Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (4 other versions)Causation.D. Lewis - 1986 - In David K. Lewis (ed.), Philosophical Papers Vol. II. Oxford University Press. pp. 159-213.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   641 citations  
  • Problems of the Self.Bernard Williams - 1973 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 37 (3):551-551.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   393 citations  
  • Kant's Theory of Freedom.Henry E. Allison - 1990 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    In his new book the eminent Kant scholar Henry Allison provides an innovative and comprehensive interpretation of Kant's concept of freedom. The author analyzes the concept and discusses the role it plays in Kant's moral philosophy and psychology. He also considers in full detail the critical literature on the subject from Kant's own time to the present day. In the first part Professor Allison argues that at the centre of the Critique of Pure Reason there is the foundation for a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   224 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kantian Modality.Tom Baldwin - 2002 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 76 (1):1-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • What is, for Kant, a Law of Nature?Eric Watkins - 2014 - Kant Studien 105 (4):471-490.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Kant-Studien Jahrgang: 105 Heft: 4 Seiten: 471-490.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Kant on Formal Modality.Ian S. Blecher - 2013 - Kant Studien 104 (1):44-62.
    I propose to explain Kant’s novel claim, in the Critique of Pure Reason, that all judgments have a formal modality. I begin by distinguishing the modality of a judgment’s form from the modality of its content, and I suggest that the former is peculiar in merely affecting the subject’s understanding of his own act of judging. I then contrast the modal account of such an understanding (in terms of the possibility and actuality of a judgment) with the traditional, non-modal understanding (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Kantian Dilemmas? Moral Conflict in Kant’s Ethical Theory.Jens Timmermann - 2013 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 95 (1):36-64.
    This paper explores the possibility of moral conflict in Kant’s ethics. An analysis of the only explicit discussion of the topic in his published writings confirms that there is no room for genuine moral dilemmas. Conflict is limited to nonconclusive ‘grounds’ of obligation. They arise only in the sphere of ethical duty and, though defeasible, ought to be construed as the result of valid arguments an agent correctly judges to apply in the situation at hand. While it is difficult to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Does ‘ought’ imply ‘can’? And did Kant think it does?Robert Stern - 2004 - Utilitas 16 (1):42-61.
    The aim of this article is twofold. First, it is argued that while the principle of ‘ought implies can’ is certainly plausible in some form, it is tempting to misconstrue it, and that this has happened in the way it has been taken up in some of the current literature. Second, Kant's understanding of the principle is considered. Here it is argued that these problematic conceptions put the principle to work in a way that Kant does not, so that there (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Values and the heart's command.Bas van Fraassen - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (1):5-19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   109 citations  
  • Asymmetrical freedom.Susan Wolf - 1980 - Journal of Philosophy 77 (March):151-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Metaphilosophy and Free Will.Richard Double - 1996 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Why is debate over the free will problem so intractable? In this broad and stimulating look at the philosophical enterprise, Richard Double uses the free will controversy to build on the subjectivist conclusion he developed in The Non-Reality of Free Will (OUP 1991). Double argues that various views about free will--e.g., compatibilism, incompatibilism, and even subjectivism--are compelling if, and only if, we adopt supporting metaphilosophical views. Because metaphilosophical considerations are not provable, we cannot show any free will theory to be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Freedom and Responsibility.Hilary Bok - 1998 - Princeton University Press.
    Can we reconcile the idea that we are free and responsible agents with the idea that what we do is determined according to natural laws? For centuries, philosophers have tried in different ways to show that we can. Hilary Bok takes a fresh approach here, as she seeks to show that the two ideas are compatible by drawing on the distinction between practical and theoretical reasoning.Bok argues that when we engage in practical reasoning--the kind that involves asking "what should I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • (1 other version)Freedom and Responsibility.J. M. Fischer - 2001 - Mind 110 (438):432-438.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Making sense of freedom and responsibility.Dana Kay Nelkin - 2011 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Nelkin presents a simple and natural account of freedom and moral responsibility which responds to the great variety of challenges to the idea that we are free and responsible, before ultimately reaffirming our conception of ourselves as agents. Making Sense of Freedom and Responsibility begins with a defense of the rational abilities view, according to which one is responsible for an action if and only if one acts with the ability to recognize and act for good reasons. The view is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   150 citations  
  • (1 other version)Obligation and motivation in recent moral philosophy.W. K. Frankena - 1958 - In Abraham Irving Melden (ed.), Essays in moral philosophy. Seattle: University of Washington Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Does ought imply can?Stuart M. Brown Jr - 1949 - Ethics 60 (4):275-284.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Selective necessity and the free will problem.Michael Slote - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (January):5-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Interest and Agency.Katerina Deligiorgi - 2017 - In Anders Moe Rasmussen & Markus Gabriel (eds.), German Idealism Today. Boston ;: De Gruyter. pp. 3-26.
    (2017) 'Interest and Agency', in Gabriel, Markus and Rasmussen, Anders Moe (eds.) German Idealism Today. De Guyter Verlag. -/- Abstract: Undeterred by Kant’s cautionary advice, contemporary defenders of free will advance substantive metaphysical theses in support of their views. This is perhaps unsurprising given the mixed reception of Kant’s solution of the conflict between freedom and natural necessity, which is supposed to vindicate reason’s withdrawal from speculation. Kant argues that neither libertarians nor determinists can win, because they deal with concepts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Autonomy in Bioethics.Katerina Deligiorgi - 2016 - Symposion: Theoretical and Applied Inquiries in Philosophy and Social Sciences 3 (2): 177-190.
    Autonomy in bioethics is coming under sustained criticism from a variety of perspectives. The criticisms, which target personal or individual autonomy, are largely justified. Moral conceptions of autonomy, such as Kant’s, on the other hand, cannot simply be applied in bioethical situations without moralizing care provision and recipience. The discussion concludes with a proposal for re-thinking autonomy by focusing on what different agents count as reasons for choosing one rather than another course of action, thus recognising their involvement in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Symmetry, Rational Abilities, and the Ought-Implies-Can Principle.Matthew Talbert - 2016 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 10 (2):283-296.
    In Making Sense of Free Will and Moral Responsibility Dana Nelkin defends the “rational abilities view.” According to this view, agents are responsible for their behavior if and only if they act with the ability to recognize and act for good reasons. It follows that agents who act well are open to praise regardless of whether they could have acted differently, but agents who act badly are open to blame only if they could have acted on the moral reasons that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Human Good and the Ambitions of Consequentialism.James Griffin - 1992 - Social Philosophy and Policy 9 (2):118.
    I want to look at one aspect of the human good: how it serves as the basis for judgments about the moral right. One important view is that the right is always derived from the good. I want to suggest that the more one understands the nature of the human good, the more reservations one has about that view. I. One Route to Consequentialism Many of us think that different things make a life good, with no one deep value underlying (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Kant's Modalities of Judgment.Jessica Leech - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (2):260-284.
    Abstract: This paper proposes a way to understand Kant's modalities of judgment—problematic, assertoric, and apodeictic—in terms of the location of a judgment in an inference. Other interpretations have tended to understand these modalities of judgment in terms of one or other conventional notion of modality. For example, Mattey (1986) argues that we should take them to be connected to notions of epistemic or doxastic modality. I shall argue that this is wrong, and that these kinds of interpretation of the modality (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kant's Theory of Propositional Attitudes.G. J. Mattey - 1986 - Kant Studien 77 (1-4):423-440.
    Kant was among the first philosophers to recognize that modalities come in many varieties, and that there are systematic connections among them--an insight which has since been confirmed by the multitude of applications of the basic techniques of formalized modal logic. In particular, He recognized an affinity among what are now called doxastic and epistemic logics, As well as with a logic of judging which has not exact counterpart in contemporary thought. This paper will be concerned with the explication of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Inaugural Address: Autonomy: The Emperor's New Clothes.Onora O'Neill - 2003 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 77 (1):1 - 21.
    Conceptions of individual autonomy and of rational autonomy have played large parts in twentieth century moral philosophy, yet it is hard to see how either could be basic to morality. Kant's conception of autonomy is radically different. He predicated autonomy neither of individual selves nor of processes of choosing, but of principles of action. Principles of action are Kantianly autonomous only if they are law-like in form and could be universal in scope; they are heteronomous if, although law-like in form, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • (2 other versions)In defense of bad infinity.Wayne M. Martin - 2007
    Hegel’s very first acknowledged publication was, among other things, an attack on Fichte.1 In 1801, Hegel was still laboring in almost complete obscurity, while Fichte was an international sensation, though already somewhat past the peak of his meteoric career. In the 1801 Differenzschrift, Hegel cut his teeth by criticizing Fichte’s already widely-criticized Wissenschaftslehre, and by demonstrating that Schelling’s philosophical system was not simply to be equated with it. Fichte himself never bothered to respond to Hegel’s criticisms; indeed he never publicly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Sollen und Können.Jens Timmermann - 2003 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 6 (1):113-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (2 other versions)In Defense Of Bad Infinity: A Fichtean Response To Hegel's Differenzschrift.Wayne M. Martin - 2007 - Bulletin of the Hegel Society of Great Britain 55:168-187.
    Hegel's very first acknowledged publication was, among other things, an attack on Fichte. In 1801, Hegel was still laboring in almost complete obscurity, while Fichte was an international sensation, though already somewhat past the peak of his meteoric career. In the 1801 Differenzschrift, Hegel cut his teeth by criticizing Fichte's already widelycriticised Wissenschaftslehre, and by demonstrating that Schelling's philosophical system was not simply to be equated with it. Fichte himself never bothered to respond to Hegel's criticisms; indeed he never publicly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Morality and the language of conduct.Hector-Neri Castañeda - 1963 - Detroit,: Wayne State University Press. Edited by George Nakhnikian.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kant's Theory of Propositional Attitudes.G. J. Mattey - 1986 - Société Française de Philosophie, Bulletin 77 (4):423.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Metaphilosophy and Free Will. [REVIEW]H. Bok - 2001 - Mind 110 (438):452-455.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations