Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Natural law and natural rights.John Finnis - 1979 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This new edition includes a substantial postscript by the author, in which he responds to thirty years of discussion, criticism and further work in the field to ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   353 citations  
  • General theory of law and state.Hans Kelsen - 1945 - Union, N.J.: Lawbook Exchange. Edited by Hans Kelsen.
    Reprinted 1999 by The Lawbook Exchange, Ltd. LCCN 98-32334. ISBN 1-886363-74-9. Cloth. $95. * Reprint of the first edition.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  • The practice of principle: in defence of a pragmatist approach to legal theory.Jules L. Coleman (ed.) - 2001 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Jules Coleman, one of the world's leading philosophers of law, here presents his most mature work so far on substantive issues in legal theory and the appropriate methodology for legal theorizing. In doing so, he takes on the views of highly respected contemporaries such as Brian Leiter, Stephen Perry, and Ronald Dworkin.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Marxism, functionalism, and game theory: A case for methodological individualism.Jon Elster - 2002 - In Derek Matravers & Jonathan Pike (eds.), Theory and Society. Routledge, in Association with the Open University. pp. 453.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Karl Marx's Theory of History: A Defence.G. A. Cohen - 1978 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    First published in 1978, this book rapidly established itself as a classicof modern Marxism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • Functional explanation, consequence explanation, and marxism.G. A. Cohen - 1982 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 25 (1):27 – 56.
    I argued in Karl Marx's Theory of History that the central claims of historical materialism are functional explanations, and I said that functional explanations are consequence explanations, ones, that is, in which something is explained by its propensity to have a certain kind of effect. I also claimed that the theory of chance variation and natural selection sustains functional explanations, and hence consequence explanations, of organismic equipment. In Section I I defend the thesis that historical materialism offers functional or consequence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The Methodological Problem in Legal Theory: Normative and Descriptive Jurisprudence Revisited.Veronica Rodriguez Blanco - 2006 - Ratio Juris 19 (1):26-54.
    Legal philosophers share the same phenomenology of legal practice. Yet, they differ in its explanation. For normativists, descriptivists got it wrong and vice versa. This controversy between normativists and descriptivists will be called “the methodological problem” in legal theory. Normativists such as Dworkin and Perry argue that descriptivists need evaluation. By contrast, descriptivists such as Coleman argue that normativists need the methods of descriptivism such as conceptual analysis and therefore might be committed to descriptivism. The paper shows that the responses (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Functions.John Bigelow & Robert Pargetter - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy 84 (4):181-196.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   220 citations  
  • Functionalism vs. Rational Choice?: Some Questions Concerning the Rationality of Choosing One or the Other.Johannes Berger - 1982 - Theory and Society 11 (4):521.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Where's the good in teleology?Mark Bedau - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (4):781-806.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Function statements.Peter Achinstein - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (3):341-367.
    An examination of difficulties in three standard accounts of functions leads to the suggestion that sentences of the form "the function of x is to do y" are used to make a variety of different claims, all of which involve a means-end relationship and the idea of design, or use, or benefit. The analysis proposed enables us to see what is right and also wrong with accounts that analyze the meaning of function statements in terms of good consequences, goals, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Law as a functional kind.Michael S. Moore - 1992 - In Robert P. George (ed.), Natural law theory: contemporary essays. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Hart's Methodological Positivism.Stephen R. Perry - 1998 - Legal Theory 4 (4):427-467.
    To understand H.L.A. Hart's general theory of law, it is helpful to distinguish betweensubstantiveandmethodologicallegal positivism. Substantive legal positivism is the view that there is no necessary connection between morality and the content of law. Methodological legal positivism is the view that legal theory can and should offer a normatively neutral description of a particular social phenomenon, namely law. Methodological positivism holds, we might say, not that there is no necessary connection between morality and law, but rather that there is no (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The concept of law.Hla Hart - 1961 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The Concept of Law is the most important and original work of legal philosophy written this century. First published in 1961, it is considered the masterpiece of H.L.A. Hart's enormous contribution to the study of jurisprudence and legal philosophy. Its elegant language and balanced arguments have sparked wide debate and unprecedented growth in the quantity and quality of scholarship in this area--much of it devoted to attacking or defending Hart's theories. Principal among Hart's critics is renowned lawyer and political philosopher (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   719 citations  
  • The morality of law.Lon Luvois Fuller - 1964 - New Haven: Yale University Press.
    Tthis book is likely to receive its warmest reception form advanced students of the philosophy of law, who will welcome the relief provided from the frequently sterile tone of much recent work in the field.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   147 citations  
  • Functions.Larry Wright - 1973 - Philosophical Review 82 (2):139-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   554 citations  
  • Function.Richard Sorabji - 1964 - Philosophical Quarterly 14 (57):289-302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Construction of Social Reality.John R. Searle - 1995 - Free Press.
    In The Construction of Social Reality, John Searle argues that there are two kinds of facts--some that are independent of human observers, and some that require..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   573 citations  
  • Was Austin right after all? On the role of sanctions in a theory of law.Frederick Schauer - 2010 - Ratio Juris 23 (1):1-21.
    In modern jurisprudence it is taken as axiomatic that John Austin's sanction-based account of law and legal obligation was demolished in H.L.A. Hart's The Concept of Law, but Hart's victory and the deficiencies of the Austinian account may not be so clear. Not only does the alleged linguistic distinction between being obliged and having an obligation fail to provide as much support for the idea of a sanction-independent legal obligation as is commonly thought, but the soundness of Hart's claims, as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The authority of law: essays on law and morality.Joseph Raz - 1979 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Legitimate authority -- The claims of law -- Legal positivism and the sources of law -- Legal reasons, sources, and gaps -- The identity of legal systems -- The institutional nature of law -- Kelsen's theory of the basic norm -- Legal validity -- The functions of law -- Law and value in adjudication -- The rule of law and its virtue -- The obligation to obey the law -- Respect for law -- A right to dissent? : civil disobedience (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   151 citations  
  • Natural law jurisprudence.Mark C. Murphy - 2003 - Legal Theory 9 (4):241-267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Law as justice.Michael S. Moore - 2001 - Social Philosophy and Policy 18 (1):115-145.
    A perennial question of jurisprudence has been whether there is a relationship between law and morality. Those who believe that there is no such relationship are known as while those who hold that some such relationship exists are usually tagged with the label Unfortunately, the latter phrase has been used in quite divergent senses. Sometimes it is used to designate any objectivist position about morality; as often, it labels the view that human nature determines what is objectively good or right; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Functional analysis and etiology.Ron McClamrock - 1993 - Erkenntnis 38 (2):249-260.
    Cummins (1982) argues that etiological considerations are not onlyinsufficient butirrelevant for the determination offunction. I argue that his claim of irrelevance rests on a misrepresentation of the use of functions in evolutionary explanations. I go on to suggest how accepting anetiological constraint on functional analysis might help resolve some problems involving the use of functional explanations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • G. A. Cohen's defense of functional explanation.Maurice Mandelbaum - 1982 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 12 (3):285-287.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Final authority to bind with moral mistakes: On the explanatory potential of inclusive legal positivism. [REVIEW]Kenneth E. Himma - 2005 - Law and Philosophy 24 (1):1-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Functions of Law.Leslie Green - 1998 - Cogito 12 (2):117-124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Legal positivism and the separation of existence and validity.Matthew Grellette - 2010 - Ratio Juris 23 (1):22-40.
    This paper centers upon the issue, within the project of analytic jurisprudence, of how to construe the status of the legal activities of a state when there is a disjuncture between a nation's formal legal commitments, such as those stated within a bill or charter of rights, and the way in which its officials actually engage in the practice of law, i.e., legislation and adjudication. Although there are two positions within contemporary legal theory which focus directly on this issue (Inclusive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Triviality arguments against functionalism.Peter Godfrey-Smith - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 145 (2):273 - 295.
    “Triviality arguments” against functionalism in the philosophy of mind hold that the claim that some complex physical system exhibits a given functional organization is either trivial or has much less content than is usually supposed. I survey several earlier arguments of this kind, and present a new one that overcomes some limitations in the earlier arguments. Resisting triviality arguments is possible, but requires functionalists to revise popular views about the “autonomy” of functional description.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • The Legality of Law.John Gardner - 2004 - Ratio Juris 17 (2):168-181.
    In this paper I outline various different objects of investigation that may be picked out by word “law” (or its cognates). All of these objects must be investigated in an integrated way before one can provide a complete philosophical explanation of the nature of law. I begin with the distinction between laws (artefacts) and law (the genre to which the artefacts belong). This leads me to the distinction between the law (of a particular legal system) and law (the genre of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Marxism, Functionalism, and Game Theory: The Case for Methodological Individualism.Jon Elster - 1982 - Theory and Society 11 (4):453.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Defending the possibility of a neutral functional theory of law.Kenneth M. Ehrenberg - 2008 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 29 (1):91.
    I argue that there is methodological space for a functional explanation of the nature of law that does not commit the theorist to a view about the value of that function for society, nor whether law is the best means of accomplishing it. A functional explanation will nonetheless provide a conceptual framework for a better understanding of the nature of law. First I examine the proper role for function in a theory of law and then argue for the possibility of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Two qualms about functionalist marxism.Joel Dickman - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (4):631-643.
    In Karl Marx's Theory of History: A Defence (1978), G. A. Cohen has developed a distinctively functionalist interpretation of historical materialism. In this paper I outline Cohen's novel reconstruction of Marx and subject it to two independent internal criticisms. I first argue that explanations cannot conform to Cohen's functionalist model. I then suggest that even if there could be explanations having the structure he has proposed, they would fail to be helpful in illuminating the causal kernel of Marx's theory. Finally (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Evaluation and Legal Theory.Julie Dickson - 2001 - Hart Publishing.
    If Raz and Dworkin disagree over how law should be characterised,how are we, their jurisprudential public, supposed to go about adjudicating between the rival theories which they offer us? To what considerations would those theorists themselves appeal in order to convince us that their accounts of law are accurate and successful? Moreover, what is it that makes an account of law successful? Evaluation and Legal Theory tackles methodological or meta-theoretical issues such as these, and does so via attempting to answer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Law’s Empire.Ronald Dworkin - 1986 - Harvard University Press.
    In this reprint of Law's Empire,Ronald Dworkin reflects on the nature of the law, its given authority, its application in democracy, the prominent role of interpretation in judgement, and the relations of lawmakers and lawgivers to the community on whose behalf they pronounce. For that community, Law's Empire provides a judicious and coherent introduction to the place of law in our lives.Previously Published by Harper Collins. Reprinted (1998) by Hart Publishing.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   495 citations  
  • Inclusive legal positivism.Wilfrid J. Waluchow - 1994 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Teleological Explanations: An Etiological Analysis of Goals and Functions.Larry Wright - 1976 - University of California Press.
    INTRODUCTION The appeal to teleological principles of explanation within the body of natural science has had an unfortunate history. ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • John Searle.Barry Smith (ed.) - 2003 - Cambridge University Press.
    From his groundbreaking book Speech Acts to his most recent studies of consciousness, freedom and rationality John Searle has been a dominant and highly influential figure amongst contemporary philosophers. This systematic introduction to the full range of Searle's work begins with the theory of speech acts and proceeds with expositions of Searle's writings on intentionality, consciousness and perception, as well as a careful presentation of the so-called Chinese Room argument. The volume considers Searle's recent work on social ontology and his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Making the Social World: The Structure of Human Civilization.John R. Searle (ed.) - 2009 - , US: Oxford University Press.
    The purpose of this book -- Intentionality -- Collective intentionality and the assignment of function -- Language as biological and social -- The general theory of institutions and institutional facts: -- Language and social reality -- Free will, rationality, and institutional facts -- Power : deontic, background, political, and other -- Human rights -- Concluding remarks : the ontological foundations of the social sciences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   273 citations  
  • Positive law and objective values.Andrei Marmor (ed.) - 2001 - Oxford [England] ; New York: Clarendon Press.
    This book presents a comprehensive defence of legal positivism on the basis of a novel account of social conventions. Marmor argues that the law is founded on constitutive conventions, and that consequently moral values cannot determine what the law is.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Explaining Technical Change: A Case Study in the Philosophy of Science.Jon Elster - 1983 - Universitetsforlaget.
    In this volume, first published in 1983, Jon Elster approaches the study of technical change from an epistemological perspective.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence & Philosophy of Law.Jules L. Coleman & Scott Shapiro (eds.) - 2002 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    One of the first volumes in the new series of prestigious Oxford Handbooks, The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law brings together specially commissioned essays by twenty-six of the foremost legal theorists currently writing, to provide a state of the art overview of jurisprudential scholarship.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • John Searle: Od aktów mowy do rzeczywistości społecznej.Barry Smith - 2003 - Roczniki Filozoficzne 51 (1):265-292.
    Polish translation of "John Searle: From Speech Acts to Social Reality", -/- We provide an overview of Searle's contributions to speech act theory and the ontology of social reality, focusing on his theory of constitutive rules. In early versions of this theory, Searle proposed that all such rules have the form 'X counts as Y in context C' formula – as for example when Barack Obama (X) counts as President of the United States (Y) in the context of US political (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Construction of Social Reality: An Exchange.Barry Smith & John Searle - 2003 - American Journal of Economics and Sociology 62 (2):285-309.
    Part 1 of this exchange consists in a critique by Smith of Searle’s The Construction of Social Reality focusing on Searle’s use of the formula ‘X counts as Y in context C’. Smith argues that this formula works well for social objects such as dollar bills and presidents where the corresponding X terms (pieces of paper, human beings) are easy to identify. In cases such as debts and prices and money in a bank's computers, however, the formula fails, because these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Unconstitutionality, Invalidity, and Charter Challenges.Michael Giudice - 2002 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 15 (1):69-83.
    Inclusive legal positivism maintains that the existence and content of laws may, but need not, depend on standards of morality. As Wil Waluchow argues, inclusive positivism derives much of its plausibility through its explanation of Charter societies such as Canada. On his account, the fundamental rights of political morality contained in the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms serve as ultimate criteria of the existence or validity of all laws in Canada, and thus form part of Canada's rule of recognition. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The problem of authority: Revisiting the service conception.Joseph Raz - manuscript
    The problem I have in mind is the problem of the possible justification of subjecting one's will to that of another, and of the normative standing of demands to do so. The account of authority that I offered, many years ago, under the title of the service conception of authority, addressed this issue, and assumed that all other problems regarding authority are subsumed under it. Many found the account implausible. It is thin, relying on very few ideas. It may well (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations