Switch to: Citations

References in:

Scientific representation is representation-as

In Hsiang-Ke Chao & Julian Reiss (eds.), Philosophy of Science in Practice: Nancy Cartwright and the nature of scientific reasoning. Cham: Springer International Publishing. pp. 149-179 (2016)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Simulation and Similarity: Using Models to Understand the World.Michael Weisberg - 2013 - New York, US: Oxford University Press.
    one takes to be the most salient, any pair could be judged more similar to each other than to the third. Goodman uses this second problem to showthat there can be no context-free similarity metric, either in the trivial case or in a scientifically ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   371 citations  
  • Three Kinds of Idealization.Michael Weisberg - 2007 - Journal of Philosophy 104 (12):639-659.
    Philosophers of science increasingly recognize the importance of idealization: the intentional introduction of distortion into scientific theories. Yet this recognition has not yielded consensus about the nature of idealization. e literature of the past thirty years contains disparate characterizations and justifications, but little evidence of convergence towards a common position.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   288 citations  
  • (1 other version)Seven Strictures on Similarity.Nelson Goodman - 1972 - In Problems and projects. Indianapolis,: Bobbs-Merrill.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   266 citations  
  • (1 other version)Languages of Art: An Approach to a Theory of Symbols.Nelson Goodman - 1968 - Indianapolis,: Bobbs-Merrill.
    . . . Unlike Dewey, he has provided detailed incisive argumentation, and has shown just where the dogmas and dualisms break down." -- Richard Rorty, The Yale Review.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   568 citations  
  • The transfiguration of the commonplace: a philosophy of art.Arthur Coleman Danto - 1981 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Mr. Danto argues that recent developments in the artworld, in particular the production of works of art that cannot be told from ordinary things, make urgent the need for a new theory of art and make plain the factors such a theory can and cannot involve. In the course of constructing such a theory, he seeks to demonstrate the relationship between philosophy and art, as well as the connections that hold between art and social institutions and art history. The book (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • Can robots make good models of biological behaviour?Barbara Webb - 2001 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (6):1033-1050.
    How should biological behaviour be modelled? A relatively new approach is to investigate problems in neuroethology by building physical robot models of biological sensorimotor systems. The explication and justification of this approach are here placed within a framework for describing and comparing models in the behavioural and biological sciences. First, simulation models – the representation of a hypothesis about a target system – are distinguished from several other relationships also termed “modelling” in discussions of scientific explanation. Seven dimensions on which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • An inferential conception of scientific representation.Mauricio Suárez - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (5):767-779.
    This paper defends an inferential conception of scientific representation. It approaches the notion of representation in a deflationary spirit, and minimally characterizes the concept as it appears in science by means of two necessary conditions: its essential directionality and its capacity to allow surrogate reasoning and inference. The conception is defended by showing that it successfully meets the objections that make its competitors, such as isomorphism and similarity, untenable. In addition the inferential conception captures the objectivity of the cognitive representations (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   250 citations  
  • Languages of art at the turn of the century.Jenefer Robinson - 2000 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 58 (3):213-218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Models and representation.Richard Hughes - 1997 - Philosophy of Science 64 (4):336.
    A general account of modeling in physics is proposed. Modeling is shown to involve three components: denotation, demonstration, and interpretation. Elements of the physical world are denoted by elements of the model; the model possesses an internal dynamic that allows us to demonstrate theoretical conclusions; these in turn need to be interpreted if we are to make predictions. The DDI account can be readily extended in ways that correspond to different aspects of scientific practice.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   207 citations  
  • The strategy of model-based science.Peter Godfrey-Smith - 2006 - Biology and Philosophy 21 (5):725-740.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   280 citations  
  • How models are used to represent reality.Ronald N. Giere - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (5):742-752.
    Most recent philosophical thought about the scientific representation of the world has focused on dyadic relationships between language-like entities and the world, particularly the semantic relationships of reference and truth. Drawing inspiration from diverse sources, I argue that we should focus on the pragmatic activity of representing, so that the basic representational relationship has the form: Scientists use models to represent aspects of the world for specific purposes. Leaving aside the terms "law" and "theory," I distinguish principles, specific conditions, models, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   305 citations  
  • True enough.Catherine Z. Elgin - 2004 - Philosophical Issues 14 (1):113–131.
    Truth is standardly considered a requirement on epistemic acceptability. But science and philosophy deploy models, idealizations and thought experiments that prescind from truth to achieve other cognitive ends. I argue that such felicitous falsehoods function as cognitively useful fictions. They are cognitively useful because they exemplify and afford epistemic access to features they share with the relevant facts. They are falsehoods in that they diverge from the facts. Nonetheless, they are true enough to serve their epistemic purposes. Theories that contain (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   324 citations  
  • True Enough.Catherine Z. Elgin - 2017 - Cambridge: MIT Press.
    Science relies on models and idealizations that are known not to be true. Even so, science is epistemically reputable. To accommodate science, epistemology should focus on understanding rather than knowledge and should recognize that the understanding of a topic need not be factive. This requires reconfiguring the norms of epistemic acceptability. If epistemology has the resources to accommodate science, it will also have the resources to show that art too advances understanding.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   199 citations  
  • Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective.B. C. van Fraassen - 2010 - Analysis 70 (3):511-514.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   270 citations  
  • Self-organised criticality—what it is and what it isn’t.Roman Frigg - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (3):613-632.
    The last decade and a half has seen an ardent development of self-organised criticality, a new approach to complex systems, which has become important in many domains of natural as well as social science, such as geology, biology, astronomy, and economics, to mention just a few. This has led many to adopt a generalist stance towards SOC, which is now repeatedly claimed to be a universal theory of complex behaviour. The aim of this paper is twofold. First, I provide a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • (1 other version)There Is No Special Problem About Scientific Representation.Craig Callender & Jonathan Cohen - 2006 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 21 (1):67-85.
    We propose that scientific representation is a special case of a more general notion of representation, and that the relatively well worked-out and plausible theories of the latter are directly applicable to thc scientific special case. Construing scientific representation in this way makes the so-called “problem of scientific representation” look much less interesting than it has seerned to many, and suggests that some of the (hotly contested) debates in the literature are concerned with non-issues.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Scientific representation.Roman Frigg & James Nguyen - 2016 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Science provides us with representations of atoms, elementary particles, polymers, populations, genetic trees, economies, rational decisions, aeroplanes, earthquakes, forest fires, irrigation systems, and the world’s climate. It's through these representations that we learn about the world. This entry explores various different accounts of scientific representation, with a particular focus on how scientific models represent their target systems. As philosophers of science are increasingly acknowledging the importance, if not the primacy, of scientific models as representational units of science, it's important to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Missing systems and the face value practice.Martin Thomson-Jones - 2010 - Synthese 172 (2):283-299.
    Call a bit of scientific discourse a description of a missing system when (i) it has the surface appearance of an accurate description of an actual, concrete system (or kind of system) from the domain of inquiry, but (ii) there are no actual, concrete systems in the world around us fitting the description it contains, and (iii) that fact is recognised from the outset by competent practitioners of the scientific discipline in question. Scientific textbooks, classroom lectures, and journal articles abound (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • (1 other version)Deeper Into Pictures: An Essay on Pictorial Representation.Flint Schier - 1986 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book presents an original theory of the nature of pictorial representation. The most influential recent theory of depiction, put forward by Nelson Goodman, holds that the relation between depictions and what they represent is entirely conventional. Flint Schier argues to the contrary that depiction involves resemblance to the things depicted, providing a sophisticated defence of our basic intuitions on the subject. Canvassing an attractive theory of 'generativity' rather than resemblance, Dr Schier provides a detailed account of depiction, showing how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective.Bas C. Van Fraassen - 2008 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Bas C. van Fraassen presents an original exploration of how we represent the world.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   295 citations  
  • The World in the Model: How Economists Work and Think.Mary S. Morgan - 2012 - Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.
    During the last two centuries, the way economic science is done has changed radically: it has become a social science based on mathematical models in place of words. This book describes and analyses that change - both historically and philosophically - using a series of case studies to illuminate the nature and the implications of these changes. It is not a technical book; it is written for the intelligent person who wants to understand how economics works from the inside out. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • (1 other version)Models and the limits of theory: quantum hamiltonians and the BCS model of superconductivity.Nancy Cartwright - 1999 - In Mary S. Morgan & Margaret Morrison (eds.), Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science. Cambridge University Press. pp. 241-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Idealization and abstraction: A framework.Martin R. Jones - 2005 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 86 (1):173-218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • Of mind and other matters.Nelson Goodman - 1984 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Essays discuss cognition, perception, art, science, truth, metaphor, education, philosophy, and cognitive psychology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • Twilight of the perfect model model.Paul Teller - 2001 - Erkenntnis 55 (3):393-415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   168 citations  
  • Pictorial representation.John Kulvicki - 2006 - Philosophy Compass 1 (6):535–546.
    Maps, notes, descriptions, diagrams, flowcharts, photographs, paintings, and prints, all, in one way or another, manage to be about things or stand for them. This article looks at three ways in which philosophers have explained the way that pictures represent the world. It starts by describing some leading perceptual accounts and then surveys contemporary content and structural alternatives.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • What Goodman should have said about representation.Douglas Arrell - 1987 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 46 (1):41-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Deeper into pictures: an essay on pictorial representation.Flint Schier - 1986 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book presents an original theory of the nature of pictorial representation. The most influential recent theory of depiction, put forward by Nelson Goodman, holds that the relation between depictions and what they represent is entirely conventional. Flint Schier argues to the contrary that depiction involves resemblance to the things depicted, providing a sophisticated defence of our basic intuitions on the subject. Canvassing an attractive theory of 'generativity' rather than resemblance, Dr Schier provides a detailed account of depiction, showing how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  • (1 other version)Fiction and scientific representation.Roman Frigg - 2008 - In Roman Frigg & Matthew Hunter (eds.), Beyond Mimesis and Convention: Representation in Art and Science. Boston Studies in Philosophy of Science. pp. 97-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Languages of Art.Nelson Goodman - 1970 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 3 (1):62-63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   625 citations  
  • Art and Illusion: A Study in the Psychology of Pictorial Representation.Ernst Hans Gombrich - 1960 - Phaidon.
    The A.W. Mellon lectures in the fine arts 1956, National Gallery of Art, Washington.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   305 citations  
  • Scientific representation, interpretation, and surrogative reasoning.Gabriele Contessa - 2007 - Philosophy of Science 74 (1):48-68.
    In this paper, I develop Mauricio Suárez’s distinction between denotation, epistemic representation, and faithful epistemic representation. I then outline an interpretational account of epistemic representation, according to which a vehicle represents a target for a certain user if and only if the user adopts an interpretation of the vehicle in terms of the target, which would allow them to perform valid (but not necessarily sound) surrogative inferences from the model to the system. The main difference between the interpretational conception I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • With Reference to Reference.Catherine Z. Elgin - 1983 - Hackett Publishing Company.
    "Systematizes and develops in a comprehensive study Nelson Goodman's philosophy of language. The Goodman-Elgin point of view is important and sophisticated, and deals with a number of issues, such as metaphor, ignored by most other theories." --John R. Perry, Stanford University.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Art and Illusion. A Study in the Psychology of Pictorial Representation.George Boas - 1960 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 19 (2):229-229.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   142 citations  
  • Of Mind and Other Matters.Alexander Nehamas - 1984 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 43 (2):209-211.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science.Nancy Cartwright - 2002 - Noûs 36 (4):699-725.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   275 citations  
  • Deeper into Pictures: An Essay on Pictorial Representation. [REVIEW]Diana Raffman - 1989 - Philosophical Review 98 (4):576.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • With Reference to Reference.Stephanie Ross - 1984 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 42 (4):448-451.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Models of machines and models of phenomena.Susan G. Sterrett - 2004 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 20 (1):69 – 80.
    Experimental engineering models have been used both to model general phenomena, such as the onset of turbulence in fluid flow, and to predict the performance of machines of particular size and configuration in particular contexts. Various sorts of knowledge are involved in the method - logical consistency, general scientific principles, laws of specific sciences, and experience. I critically examine three different accounts of the foundations of the method of experimental engineering models (scale models), and examine how theory, practice, and experience (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (1 other version)Fiction and scientific representation.Roman Frigg - 2010 - In .
    Understanding scientific modelling can be divided into two sub-projects: analysing what model-systems are, and understanding how they are used to represent something beyond themselves. The first is a prerequisite for the second: we can only start analysing how representation works once we understand the intrinsic character of the vehicle that does the representing. Coming to terms with this issue is the project of the first half of this chapter. My central contention is that models are akin to places and characters (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • The Transfiguration of the Commonplace, a Philosophy of Art.Marcia M. Eaton - 1981 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 40 (2):206-208.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Of Mind and Other Matters.N. Goodman - 1986 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (2):242-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Exemplification, idealization, and scientific understanding.Catherine Elgin - 2008 - In Mauricio Suárez (ed.), Fictions in Science: Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealization. New York: Routledge. pp. 77-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Fashioning descriptive models in biology: Of Worms and wiring diagrams.Rachel A. Ankeny - 2000 - Philosophy of Science 67 (3):272.
    The biological sciences have become increasingly reliant on so-called 'model organisms'. I argue that in this domain, the concept of a descriptive model is essential for understanding scientific practice. Using a case study, I show how such a model was formulated in a preexplanatory context for subsequent use as a prototype from which explanations ultimately may be generated both within the immediate domain of the original model and in additional, related domains. To develop this concept of a descriptive model, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science.Nancy Cartwright - 1999 - Philosophy 75 (294):613-616.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   580 citations  
  • (1 other version)Models and the limits of theory: quantum hamiltonians and the BCS model of superconductivity.Nancy Cartwright - 1999 - In Mary S. Morgan & Margaret Morrison (eds.), Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science. Cambridge University Press. pp. 241-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • With Reference to Reference.Catherine Z. Elgin - 1983 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 42 (2):336-340.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations