Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Naturalizing Kuhn.Alexander Bird - 2005 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105 (1):99-117.
    I argue that the naturalism of Thomas Kuhn's "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions," which he himself later ignored, is worthy of rehabilitation. A naturalistic conception of paradigms is ripe for development with the tools of cognitive science. As a consequence a naturalistic understanding of world-change and incommensurability is also viable.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • V *-naturalizing Kuhn.Alexander Bird - 2005 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105 (1):99-117.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Naturalizing Kuhn.Alexander Bird - 2005 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105 (1):99–117.
    I argue that the naturalism of Thomas Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, which he himself later ignored, is worthy of rehabilitation. A naturalistic conception of paradigms is ripe for development with the tools of cognitive science. As a consequence a naturalistic understanding of world-change and incommensurability is also viable.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Cognitive Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Peter Barker - 2011 - Erkenntnis 75 (3):445-465.
    For historical epistemology to succeed, it must adopt a defensible set of categories to characterise scientific activity over time. In historically orientated philosophy of science during the twentieth century, the original categories of theory and observation were supplemented or replaced by categories like paradigm, research program and research tradition. Underlying all three proposals was talk about conceptual systems and conceptual structures, attributed to individual scientists or to research communities, however there has been little general agreement on the nature of these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The discovery of time.Stephen Toulmin - 1965 - New York: Octagon Books. Edited by June Goodfield.
    "A discussion of the historical development of our ideas of time as they relate to nature, human nature and society. . . . The excellence of The Discovery of Time is unquestionable."--Martin Lebowitz, The Kenyon Review.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • A Function for Thought Experiments.T. Kuhn - 1981 - In David Zaret (ed.), Review of Thomas S. Kuhn The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change. Duke University Press. pp. 240-265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   149 citations  
  • The structure of scientific theories.Stephen Toulmin - 1974 - In Frederick Suppe (ed.), The Structure of scientific theories. Urbana,: University of Illinois Press. pp. 600--614.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Does the distinction between normal and revolutionary science hold water?Stephen Toulmin - 1970 - In Imre Lakatos & Alan Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge [Eng.]: Cambridge University Press. pp. 39--47.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Experience and Prediction: An Analysis of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge.Hans Reichenbach - 1938 - Chicago, IL, USA: University of Chicago Press.
    First published in 1949 expressly to introduce logical positivism to English speakers. Reichenbach, with Rudolph Carnap, founded logical positivism, a form of epistemofogy that privileged scientific over metaphysical truths.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   424 citations  
  • The philosophy of science.Stephen Toulmin - 1953 - New York,: Hutchinson's University Library.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Foresight and understanding: an enquiry into the aims of science.Stephen Toulmin - 1961 - Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   103 citations  
  • The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Thomas Samuel Kuhn - 1962 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Otto Neurath.
    A scientific community cannot practice its trade without some set of received beliefs. These beliefs form the foundation of the "educational initiation that prepares and licenses the student for professional practice". The nature of the "rigorous and rigid" preparation helps ensure that the received beliefs are firmly fixed in the student's mind. Scientists take great pains to defend the assumption that scientists know what the world is like...To this end, "normal science" will often suppress novelties which undermine its foundations. Research (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2705 citations  
  • Human understanding.Stephen Toulmin - 1972 - Princeton, N.J.,: Princeton University Press.
    v. 1. The collective use and evolution of concepts.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   139 citations  
  • Review of Thomas S. Kuhn The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change. [REVIEW]David Zaret - 1981 - Philosophical Review 90 (1):146.
    Review of T. S. Kuhn's The Essential Tension.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   261 citations  
  • Kuhn and the Discovery of Paradigms.K. Brad Wray - 2011 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 41 (3):380-397.
    I present a history of Kuhn’s discovery of paradigms, one that takes account of the complexity of the discovery process. Rather than emerging fully formed in Structure , the concept paradigm emerged through a series of phases. Early criticism of Structure revealed that the role of paradigms was unclear. It was only as Kuhn responded to criticism that he finally articulated a precise understanding of the concept paradigm. In a series of publications in the 1970s, he settled on a conception (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On the theoretical basis of prediction in economics.Wenceslao J. González - 1996 - Journal of Social Philosophy 27 (3):201-228.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Discovery of Time.H. V. Stopes-Roe - 1967 - Philosophy 42 (161):282-284.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Symposium: “Probability”.S. E. Toulmin & L. J. Russell - 1950 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 24 (1):27-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Foresight and Understanding: An Enquiry into the Aims of Science.Neil Cooper - 1963 - Philosophical Quarterly 13 (51):180-181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Conceptual revolutions in science.Stephen Toulmin - 1967 - Synthese 17 (1):75 - 91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Criticism in the history of science: Newton on absolute space, time, and motion, II.Stephen Toulmin - 1959 - Philosophical Review 68 (2):203-227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Philosophy of Science. An Introduction.Michael Scriven & Stephen Toulmin - 1955 - Philosophical Review 64 (1):124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Notes & Correspondence.George Sarton, Thomas Kuhn & C. Adams - 1952 - Isis 43:364-366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Kuhn, Normativity and History and Philosophy of Science.Howard Sankey - 2012 - Epistemologia:103-111.
    This paper addresses the relationship between the history and philosophy of science by way of the issue of epistemic normativity. After brief discussion of the relationship between history and philosophy of science in Kuhn’s own thinking, the paper focuses on the implications of the history of science for epistemic normativity. There may be historical evidence for change of scientific methodology, which may seem to support a position of epistemic relativism. However, the fact that the methods of science undergo variation does (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Experience and Prediction.William R. Dennes - 1939 - Philosophical Review 48 (5):536-538.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   141 citations  
  • Experience and Prediction.Eleanor Bisbee - 1938 - Philosophy of Science 5 (3):360-366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Experience and Prediction. An Analysis of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge. [REVIEW]E. N. & Hans Reichenbach - 1938 - Journal of Philosophy 35 (10):270.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   451 citations  
  • Thought styles and paradigms—a comparative study of Ludwik Fleck and Thomas S. Kuhn.Nicola Mößner - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (2):362–371.
    At first glance there seem to be many similarities between Thomas S. Kuhn’s and Ludwik Fleck’s accounts of the development of scientific knowledge. Notably, both pay attention to the role played by the scientific community in the development of scientific knowledge. But putting first impressions aside, one can criticise some philosophers for being too hasty in their attempt to find supposed similarities in the works of the two men. Having acknowledged that Fleck anticipated some of Kuhn’s later theses, there seems (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Foresight and Understanding: An Enquiry into the Aims of Science.Henry E. Kyburg - 1963 - Philosophical Review 72 (1):115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The Essential Tension.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (4):649-652.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   249 citations  
  • The Function of Measurement in Modern Physical Science.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1961 - Isis 52 (2):161-193.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1957 - Harvard University Press.
    The significance of the plurality of the Copernican Revolution is the main thrust of this undergraduate text In this study of the Copernican Revolution, the ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   218 citations  
  • The Copernican Revolution: Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought. Thomas S. Kuhn. [REVIEW]Philip P. Wiener - 1957 - Philosophy of Science 25 (4):297-299.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Sadi Carnot and the Cagnard Engine.Thomas Kuhn - 1961 - Isis 52:567-574.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Sadi Carnot and the Cagnard Engine.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1961 - Isis 52 (4):567-574.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Robert Boyle and Structural Chemistry in the Seventeenth Century.Thomas Kuhn - 1952 - Isis 43:12-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Robert Boyle and Structural Chemistry in the Seventeenth Century.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1952 - Isis 43 (1):12-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Notes & Correspondence.Thomas S. Kuhn & C. W. Adams - 1952 - Isis 43 (4):364-366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Newton's "31st Query" and the Degradation of Gold.Thomas Kuhn - 1951 - Isis 42:296-298.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Newton's "31st Query" and the Degradation of Gold.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1951 - Isis 42 (4):296-298.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Reichenbach's concept of prediction.Wenceslao J. González - 1995 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 9 (1):37-58.
    Reichenbach emphasizes the central importance of prediction, which is—for him—the principal aim of science. This paper offers a critical reconstruction of his concept of prediction, taking into account the different periods of his thought. First, prediction is studied as a key factor in rejecting the positivism of the Vienna Circle. This part of the discussion concentres on the general features of prediction before Experience and Prediction (EP) (section 1). Second, prediction is considered in the context of Reichenbach's disagreements with his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Reichenbach's concept of prediction.Wenceslao J. González - 1995 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 9 (1):37-58.
    Reichenbach emphasizes the central importance of prediction, which is—for him—the principal aim of science. This paper offers a critical reconstruction of his concept of prediction, taking into account the different periods of his thought. First, prediction is studied as a key factor in rejecting the positivism of the Vienna Circle. This part of the discussion concentres on the general features of prediction before Experience and Prediction (EP) (section 1). Second, prediction is considered in the context of Reichenbach's disagreements with his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Interpreting Thomas Kuhn as a Response-Dependence Theorist.Nathaniel Goldberg - 2011 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 19 (5):729 - 752.
    Abstract Thomas Kuhn is the most famous historian and philosopher of science of the last century. He is also among the most controversial. Since Kuhn's death, his corpus has been interpreted, systematized, and defended. Here I add to this endeavor in a novel way by arguing that Kuhn can be interpreted as a global response-dependence theorist. He can be understood as connecting all concepts and terms in an a priori manner to responses of suitably situated subjects to objects in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Physical Reality Philosophical Essays on Twentieth-Century Physics.Stephen Edelston Toulmin - 1970 - Harper & Row.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Thomas Kuhn.Thomas Nickles (ed.) - 2002 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Contemporary Philosophy in Focus offers a series of introductory volumes to many of the dominant philosophical thinkers of the current age. Thomas Kuhn, the author of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, is probably the best-known and most influential historian and philosopher of science of the last 25 years, and has become something of a cultural icon. His concepts of paradigm, paradigm change and incommensurability have changed the way we think about science. This volume offers an introduction to Kuhn's life and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The Cognitive Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Hanne Andersen, Peter Barker & Xiang Chen - 2006 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Peter Barker & Xiang Chen.
    Thomas Kuhn's Structure of Scientific Revolutions became the most widely read book about science in the twentieth century. His terms 'paradigm' and 'scientific revolution' entered everyday speech, but they remain controversial. In the second half of the twentieth century, the new field of cognitive science combined empirical psychology, computer science, and neuroscience. In this book, the theories of concepts developed by cognitive scientists are used to evaluate and extend Kuhn's most influential ideas. Based on case studies of the Copernican revolution, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Lakatos’s Approach on Prediction and Novel Facts.Wenceslao J. Gonzalez - 2001 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 16 (3):499-518.
    Lakatos’s approach to prediction and novel facts is of considerable interest. Prediction appears in his conception in at least three different levels: a) as an important aim of the research programs; b) as a procedure -a key method- for increasing our scientific knowledge both theoretically and empirically; and c) as the way to assess the scientific character of knowledge claims -means for evaluating results-. At all these levels he envisions a close connection between prediction and novel facts. The paper has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Discovery of Time.Stephen Toulmin & June Goodfield - 1965 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 17 (1):73-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Lakatos's approach on prediction and novel facts.Wenceslao J. Gonzalez - 2001 - Theoria 16 (3):499-518.
    Lakatos’s approach to prediction and novel facts is of considerable interest. Prediction appears in his conception in at least three different levels: a) as an important aim of the research programs; b) as a procedure -a key method- for increasing our scientific knowledge both theoretically and empirically; and c) as the way to assess the scientific character of knowledge claims -means for evaluating results-. At all these levels he envisions a close connection between prediction and novel facts. The paper has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Normal science: From logic to case-based and model-based reasoning.Tom Nickles - 2003 - In Thomas Kuhn. Cambridge University Press. pp. 142-77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations