Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Directive Pictures.Dominic Mciver Lopes - 2004 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 62 (2):189–196.
    Pictures are principally descriptive. Advertising images highlight features of potential purchases; cartoons open portals to scenes in fictional worlds; snapshots in the family photo album remind us of our past selves and landmark events in our personal histories; works of pictorial art express thoughts or feelings about depicted scenes. In addition, pictures serve a directive or action-guiding function that, though not taken into account by theorists, deserves no less attention than their descriptive one. Theories of depiction and the appreciation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Ontological Relativity and Other Essays.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1969 - New York: Columbia University Press.
    This volume consists of the first of the John Dewey Lectures delivered under the auspices of Columbia University's Philosophy Department as well as other essays by the author. Intended to clarify the meaning of the philosophical doctrines propounded by Professor Quine in 'Word and Objects', the essays included herein both support and expand those doctrines.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   789 citations  
  • Inference to the Best Explanation.Peter Lipton - 1991 - London and New York: Routledge.
    How do we go about weighing evidence, testing hypotheses, and making inferences? According to the model of _Inference to the Best Explanation_, we work out what to infer from the evidence by thinking about what would actually explain that evidence, and we take the ability of a hypothesis to explain the evidence as a sign that the hypothesis is correct. In _Inference to the Best Explanation_, Peter Lipton gives this important and influential idea the development and assessment it deserves. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   428 citations  
  • (1 other version)Précis of Inference to the Best Explanation, 2 nd Edition.Peter Lipton - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (2):421-423.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   565 citations  
  • The irreducible historicality of the concept of art.Jerrold Levinson - 2002 - British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (4):367-379.
    In this short paper I begin by underlining the sense in which my intentional-historical theory of art, first proposed in 1979, attributes to art a certain irreducible historicality. I next defend the theory, in broad outline, against a number of objections that have been raised against it in the past ten years. I conclude with some remarks on the similarities and differences between ordinary artefact concepts and the concept of an artwork.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Book Review:The Poverty of Historicism. Karl R. Popper. [REVIEW]Leon J. Goldstein - 1957 - Ethics 68 (4):296-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • Psychology of the Arts.Hans Kreitler & Shulamith Kreitler - 1973 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 32 (1):123-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Explaining Explanation.Robert A. Wilson & Frank C. Keil - 2000 - In Frank C. Keil & Robert Andrew Wilson (eds.), Explanation and Cognition. MIT Press. pp. 1-18.
    It is not a particularly hard thing to want or seek explanations. In fact, explanations seem to be a large and natural part of our cognitive lives. Children ask why and how questions very early in development and seem genuinely to want some sort of answer, despite our often being poorly equipped to provide them at the appropriate level of sophistication and detail. We seek and receive explanations in every sphere of our adult lives, whether it be to understand why (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Person as scientist, person as moralist.Joshua Knobe - 2010 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33 (4):315.
    It has often been suggested that people’s ordinary capacities for understanding the world make use of much the same methods one might find in a formal scientific investigation. A series of recent experimental results offer a challenge to this widely-held view, suggesting that people’s moral judgments can actually influence the intuitions they hold both in folk psychology and in causal cognition. The present target article distinguishes two basic approaches to explaining such effects. One approach would be to say that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   181 citations  
  • Aesthetic Contextualism.Jerrold Levinson - 2007 - Postgraduate Journal of Aesthetics 4 (3):1-12.
    Let me begin with a quote: “The universal organum of philosophy—the ground stone of its entire architecture—is the philosophy of art.”1 This statement, made in 1800 by the German Idealist philosopher Friedrich Schelling, is rather striking, not only because of its grandiosity, but also because it contrasts with what the majority of contemporary philosophers would be prepared to say on the subject. There is nevertheless a grain of truth in the claim that there is a peculiar connection between art and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Recollection, fluency, and the explicit/implicit distinction in artificial grammar learning.Annette Kinder, David R. Shanks, Josephine Cock & Richard J. Tunney - 2003 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 132 (4):551.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind?David Premack & Guy Woodruff - 1978 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1 (4):515-526.
    An individual has a theory of mind if he imputes mental states to himself and others. A system of inferences of this kind is properly viewed as a theory because such states are not directly observable, and the system can be used to make predictions about the behavior of others. As to the mental states the chimpanzee may infer, consider those inferred by our own species, for example, purpose or intention, as well as knowledge, belief, thinking, doubt, guessing, pretending, liking, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   927 citations  
  • (1 other version)Emotional responses to music: The need to consider underlying mechanisms.Patrik N. Juslin & Daniel Västfjäll - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (5):559-575.
    Research indicates that people value music primarily because of the emotions it evokes. Yet, the notion of musical emotions remains controversial, and researchers have so far been unable to offer a satisfactory account of such emotions. We argue that the study of musical emotions has suffered from a neglect of underlying mechanisms. Specifically, researchers have studied musical emotions without regard to how they were evoked, or have assumed that the emotions must be based on the mechanism for emotion induction, a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  • Art, Value, and Philosophy.J. Levinson - 1996 - Mind 105 (420):667-682.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Realism, Anti-Foundationalism and the Enthusiasm for Natural Kinds.Richard Boyd - 1991 - Philosophical Studies 61 (1):127-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   387 citations  
  • Recreative Minds: Imagination in Philosophy and Psychology, by Gregory Currie and Ian Ravenscroft. [REVIEW]Christoph Hoerl - 2005 - Mind and Language 20 (5):559-564.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   134 citations  
  • The Social History of Art.Arnold Hauser & S. Godman - 1953 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 11 (3):265-265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The Early Music Revival: A History.Harry Haskell - 1991 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 49 (1):103-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Work of the Imagination.Tamar Szabó Gendler - 2002 - Mind 111 (442):414-418.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • The role of historical intuitions in children's and adults' naming of artifacts.Grant Gutheil, Paul Bloom, Nohemy Valderrama & Rebecca Freedman - 2004 - Cognition 91 (1):23-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Languages of Art.Nelson Goodman - 1970 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 3 (1):62-63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   634 citations  
  • (1 other version)Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts.Kendall L. WALTON - 1990 - Philosophy 66 (258):527-529.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   403 citations  
  • After the End of Art: Contemporary Art and the Pale of History.Marcia Muelder Eaton - 1998 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 56 (3):309-311.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Art Instinct: Beauty, Pleasure, and Human Evolution.Mara Miller - 2009 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 67 (3):333-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Art and Illusion. A Study in the Psychology of Pictorial Representation.George Boas - 1960 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 19 (2):229-229.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   143 citations  
  • Danto and His Critics.Francis Sparshott - 1994 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52 (4):482-483.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • After the End of Art: Contemporary Art and the Pale of History.Arthur C. Danto - 2001 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 59 (2):214-215.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Values of Art: Pictures, Poetry, and Music.Eileen John - 1999 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 57 (1):76-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • (1 other version)Meaning.Herbert Paul Grice - 1957 - Philosophical Review 66 (3):377-388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1013 citations  
  • Values of Art: Pictures, Poetry and Music.Malcolm Budd - 1997 - Philosophical Quarterly 47 (187):246-248.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • (1 other version)Understanding Pictures.Dominic Lopes - 1999 - Philosophical Quarterly 49 (196):398-400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   114 citations  
  • Ways of Worldmaking.J. M. Moravcsik - 1978 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 37 (4):483-485.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   235 citations  
  • (5 other versions)Philosophical Explanations.Robert Nozick - 1981 - Mind 93 (371):450-455.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   882 citations  
  • Representation and make-believe.Alan H. Goldman - 1990 - Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 36 (3):335 – 350.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   168 citations  
  • Critique of the Power of Judgment.Hannah Ginsborg, Immanuel Kant, Paul Guyer & Eric Matthews - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (3):429.
    This new translation is an extremely welcome addition to the continuing Cambridge Edition of Kant’s works. English-speaking readers of the third Critique have long been hampered by the lack of an adequate translation of this important and difficult work. James Creed Meredith’s much-reprinted translation has charm and elegance, but it is often too loose to be useful for scholarly purposes. Moreover it does not include the first version of Kant’s introduction, the so-called “First Introduction,” which is now recognized as indispensable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   404 citations  
  • Clues.Carlo Ginzburg - 1979 - Theory and Society 7 (3):273-288.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Puzzle of Imaginative Resistance.Tamar Gendler - 2000 - Journal of Philosophy 97 (2):55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   236 citations  
  • Thought experiments rethought—and reperceived.Tamar Szabó Gendler - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (5):1152-1163.
    Contemplating imaginary scenarios that evoke certain sorts of quasi‐sensory intuitions may bring us to new beliefs about contingent features of the natural world. These beliefs may be produced quasi‐observationally; the presence of a mental image may play a crucial cognitive role in the formation of the belief in question. And this albeit fallible quasi‐observational belief‐forming mechanism may, in certain contexts, be sufficiently reliable to count as a source of justification. This sheds light on the central puzzle surrounding scientific thought experiment, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Imaginative contagion.Tamar Szabó Gendler - 2006 - Metaphilosophy 37 (2):183-203.
    The aim of this article is to expand the diet of examples considered in philosophical discussions of imagination and pretense, and to offer some preliminary observations about what we might learn about the nature of imagination as a result. The article presents a number of cases involving imaginative contagion: cases where merely imagining or pretending that P has effects that we would expect only perceiving or believing that P to have. Examples are offered that involve visual imagery, motor imagery, fictional (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • The Power of Images: Studies in the History and Theory of Response.David Freedberg - 1991 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 49 (1):85-86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Perceiving Artworks.Arthur Danto - 1981 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 39 (3):315-316.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • An argument for basic emotions.Paul Ekman - 1992 - Cognition and Emotion 6 (3):169-200.
    Emotions are viewed as having evolved through their adaptive value in dealing with fundamental life-tasks. Each emotion has unique features: signal, physiology, and antecedent events. Each emotion also has characteristics in common with other emotions: rapid onset, short duration, unbidden occurrence, automatic appraisal, and coherence among responses. These shared and unique characteristics are the product of our evolution, and distinguish emotions from other affective phenomena.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   500 citations  
  • (1 other version)Implicit preferences: The role(s) of familiarity in the structural mere exposure effect.D. Zizak - 2004 - Consciousness and Cognition 13 (2):336-362.
    In four experiments using an artificial grammar learning procedure, the authors examined the links between the “classic” mere exposure effect [heightened affect for previously encountered stimulus items ] and the “structural” mere exposure effect [greater hedonic appreciation for novel stimuli that conform to an implicitly acquired underlying rule system ]. After learning, participants: classified stimuli according to whether they conformed to the principles of the grammar and, rated them in terms of how much they liked them. In some experiments unusual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • To understand it on its own terms.Denis Dutton - 1974 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 35 (2):246-256.
    We commonly hear it said that a work of art must be understood “on its own terms,” and that phrase is used in other contexts as well; people, especially people very different from ourselves, are said to have to be understood on their own terms. But what is the meaning of the expression “on its/their own terms?” Note that we do not say of every possible object of understanding that it must be understood on its own terms. The statement, “Chemistry (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Artistic crimes: The problem of forgery in the arts.Denis Dutton - 1979 - British Journal of Aesthetics 19 (4):302-314.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Art and the language of the emotions.C. J. Ducasse - 1964 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 23 (1):109-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Explaining Behaviour: Reasons in a World of Causes.Andy Clark - 1990 - Philosophical Quarterly 40 (158):95-102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   537 citations  
  • The interpretation of texts, people and other artifacts.Daniel C. Dennett - 1990 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50:177-194.
    I want to explore four different exercises of interpretation: (1) the interpretation of texts (or hermeneutics), (2) the interpretation of people (otherwise known as "attribution" psychology, or cognitive or intentional psychology), (3) the interpretation of other artifacts (which I shall call artifact hermeneutics), (4) the interpretation of organism design in evolutionary biology--the controversial interpretive activity known as adaptationism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Music, Art, and Metaphysics.Stephen Davies - 1992 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 26 (2):110.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • (1 other version)The transfiguration of the commonplace.Arthur C. Danto - 1974 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 33 (2):139-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   134 citations