Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Sartre and the Problem of Universal Human Nature Revisited.David Rose - 2003 - Sartre Studies International 9 (1):1-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Legal Positivism: 5½ Myths.John Gardner - 2001 - American Journal of Jurisprudence 46 (1):199-227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • The soundest theory of law.C. L. Ten - 1979 - Mind 88 (352):522-537.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Proportionalists, Deontologists and the Human Good.Bernard Hoose - 1992 - Heythrop Journal 33 (2):175-191.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Natural Law and Unnatural Acts.John M. Finnis - 1970 - Heythrop Journal 11 (4):365-387.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Desire as Belief.David K. Lewis - 1988 - Mind 97 (387):323-332.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • Weakness of Will, Commensurability, and the Objects of Deliberation and Desire.David Wiggins - 1979 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 79:251 - 277.
    David Wiggins; XV*—Weakness of Will Commensurability, and the Objects of Deliberation and Desire, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 79, Issue 1, 1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • XV*—Weakness of Will Commensurability, and the Objects of Deliberation and Desire.David Wiggins - 1979 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 79 (1):251-278.
    David Wiggins; XV*—Weakness of Will Commensurability, and the Objects of Deliberation and Desire, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 79, Issue 1, 1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Moral Cognitivism, Moral Relativism and Motivating Moral Beliefs.David Wiggins - 1991 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91:61 - 85.
    David Wiggins; IV*—Moral Cognitivism, Moral Relativism and Motivating Moral Beliefs, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, P.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • IV*—Moral Cognitivism, Moral Relativism and Motivating Moral Beliefs.David Wiggins - 1991 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91 (1):61-86.
    David Wiggins; IV*—Moral Cognitivism, Moral Relativism and Motivating Moral Beliefs, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 91, Issue 1, 1 June 1991, P.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • II*—Deliberation and Practical Reason.David Wiggins - 1976 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 76 (1):29-52.
    David Wiggins; II*—Deliberation and Practical Reason, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 76, Issue 1, 1 June 1976, Pages 29–52, https://doi.org/10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • The concept of equal opportunity.Peter Westen - 1985 - Ethics 95 (4):837-850.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Method, Morality and the Impossibility of Legal Positivism.Stuart Toddington - 1996 - Ratio Juris 9 (3):283-299.
    The dispute between Legal Positivists (eg, Hart) and Natural Lawyers (e.g., Finnis) concerns the existence or otherwise of a necessary (conceptual) connection between law and morality. Legal Positivists such as Hart deny this connection and assert the merely contingent relationship of law and morals. However, it can be demonstrated that implicit in the valid sociological method of concept formation of post‐Austinian Positivists are interpretative or ideal‐typical models of the practical rationality of the legal enterprise which are not, and cannot possibly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hegel and Prussianism.T. M. Knox - 1940 - Philosophy 15 (57):51 - 63.
    Despite the efforts of Bosanquet, Muirhead, Basch, and many others, it is still frequently stated or implied, in both popular and scholarly literature, that Hegel constructed his philosophy of the State with an eye to pleasing the reactionary and conservative rulers of Prussia in his day, and condoned, supported, and, through his teaching, became partly responsible for some of the most criticized features in “Prussianism” and even of present-day National-Socialism.5 Ijn this article I propose to give reasons for denying that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • X*—The Validity of Transcendental Arguments.Charles Taylor - 1979 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 79 (1):151-166.
    Charles Taylor; X*—The Validity of Transcendental Arguments, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 79, Issue 1, 1 June 1979, Pages 151–166, https://do.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • The Validity of Transcendental Arguments.Charles Taylor - 1979 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 79:151 - 165.
    Charles Taylor; X*—The Validity of Transcendental Arguments, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 79, Issue 1, 1 June 1979, Pages 151–166, https://do.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Phenomenology and Linguistic Analysis.Charles Taylor & A. J. Ayer - 1959 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 33 (1):93-124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The impossibility of moral responsibility.Galen Strawson - 1994 - Philosophical Studies 75 (1-2):5-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   296 citations  
  • Hegel and Prussianism.J. A. Spender & T. M. Knox - 1940 - Philosophy 15 (58):219-220.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Humean theory of motivation.Michael Smith - 1987 - Mind 96 (381):36-61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   269 citations  
  • On Humeans, anti-Humeans, and motivation: A reply to Pettit.Michael Smith - 1988 - Mind 97 (388):589-595.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Logic and the Sachverhalt.Barry Smith - 1989 - The Monist 72 (1):52-69.
    Those who conceive logic as a science have generally favoured one of two alternative conceptions as to what the subject-matter of this science ought to be. On the one hand is the nowadays somewhat old-fashioned-seeming view of logic as the science of judgment, or of thinking or reasoning activities in general. On the other hand is the view of logic as a science of ideal meanings, 'thoughts', or 'propositions in themselves'. There is, however, a third alternative conception, which enjoyed only (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Dispositional Theories of Value.Michael Smith, David Lewis & Mark Johnston - 1989 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 63 (1):89-174.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   407 citations  
  • Sidgwick and Reflective Equilibrium.Peter Singer - 1974 - The Monist 58 (3):490-517.
    In his book A Theory of Justice, John Rawls introduces and employs the concept of “reflective equilibrium” as a method of testing which of rival moral theories is to be preferred. The introduction of this concept is plainly a significant event for moral philosophy. The criterion by which we decide to reject, say, utilitarianism in favour of a contractual theory of justice is, if anything, even more fundamental than the choice of theory itself, since our choice of moral theory may (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   137 citations  
  • The Third.William Paul Simmons - 1999 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 25 (6):83-104.
    Emmanuel Levinas' radical heteronomous ethics has received a great deal of scholarly attention. However, his political thought remains relatively neglected. This essay shows how Levinas moves from the anarchical, ethical relationship with the Other to the totalizing realm of politics with his phenomenology of the third person, the Third. With the appearance of the Third, the ego must respond to more than one Other. It must decide whom to respond to first. This decision leads the ego from the an-archical, ethical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • A defense of motivational externalism.Russ Shafer-Landau - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 97 (3):267-291.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Minds, brains, and programs.John Searle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):417-57.
    What psychological and philosophical significance should we attach to recent efforts at computer simulations of human cognitive capacities? In answering this question, I find it useful to distinguish what I will call "strong" AI from "weak" or "cautious" AI. According to weak AI, the principal value of the computer in the study of the mind is that it gives us a very powerful tool. For example, it enables us to formulate and test hypotheses in a more rigorous and precise fashion. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1721 citations  
  • Natural Rights, Equality, and the Minimal State.Samuel Scheffler - 1976 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 6 (1):59 - 76.
    The idea of equality exerts considerable influence on our moral imaginations, yet it has remained philosophically elusive. Although men and women have thought equality worth dying for, philosophers have been largely unable to give any systematic account of its importance as a moral ideal, or of its function in moral and political theory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Sartre and the problem of universal human nature revisited.David Rose - 2003 - Sartre Studies International 9 (1):1-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Democracy and Distribution.Paden Roger - 1998 - Social Theory and Practice 24 (3):419-447.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Incommensurability and basic values.Andrew F. Reeve - 1997 - Journal of Value Inquiry 31 (4):545-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Moral realism.Peter Railton - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (2):163-207.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   546 citations  
  • Defending desire-as-belief.Huw Price - 1989 - Mind 98 (January):119-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • A definition of negative liberty.Philip Pettit - 1989 - Ratio 2 (2):153-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Universalizability without utilitarianism.Philip Pettit - 1987 - Mind 96 (381):74-82.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Humeans, anti-Humeans, and motivation.Philip Pettit - 1987 - Mind 96 (384):530-533.
    In 'The Humean Theory of Motivation' Michael Smith attempts two tasks: he offers an account of the debate about motivation between Humeans and anti-Humeans and he provides arguments that are designed to show that the Humeans win. While the paper is of great virtue in clarifying the debate, I believe that it falls short of both its goals. It does not highlight the really central issue between Humeans and anti-Humeans and it does not provide arguments which would settle that issue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Democracy and Distribution.Roger Paden - 1998 - Social Theory and Practice 24 (3):419-447.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • When conscience calls, will dasein answer? Heideggerian authenticity and the possibility of ethical life.Mariana Ortega - 2005 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 13 (1):15 – 34.
    How does everyday, inauthentic Dasein dominated by das Man become authentic? The aim of this article is to answer this and other questions about Dasein's authenticity by carrying out an analysis of the 'call of conscience'. This analysis, in turn, provides insights about Dasein's possibility for ethical existence. We will see that even though there are some puzzling issues in Heidegger's explanation of Dasein in its everydayness and its authenticity, the Heideggerian Existential Analytic is not 'anti-ethical' as some have claimed. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • H. L. A. Hart on Legal Obligation.Adejare Oladosu - 1991 - Ratio Juris 4 (2):152-176.
    .The author discusses Hart's concept of legal obligation, especially his contention that there is an obligation to obey the law which is peculiarly legal, i.e., non‐moral. This view is held to be mistaken. What is denied is that legal rules, merely by their being issued, offer a justification for the use of coercion to ensure compliance with them. Although moral and other social rules are considered self‐justifying, that is not the case of legal rules. Any analogy between these two types (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Some Levinasian Reflections on the Argument from Design.A. T. Nuyen - 2002 - Philosophy Today 46 (1):31-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Existentialism and the Return to Religion.A. T. Nuyen - 2000 - Philosophy Today 44 (2):169-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Lévinas and the Ethics of Pity.A. T. Nuyen - 2000 - International Philosophical Quarterly 40 (4):411-421.
    Much has been written on Levinas's ethics. However, there is a problem with his ethical theory that has received little attention in the literature, the problem of moral motivation. Nuyen argues that given what Levinas says about the empirical conditions in which metaphysical responsibility is played out, he stills owes an account of the normative force of such an ethics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On a Case for Animal Rights.Jan Narveson - 1987 - The Monist 70 (1):31-49.
    Down through the past decade and more, no philosophical writer has taken a greater interest in the issues of how we ought to act in relation to animals, nor pressed more strongly the case for according them rights, than Tom Regan, in many articles, reviews, and exchanges at scholarly conferences and in print. Now, in The Case for Animal Rights we have a substantial volume in which Regan most fully and systematically presents his case for a strong panoply of rights (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Animal Rights.Jan Narveson - 1977 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (1):161 - 178.
    What do we owe to the lower animals, if anything? The issues raised by this question are among the most fascinating and fundamental in ethical theory. They provide a real watershed for the moral philosopher and, on perhaps the most widely professed view, a trenchant test of consistency in ethical practice. Among the virtues of these two challenging books is that they make painfully clear that there has been a paucity of clear and plausible argument in support of the nearly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • What is it like to be a bat?Thomas Nagel - 1974 - Philosophical Review 83 (October):435-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2182 citations  
  • Objective Decision Making.D. H. Mellor - 1983 - Social Theory and Practice 9 (2-3):289-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Internalist moral cognitivism and listlessness.Alfred R. Mele - 1996 - Ethics 106 (4):727-753.
    This paper criticizes the conjunction of two theses: 1) cognitivism about first-person moral ought-beliefs, the thesis (roughly) that such beliefs are attitudes with truth-valued contents; 2) robust internalism about these beliefs, the thesis that, necessarily, agents' beliefs that they ought, morally, to A constitute motivation to A. It is argued that the conjunction of these two theses places our moral agency at serious risk. The argument, which centrally involves attention to clinical depression, is extended to a less demanding, recent brand (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • The Game Game.Mary Midgley - 1974 - Philosophy 49 (189):231 - 253.
    Some time ago, an Innocent Bystander, after glancing through a copy of Mind , asked me, ‘Why do philosophers talk so much about Games? Do they play them a lot or something?’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Violence and Metaphysics.”.Jacques Derrida - 2005 - In Claire Elise Katz & Lara Trout (eds.), Emmanuel Levinas. New York: Routledge. pp. 1--88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • Scorekeeping in a language game.David Lewis - 1979 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (1):339--359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   916 citations