x3’, etc., then … ‘φx’ formally implies ‘Ψx’ if and only if, whatever values of ‘x’, ‘xn’, be chosen, ‘φxn’ materially implies ‘Ψxn’ …However, this still leaves it doubtful which of two possible interpretations of expressions having the form ‘ φx ⊃ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • A Slim Book About Narrow Content.Gabriel Segal - 2000 - MIT Press.
    The book, written in a clear, engaging style, contains four chapters.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • The Watson-Crick model and reductionism.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1969 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 20 (4):325-348.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • The peripherality of reductionism in the development of molecular biology.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1974 - Journal of the History of Biology 7 (1):111-139.
    I have not attempted to provide here an analysis of the methodology of molecular biology or molecular genetics which would demonstrate at what specific points a more reductionist aim would make sense as a research strategy. This, I believe, would require a much deeper analysis of scientific growth than philosophy of science has been able to provide thus far. What I have tried to show is that a straightforward reductionist strategy cannot be said to be follwed in important cases of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Theories and explanations in biology.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1969 - Journal of the History of Biology 2 (1):19-33.
    It seems that the above account of explanation-strategy in the area of temperature adaptation underscores many of the points made earlier. First, it discloses the fruitful interaction of classical, evolutionary, and molecular approaches. Secondly, it indicates that biological characterizations are not rival accounts to chemical ones. Thirdly, it stresses the importance of the DNA sequence order in chemical explanations of biological organisms.One feature which this area does not seem to reveal, which genetics does, is the development of a biological (that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Logic of discovery and justification in regulatory genetics.Kenneth Schaffner - 1974 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 4 (4):349-385.
    In the above pages I have sketched a history of the genesis and comparative evaluation of the repressor model of genetic regulation of enzyme induction. I have not attempted in this article to carry out an analysis of the more scientifically interesting fully developed Jacob-Monod operon theory of genetic regulations but such an analysis of the operon theory would not, I believe, involve any additional logical or epistemological features than have been discussed above. I have argued that the above account (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Approaches to reduction.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1967 - Philosophy of Science 34 (2):137-147.
    Four current accounts of theory reduction are presented, first informally and then formally: (1) an account of direct theory reduction that is based on the contributions of Nagel, Woodger, and Quine, (2) an indirect reduction paradigm due to Kemeny and Oppenheim, (3) an "isomorphic model" schema traceable to Suppes, and (4) a theory of reduction that is based on the work of Popper, Feyerabend, and Kuhn. Reference is made, in an attempt to choose between these schemas, to the explanation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   228 citations  
  • Criteria of identity and the individuation of natural-kind events.Elias E. Savellos - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (4):807-831.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Models of reduction and categories of reductionism.Sahotra Sarkar - 1992 - Synthese 91 (3):167-94.
    A classification of models of reduction into three categories — theory reductionism, explanatory reductionism, and constitutive reductionism — is presented. It is shown that this classification helps clarify the relations between various explications of reduction that have been offered in the past, especially if a distinction is maintained between the various epistemological and ontological issues that arise. A relatively new model of explanatory reduction, one that emphasizes that reduction is the explanation of a whole in terms of its parts is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Information in genetics and developmental biology: Comments on Maynard Smith.Sahotra Sarkar - 2000 - Philosophy of Science 67 (2):208-213.
    Maynard Smith notes that he provides a natural history and not a philosophical analysis of the use of concepts of information in contemporary biology. Just a natural history, however rich, would do little to resolve the ongoing controversy about the role of these concepts in biology. None of the disputants deny that the biological use of these concepts is pervasive. The dispute is about whether these concepts—and the framework in which they are embedded—continue to be of explanatory value in contemporary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Logic.Wesley C. Salmon - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (1):107-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Two Biological Revolutions.Michael E. Ruse - 1971 - Dialectica 25 (1):17-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Reduction, Replacement, and Molecular Biology.Michael E. Ruse - 1971 - Dialectica 25 (1):39-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Richard Owen's Vertebrate Archetype.Nicholas Rupke - 1993 - Isis 84:231-251.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Reductionism redux: Computing the embryo. [REVIEW]Alex Rosenberg - 1997 - Biology and Philosophy 12 (4):445-470.
    This paper argues that the consensus physicalist antireductionism in the philosophy of biology cannot accommodate the research strategy or indeed the recent findings of molecular developmental biology. After describing Wolperts programmatic claims on its behalf, and recent work by Gehring and others to identify the molecular determinants of development, the paper attempts to identify the relationship between evolutionary and developmental biology by reconciling two apparently conflicting accounts of bio-function – Wrights and Nagels (as elaborated by Cummins). Finally, the paper seeks (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • How to Blunt the Sword of compositionality.Philip Robbins - 2002 - Noûs 36 (2):313-334.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • How developmental is evolutionary developmental biology?Jason Scott Robert - 2002 - Biology and Philosophy 17 (5):591-611.
    Evolutionary developmental biology (evo-devo) offers both an account of developmental processes and also new integrative frameworks for analyzing interactions between development and evolution. Biologists and philosophers are keen on evo-devo in part because it appears to offer a comfort zone between, on the one hand, what some take to be the relative inability of mainstream evolutionary biology to integrate a developmental perspective; and, on the other hand, what some take to be more intractable syntheses of development and evolution. In this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations