Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. An examination of restricted utilitarianism.H. J. McCloskey - 1957 - Philosophical Review 66 (4):466-485.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Why scientists gather evidence.Patrick Maher - 1990 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 41 (1):103-119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Joyce’s Argument for Probabilism.Patrick Maher - 2002 - Philosophy of Science 69 (1):73-81.
    James Joyce's 'Nonpragmatic Vindication of Probabilism' gives a new argument for the conclusion that a person's credences ought to satisfy the laws of probability. The premises of Joyce's argument include six axioms about what counts as an adequate measure of the distance of a credence function from the truth. This paper shows that (a) Joyce's argument for one of these axioms is invalid, (b) his argument for another axiom has a false premise, (c) neither axiom is plausible, and (d) without (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • On the seriousness of mistakes.Isaac Levi - 1962 - Philosophy of Science 29 (1):47-65.
    Several authors have recently contended that modern statistical theory provides a powerful argument in favor of the view that if scientists accept or reject hypotheses at all they do so only in a behavioral sense--i.e., in a sense which reduces "accepting P" to "acting on the basis of P relative to an objective O". In this paper, the argument from statistics in favor of a behavioral view is outlined; an interpretation of two statistical procedures (Bayes method and signifigance testing) is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Epistemic utility and the evaluation of experiments.Isaac Levi - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (3):368-386.
    William K. Goosens claims to show that my account of epistemic utility runs into serious difficulties when confronted with certain attractive conditions of adequacy for the evaluation of experiments. I show that those conditions of adequacy which are, indeed, acceptable to both of us are satisfied by the procedures for evaluating experiments mandated by combining my theory of epistemic utilities with the approach to evaluating experiments on which Goosens' argument is based. In particular, I demonstrate that my theory does not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Knowledge and Tradition.Philip Kitcher - 2001 - Philosophical Topics 29 (1-2):251-270.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Minimizing Inaccuracy for Self-Locating Beliefs.Brian Kierland & Bradley Monton - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (2):384-395.
    One's inaccuracy for a proposition is defined as the squared difference between the truth value (1 or 0) of the proposition and the credence (or subjective probability, or degree of belief) assigned to the proposition. One should have the epistemic goal of minimizing the expected inaccuracies of one's credences. We show that the method of minimizing expected inaccuracy can be used to solve certain probability problems involving information loss and self-locating beliefs (where a self-locating belief of a temporal part of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Decision Theory and Epistemology.Mark Kaplan - 2002 - In Paul K. Moser (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology. New York: Oup Usa.
    In ”Decision Theory and Epistemology,” Mark Kaplan finds it characteristic of orthodox Bayesians to hold that for each person and each hypothesis she comprehends, there is a precise degree of confidence that person has in the truth of that proposition, and no person can be counted as rational unless the degree of confidence assignment she thus harbors satisfies the axioms of the probability calculus. Kaplan's purpose is twofold. First, he aims to show that, as powerful as many criticisms are against (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)A nonpragmatic vindication of probabilism.James M. Joyce - 1998 - Philosophy of Science 65 (4):575-603.
    The pragmatic character of the Dutch book argument makes it unsuitable as an "epistemic" justification for the fundamental probabilist dogma that rational partial beliefs must conform to the axioms of probability. To secure an appropriately epistemic justification for this conclusion, one must explain what it means for a system of partial beliefs to accurately represent the state of the world, and then show that partial beliefs that violate the laws of probability are invariably less accurate than they could be otherwise. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   506 citations  
  • Valuation and acceptance of scientific hypotheses.Richard C. Jeffrey - 1956 - Philosophy of Science 23 (3):237-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   144 citations  
  • On the relation between categorical and probabilistic belief.Daniel Hunter - 1996 - Noûs 30 (1):75-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Theory and Evidence by Clark Glymour. [REVIEW]Paul Horwich - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (12):775-781.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Epistemic Consequentialism: Philip Percival.Philip Percival - 2002 - Supplement to the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 76 (1):121-151.
    I aim to illuminate foundational epistemological issues by reflecting on 'epistemic consequentialism'—the epistemic analogue of ethical consequentialism. Epistemic consequentialism employs a concept of cognitive value playing a role in epistemic norms governing belief-like states that is analogous to the role goodness plays in act-governing moral norms. A distinction between 'direct' and 'indirect' versions of epistemic consequentialism is held to be as important as the familiar ethical distinction on which it is based. These versions are illustrated, respectively, by cognitive decision-theory and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Inductive inconsistencies.Carl Gustav Hempel - 1960 - Synthese 12 (4):439-69.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • The preface, the lottery, and the logic of belief.James Hawthorne & Luc Bovens - 1999 - Mind 108 (430):241-264.
    John Locke proposed a straightforward relationship between qualitative and quantitative doxastic notions: belief corresponds to a sufficiently high degree of confidence. Richard Foley has further developed this Lockean thesis and applied it to an analysis of the preface and lottery paradoxes. Following Foley's lead, we exploit various versions of these paradoxes to chart a precise relationship between belief and probabilistic degrees of confidence. The resolutions of these paradoxes emphasize distinct but complementary features of coherent belief. These features suggest principles that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • On the principle of total evidence.Irving John Good - 1966 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 17 (4):319-321.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   143 citations  
  • Reply to commentators. [REVIEW]Alvin I. Goldman - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (1):215–227.
    I am most appreciative of the careful and incisive commentaries on KSW that Professors Kitcher, Talbott, and Copp have produced. They have pressed me to think more deeply about a number of issues of importance to social epistemology. Since their commentaries focus on completely different topics, I shall reply to them independently.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Knowledge in a social world.Alvin I. Goldman - 1991 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Knowledge in a Social World offers a philosophy for the information age. Alvin Goldman explores new frontiers by creating a thoroughgoing social epistemology, moving beyond the traditional focus on solitary knowers. Against the tides of postmodernism and social constructionism Goldman defends the integrity of truth and shows how to promote it by well-designed forms of social interaction. From science to education, from law to democracy, he shows why and how public institutions should seek knowledge-enhancing practices. The result is a bold, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   715 citations  
  • It Probably is a Valid Experimental Result: a Bayesian Approach to the Epistemology of Experiment.Allan Franklin - 1988 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 19 (4):419.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Realism and relativism.Hartry Field - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (10):553-567.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Goldman on Probabilistic Inference.Fallis Don - 2002 - Philosophical Studies 109 (3):223 - 240.
    In his recent book, Knowledge in a Social World, Alvin Goldman claims to have established that if a reasoner starts with accurate estimates of the reliability of new evidence and conditionalizes on this evidence, then this reasoner is objectively likely to end up closer to the truth. In this paper, I argue that Goldman's result is not nearly as philosophically significant as he would have us believe. First, accurately estimating the reliability of evidence – in the sense that Goldman requires (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Truth consequentialism, withholding and proportioning belief to the evidence.Michael R. DePaul - 2004 - Philosophical Issues 14 (1):91–112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • IIRobert Stalnaker.Robert Stalnaker - 2002 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 76 (1):153-168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Veritistic value and the use of evidence: A shortcoming of Goldman's epistemic evaluation of social practices.Hans Berends - 2001 - Social Epistemology 16 (2):177 – 179.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A bayesian paradox.Ruth Weintraub - 2001 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 52 (1):51-66.
    A seemingly plausible application of Bayesian decision-theoretic reasoning to determine one's rational degrees of belief yields a paradoxical conclusion: one ought to jettison one's intermediate credences in favour of more extreme (opinionated) ones. I discuss various attempts to solve the paradox, those involving the acceptance of the paradoxical conclusion, and those which attempt to block its derivation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Can we do without pragmatic encroachment.Brian Weatherson - 2005 - Philosophical Perspectives 19 (1):417–443.
    I consider the problem of how to derive what an agent believes from their credence function and utility function. I argue the best solution of this problem is pragmatic, i.e. it is sensitive to the kinds of choices actually facing the agent. I further argue that this explains why our notion of justified belief appears to be pragmatic, as is argued e.g. by Fantl and McGrath. The notion of epistemic justification is not really a pragmatic notion, but it is being (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   203 citations  
  • After the Neutrality Ideal: Science, Politics, and "Strong Objectivity".Sandra Harding - 1992 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 59:567-588.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Epistemic consequentialism.Robert Stalnaker - 2002 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 76 (1):153–168.
    [Philip Percival] I aim to illuminate foundational epistemological issues by reflecting on 'epistemic consequentialism'-the epistemic analogue of ethical consequentialism. Epistemic consequentialism employs a concept of cognitive value playing a role in epistemic norms governing belief-like states that is analogous to the role goodness plays in act-governing moral norms. A distinction between 'direct' and 'indirect' versions of epistemic consequentialism is held to be as important as the familiar ethical distinction on which it is based. These versions are illustrated, respectively, by cognitive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Veritistic value.Frederick F. Schmitt - 2000 - Social Epistemology 14 (4):259 – 280.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Balancing our epistemic goals.Wayne D. Riggs - 2003 - Noûs 37 (2):342–352.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Epistemic Consequentialism.Philip Percival - 2002 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 76 (1):121-151.
    I aim to illuminate foundational epistemological issues by reflecting on ‘epistemic consequentialism’—the epistemic analogue of ethical consequentialism. Epistemic consequentialism employs a concept of cognitive value playing a role in epistemic norms governing belief-like states that is analogous to the role goodness plays in act-governing moral norms. A distinction between ‘direct’ and ‘indirect’ versions of epistemic consequentialism is held to be as important as the familiar ethical distinction on which it is based. These versions are illustrated, respectively, by cognitive decision-theory and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Conditionalization, cogency, and cognitive value.Graham Oddie - 1997 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (4):533-541.
    Why should a Bayesian bother performing an experiment, one the result of which might well upset his own favored credence function? The Ramsey-Good theorem provides a decision theoretic answer. Provided you base your decision on expected utility, and the the experiment is cost-free, performing the experiment and then choosing has at least as much expected utility as choosing without further ado. Furthermore, doing the experiment is strictly preferable just in case at least one possible outcome of the experiment could alter (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • The Epistemology of Belief and the Epistemology of Degrees of Belief.Richard Foley - 1992 - American Philosophical Quarterly 29 (2):111 - 124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   142 citations  
  • Reason and consistency.Keith Lehrer - 1975 - In Analysis and Metaphysics. Boston: Springer. pp. 57--74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations