Switch to: Citations

References in:

What is relative confirmation?

Noûs 31 (3):370-384 (1997)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Theory and Evidence.Clark N. Glymour - 1980 - Princeton University Press.
    The Description for this book, Theory and Evidence, will be forthcoming.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   371 citations  
  • Beyond bootstrapping: A new account of evidential relevance.Madison Culler - 1995 - Philosophy of Science 62 (4):561-579.
    This paper investigates the adequacy of evidential relevance relations proposed by Glymour and others. These accounts incorporate, as a necessary condition, what I call the Positive Instance Condition (PIC): the evidence statement and auxiliary assumptions entail a "positive instance" of the hypothesis. I argue that any account which incorporates PIC as a necessary condition while allowing "bootstrap testing" is doomed to fail. A nonbootstrapping evidential relevance relation of similar form is proposed, and it is argued that, in addition to avoiding (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The irrelevance of bootstrapping.David Christensen - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (4):644-662.
    The main appeal of the currently popular "bootstrap" account of confirmation developed by Clark Glymour is that it seems to provide an account of evidential relevance. This account has, however, had severe problems; and Glymour has revised his original account in an attempt to solve them. I argue that this attempt fails completely, and that any similar modifications must also fail. If the problems can be solved, it will only be by radical revisions which involve jettisoning bootstrapping's basic approach to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Glymour on evidential relevance.David Christensen - 1983 - Philosophy of Science 50 (3):471-481.
    Glymour's "bootstrap" account of confirmation is designed to provide an analysis of evidential relevance, which has been a serious problem for hypothetico-deductivism. As set out in Theory and Evidence, however, the "bootstrap" condition allows confirmation in clear cases of evidential irrelevance. The difficulties with Glymour's account seem to be due to a basic feature which it shares with hypothetico-deductive accounts, and which may explain why neither can give a satisfactory analysis of evidential relevance.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Theory and Evidence.Clark Glymour - 1982 - Erkenntnis 18 (1):105-130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   172 citations  
  • Toward a defensible bootstrapping.Sam Mitchell - 1995 - Philosophy of Science 62 (2):241-260.
    An amended bootstrapping can avoid Christensen's counterexamples. Earman and Edidin argue that Christensen's examples to bootstrapping rely on his failure to analyze background knowledge. I add an additional condition to bootstrapping that is motivated by Glymour's remarks on variety of evidence. I argue that it avoids the problems that the examples raise. I defend the modification against the charge that it is holistic, and that it collapses into Bayesianism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The promiscuity of bootstrapping.Thomas R. Grimes - 1987 - Philosophical Studies 51 (1):101 - 107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • What revisions does bootstrap testing need? A reply.John Earman & Clark Glymour - 1988 - Philosophy of Science 55 (2):260-264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • What Revisions Does Bootstrap Testing Need?Jan M. Żytkow - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (1):101 - 109.
    Clark Glymour defined bootstrap-confirmation as a three-place relation: “Evidence E bootstrap confirms hypothesis H with respect to theory T.“ By an ingenious choice of examples, David Christensen has shown that Glymour's definition is satisfied in a class of cases in which confirmation seems to be highly counterintuitive. Responding to Christensen's criticism, Glymour revised his 1980 definition of bootstrap confirmation, by introducing an additional condition that rules out Christensen's counterexamples.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Hypothetico-deductivism, content, and the natural axiomatization of theories.Ken Gemes - 1993 - Philosophy of Science 60 (3):477-487.
    In Gemes (1990) I examined certain formal versions of hypothetico-deductivism (H-D) showing that they have the unacceptable consequence that "Abe is a white raven" confirms "All ravens are black"! In Gemes (1992) I developed a new notion of content that could save H-D from this bizarre consequence. In this paper, I argue that more traditional formulations of H-D also need recourse to this new notion of content. I present a new account of the vexing notion of the natural axiomatization of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Revisions of bootstrap testing.Clark Glymour - 1983 - Philosophy of Science 50 (4):626-629.
    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of J STOR’s Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. J STOR’s Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non—commercial use.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Bootstrapping and Content Parts.Ken Gemes - 2006 - Erkenntnis 64 (3):345-370.
    Christensen [Philosophy of Science, 50: 471–481, 1983] and [Philosophy of Science, 57: 644–662, 1990] provides two sets of counter-examples to the versions of bootstrap confirmation for standard first-order languages presented in Glymour [Theory and Evidence, Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1980] and [Philosophy of Science, 50: 626–629, 1983]. This paper responds to the counter-examples of Christensen [Philosophy of Science, 50: 471–481, 1983] by utilizing a new notion of content introduced in Gemes [Journal of Philosophical Logic, 26, 449–476, 1997]. It is claimed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations