Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. A Duty to Be Charitable? A Rigoristic Reading of Kant.Peter Atterton - 2007 - Kant Studien 98 (2):135-155.
    To be beneficent, that is, to promote according to one's means the happiness of others in need, without hoping for something in return, is every man's duty. Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals Almost everyone agrees that we have a moral duty to pull out a drowning child from a shallow pond even if this means getting our clothes muddy. But what are the limits of the duty of beneficence? In “Famine, Affluence and Morality”, which first appeared in 1972, Peter (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Good but not required?—assessing the demands of Kantian ethics.Jens Timmermann - 2005 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 2 (1):9-27.
    There seems to be a strong sentiment in pre-philosophical moral thought that actions can be morally valuable without at the same time being morally required. Yet Kant, who takes great pride in developing an ethical system firmly grounded in common moral thought, makes no provision for any such extraordinary acts of virtue. Rather, he supports a classification of actions as either obligatory, permissible or prohibited, which in the eyes of his critics makes it totally inadequate to the facts of morality. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Autonomy, progress and virtue : why Kant has nothing to fear from the overdemandingness objection.Jens Timmermann - 2018 - Kantian Review 23 (3):379-397.
    Is Kant’s ethical theory too demanding? Do its commands ask too much of us, either by calling for self-sacrifice on particular occasions, or by pervading our lives to the extent that there is no room for permissible action? In this article, I argue that Kant’s ethics is very demanding, but not excessively so. The notion of ‘latitude’ does not help. But we need to bear in mind that moral laws are self-imposed and cannot be externally enforced; that ‘right action’ is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • A Tale of Two Conflicts: On Pauline Kleingeld’s New Reading of the Formula of Universal Law.Jens Timmermann - 2018 - Kant Studien 109 (4):581-596.
    Pauline Kleingeld’s “Contradiction and Kant’s Formula of Universal Law”, published in this journal in 2017, presents a powerful challenge to what has become the standard reconstruction of the categorical imperative. In this response to Kleingeld, I argue that she is right to emphasise the ‘simultaneity requirement’ - that we must be able to will a proposed maxim and ‘simulataneously’, ‘also’ or ‘at the same time’ the maxim in its universalised form - but I deny that this removes the categorical imperative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Taking rights out of human rights.John Tasioulas - 2010 - Ethics 120 (4):647-678.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Kantian Beneficence and the Problem of Obligatory Aid.Karen Stohr - 2011 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 8 (1):45-67.
    Common sense tells us that in certain circumstances, helping someone is morally obligatory. That intuition appears incompatible with Kant's account of beneficence as a wide imperfect duty, and its implication that agents may exercise latitude over which beneficent actions to perform. In this paper, I offer a resolution to the problem from which it follows that some opportunities to help admit latitude and others do not. I argue that beneficence has two components: the familiar wide duty to help others achieve (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • On the real world duties imposed on us by human rights.Zofia Stemplowska - 2009 - Journal of Social Philosophy 40 (4):466-487.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Pufendorf's place in the history of ethics.J. B. Schneewind - 1987 - Synthese 72 (1):123 - 155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Kant and natural law ethics.J. B. Schneewind - 1993 - Ethics 104 (1):53-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Imperfect Duties, Group Obligations, and Beneficence.S. Andrew Schroeder - 2014 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 11 (5):557-584.
    There is virtually no philosophical consensus on what, exactly, imperfect duties are. In this paper, I lay out three criteria which I argue any adequate account of imperfect duties should satisfy. Using beneficence as a leading example, I suggest that existing accounts of imperfect duties will have trouble meeting those criteria. I then propose a new approach: thinking of imperfect duties as duties held by groups, rather than individuals. I show, again using the example of beneficence, that this proposal can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Kantian ethical duties.Faviola Rivera - 2006 - Kantian Review 11:78-101.
    Perfect ethical duties have usually puzzled commentators on Kant's ethics because they do not fit neatly within his taxonomy of duties. Ethical duties require the adoption of maxims of ends: the happiness of others and one's own perfection are Kant's two main categories. These duties, he claims, are of wide obligation because they do not specify what in particular one ought to do, when, and how much. They leave ‘a latitude for free choice’ as he puts it. Perfect duties, however, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Perfect and imperfect obligations.George Rainbolt - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 98 (3):233-256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Human Nature and the Right to Coerce in Kant’s Doctrine of Right.Alice Pinheiro Walla - 2014 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 96 (1):126–139.
    This paper explores the alleged role of a conception of human nature for Kant’s justification of the duty to leave the state of nature and the related right to coerce others to enter the civil condition in the Doctrine of Right (1797). I criticise the interpretation put forward by Byrd and Hruschka, according to which Kant’s postulate of public right is a preventive measure based on a “presumption of badness” of human beings. Although this reading seems to be supported by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Maxims and thick ethical concepts.A. W. Moore - 2006 - Ratio 19 (2):129–147.
    I begin with Kant's notion of a maxim and consider the role which this notion plays in Kant's formulations of the fundamental categorical imperative. This raises the question of what a maxim is, and why there is not the same requirement for resolutions of other kinds to be universalizable. Drawing on Bernard Williams' notion of a thick ethical concept, I proffer an answer to this question which is intended neither in a spirit of simple exegesis nor as a straightforward exercise (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Kant and the perfect duty to others not to lie.James Edwin Mahon - 2006 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 14 (4):653 – 685.
    In this article I argue that it is possible to find, in the Groundwork, a perfect ethical duty to others not to lie to any other person, ever. This duty is not in the Doctrine of Virtue, or the Right to Lie essay. It is an exceptionless, negative duty. The argument given for this negative duty from the Universal Law formula of the Categorical Imperative is that the liar necessarily applies a double standard: do not lie (everyone else), and lie (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Contradiction and Kant’s Formula of Universal Law.Pauline Kleingeld - 2017 - Kant Studien 108 (1):89-115.
    Kant’s most prominent formulation of the Categorical Imperative, known as the Formula of Universal Law (FUL), is generally thought to demand that one act only on maxims that one can will as universal laws without this generating a contradiction. Kant's view is standardly summarized as requiring the 'universalizability' of one's maxims and described in terms of the distinction between 'contradictions in conception' and 'contradictions in the will'. Focusing on the underappreciated significance of the simultaneity condition included in the FUL, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Kantian Imperfect Duties and Modern Debates over Human Rights.Simon Hope - 2013 - Journal of Political Philosophy 22 (4):396-415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Human Welfare and Moral Worth: Kantian Perspectives.Thomas E. Hill - 2002 - Oxford, GB: Clarendon Press.
    Thomas Hill, a leading figure in the recent development of Kantian moral philosophy, presents a set of essays exploring the implications of basic Kantian ideas for practical issues. The first part of the book provides background in central themes in Kant's ethics; the second part discusses questions regarding human welfare; the third focuses on moral worth -- the nature and grounds of moral assessment of persons as deserving esteem or blame. Hill shows moral, political, and social philosophers just how valuable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Liberal Rights.Ross Harrison & Jeremy Waldron - 1996 - Philosophical Quarterly 46 (184):401.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Expanding the Limits of Universalization: Kant’s Duties and Kantian Moral Deliberation.Joshua M. Glasgow - 2003 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33 (1):23 - 47.
    Despite all the attention given to Kant’s universalizability tests, one crucial aspect of Kant’s thought is often overlooked. Attention to this issue, I will argue, helps us resolve two serious problems for Kant’s ethics. Put briefly, the first problem is this: Kant, despite his stated intent to the contrary, doesn’t seem to use universalization in arguing for duties to oneself, and, anyway, it is not at all clear why duties to oneself should be grounded on a procedure that envisions a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Kant and the Claims of the Poor.Pablo Gilabert - 2010 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81 (2):382-418.
    Do we have positive duties to help others in need or are our moral duties only negative, focused on not harming them? If these positive duties exist, are they strong and strict demands or are they weak and discretionary? Can we say that at least some positive duties of assistance are also duties of justice worthy of institutionalization and coercive enforcement by legal institutions? Can the scope of some of such duties be cosmopolitan or should all of them be circumscribed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The form of practical knowledge: a study of the categorical imperative.Stephen P. Engstrom - 2009 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
    Introduction -- Part I: Willing as practical knowing -- The will and practical judgment -- Fundamental practical judgments : the wish for happiness -- Part II: From presuppositions of judgment to the idea of a categorical imperative -- The formal presuppositions of practical judgment -- Constraints on willing -- Part III: Interpretation -- The categorical imperative -- Applications -- Conclusion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   106 citations  
  • Herman on mutual aid.Stephen Engstrom - 1986 - Ethics 96 (2):346-349.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The practice of moral judgment.Barbara Herman - 1985 - Journal of Philosophy 82 (8):414-436.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   330 citations  
  • Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals.Immanuel Kant - 1785/2002 - In Practical Philosophy. Cambridge University Press. pp. 37-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   819 citations  
  • Acts, Perfect Duties, and Imperfect Duties.Michael Stocker - 1967 - Review of Metaphysics 20 (3):507 - 517.
    What I have just said strikes me as not only paradoxical but true. In what follows I shall try to show that it is not all that paradoxical and that it is true. In order to show this, and in order to discuss some important and neglected features of act and duty individuation, I shall contrast the concepts of perfect duty and imperfect duty.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Basic Rights.Henry Shue - 1983 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 173 (3):342-342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   141 citations  
  • Why The Doctrine Of Right Does Not Belong In The Metaphysics Of Morals.Marcus Willaschek - 1997 - Jahrbuch für Recht Und Ethik 5.
    Der Aufsatz behandelt den Zusammenhang zwischen Recht, Ethik und Moral in der MdS. Ausgangspunkt ist der Befund, daß Kants System der Pflichten in der MdS weder konsistent noch vollständig ist, weil Rechts- und Tugendpflichten, entgegen Kants Annahme, den Bereich der moralischen Pflichten nicht erschöpfen . Kants System der Pflichten beruht auf den Unterscheidungen zwischen Recht und Ethik und zwischen Legalität und Moralität. Letztere konzipiert Kant in der MdS anders als in früheren Werken, indem er sie nun auf die beiden Arten (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Imperfect Duties And Supererogatory Acts.Marcia Baron - 1998 - Jahrbuch für Recht Und Ethik 6.
    In this essay I rethink a view that I developed in my Kantian Ethics Almost Without Apology , concerning how ethical theory should handle the phenomena that are standardly classified as supererogatory acts. The view I elaborated rejects the standard contemporary picture, according to which ethics needs to draw a line separating duty from what is "beyond duty"--the supererogatory. On the Kantian picture, beneficent acts are not beyond duty, for we are required to help others, but we are not required (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Natural Right Or Natural Law?Mary Gregor - 1995 - Jahrbuch für Recht Und Ethik 3.
    If Kant's account of rights had continued the "early modern Natural Law tradition", basing rights on some notion of human flourishing, there would be no difficulty about including socio-economic rights for the needy in his theory. However, his division of moral philosophy into Rechtslehre and Tugendlehre limits Rechtspflichten to duties that a moral agent can be coerced to fulfill. If a state is to give the needy statutory rights, the justification for using coercion on its citizens cannot be that they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations