Switch to: Citations

References in:

Assessing Theories. The Problem of a Quantitative Theory of Confirmation

Dissertation, University of Erfurt (2004)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (1 other version)Précis of Inference to the Best Explanation, 2 nd Edition.Peter Lipton - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (2):421-423.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   564 citations  
  • (1 other version)A Logical Measure Function.John G. Kemeny - 1954 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 19 (4):301-302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • .Jeremy Butterfield & John Earman - 1977
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   368 citations  
  • Inference to the Best Explanation.Peter Lipton - 1991 - London and New York: Routledge.
    How do we go about weighing evidence, testing hypotheses, and making inferences? According to the model of _Inference to the Best Explanation_, we work out what to infer from the evidence by thinking about what would actually explain that evidence, and we take the ability of a hypothesis to explain the evidence as a sign that the hypothesis is correct. In _Inference to the Best Explanation_, Peter Lipton gives this important and influential idea the development and assessment it deserves. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   428 citations  
  • What Price Coherence?Peter Klein & Ted A. Warfield - 1994 - Analysis 54 (3):129 - 132.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • From a Logical Point of View.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1953 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Several of these essays have been printed whole in journals; others are in varying degrees new. Two main themes run through them. One is the problem of meaning, particularly as involved in the notion of an analytic statement. The other is the notion of ontological, commitment, particularly as involved in the problem of universals.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   863 citations  
  • Scientific reasoning: the Bayesian approach.Peter Urbach & Colin Howson - 1993 - Chicago: Open Court. Edited by Peter Urbach.
    Scientific reasoning is—and ought to be—conducted in accordance with the axioms of probability. This Bayesian view—so called because of the central role it accords to a theorem first proved by Thomas Bayes in the late eighteenth ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   569 citations  
  • (1 other version)Coherence and the axioms of confirmation.Abner Shimony - 1955 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 20 (1):1-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   113 citations  
  • Studies in the logic of confirmation (I.).Carl Gustav Hempel - 1945 - Mind 54 (213):1-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   299 citations  
  • Two Dogmas of Empiricism.W. Quine - 1951 - [Longmans, Green].
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1215 citations  
  • Reply to Akiba on the probabilistic measure of coherence.Tomoji Shogenji - 2001 - Analysis 61 (2):147-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Paradoxes solved by simple relevance criteria.Paul Weingartner & Gerhard Schurz - 1986 - Logique Et Analyse 29 (113):3-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • (1 other version)Speaking of Objects.W. V. Quine - 1957 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 31 (3):5 - 22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • On Behalf of the Coherentist.Trenton Merricks - 1995 - Analysis 55 (4):306 - 309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Toward a defensible bootstrapping.Sam Mitchell - 1995 - Philosophy of Science 62 (2):241-260.
    An amended bootstrapping can avoid Christensen's counterexamples. Earman and Edidin argue that Christensen's examples to bootstrapping rely on his failure to analyze background knowledge. I add an additional condition to bootstrapping that is motivated by Glymour's remarks on variety of evidence. I argue that it avoids the problems that the examples raise. I defend the modification against the charge that it is holistic, and that it collapses into Bayesianism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A fuzzy measure for explanatory coherence.Daniel Schoch - 2000 - Synthese 122 (3):291-311.
    In a series of articles, Paul Thagard has developed a connectionist''s modelfor the evaluation of explanatory coherence for competing systems ofhypotheses. He has successfully applied it to various examples from thehistory of science and common language reasoning. However, I will argue thathis formalism does not adequately represent explanatory relations betweenmore than two propositions.In this paper, I develop a generalization of Thagard''s approach. It is notsubject to the connectionist paradigm of neural nets, but is based on fuzzylogic: Explanatory coherence increases with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)A Probabilistic Theory of the Coherence of an Information Set.Stephan Hartmann & Luc Bovens - 2001 - In BeckermannAnsgar (ed.), Argument & Analysis: Proceedings of the 4th International Congress of the Society for Analytical Philosophy. Bielefeld.
    Bonjour (1985: 101 and 1999: 124) and other coherence theorists of justification before him (e.g. Ewing, 1934: 246) have complained that we do not have a satisfactory analysis of the notion of coherence. The problem with existing accounts of coherence is that they try to bring precision to our intuitive notion of coherence independently of the particular role that it is meant to play within the coherence theory of justification (e.g Lewis, 1946: 338). This is a mistake: it does not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Verisimilitude defined by relevant consequence-elements.G. Schurz & P. Weingartner - 1987 - In Theo A. F. Kuipers (ed.), What is Closer-to-the-truth?: A Parade of Approaches to Truthlikeness. Amsterdam: Rodopi. pp. 47--77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Fair bets and inductive probabilities.John G. Kemeny - 1955 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 20 (3):263-273.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  • A syntactical definition of probability and of degree of confirmation.Olaf Helmer & Paul Oppenheim - 1945 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 10 (2):25-60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Shogenji's probabilistic measure of coherence is incoherent.Ken Akiba - 2000 - Analysis 60 (4):356-359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Bayesianism and the Fixity of the Theoretical Framework.Donald Gillies - 2001 - In David Corfield & Jon Williamson (eds.), Foundations of Bayesianism. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 363--379.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • A purely syntactical definition of confirmation.Carl G. Hempel - 1943 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 8 (4):122-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • No help for the coherentist.Peter Klein & Ted A. Warfield - 1996 - Analysis 56 (2):118-121.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Bayesianism With A Human Face.Richard C. Jeffrey - 1983 - In John Earman (ed.), Testing Scientific Theories. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. pp. 133--156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • What is the problem of coherence and truth?Erik J. Olsson - 2002 - Journal of Philosophy 99 (5):246-272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • Hypothetico-deductivism is hopeless.Clark Glymour - 1980 - Philosophy of Science 47 (2):322-325.
    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of J STOR’s Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. J STOR’s Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non—commercial use.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • A new theory of content II: Model theory and some alternatives. [REVIEW]Ken Gemes - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (4):449-476.
    This paper develops a semantical model - theoretic account of (logical) content complementing the syntactically specified account of content developed in "A New Theory of Content I", JPL 23: 596-620, 1994. Proofs of Completeness are given for both propositional and quantificational languages (without identity). Means for handling a quantificational language with identity are also explored. Finally, this new notion of content is compared, in respect of both logical properties and philosophical applications, to alternative partitions of the standard consequence class relation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Coherence and truth conducive justification.Charles B. Cross - 1999 - Analysis 59 (3):186-193.
    In a 1994 ANALYSIS article Peter Klein and Ted Warfield show that an epistemically more coherent set of beliefs often has a smaller unconditional probability of joint truth than some of its less coherent subsets. They conclude that epistemic justification, as understood in one version of a coherence theory of justification, is not truth conducive. After getting clear about what truth conduciveness requires, I show that their argument does not tell against BonJour's coherence theory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Erklärung und wissenschaftliches Verstehen: Die Vereinheitlichung der Gesetze.Michael Friedman - 1990 - In G. Schurz (ed.), Erklären und Verstehen in der Wissenschaft. Vittorio Klostermann. pp. 171-192.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (2 other versions)Error and the growth of experimental knowledge.Deborah Mayo - 1996 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 15 (1):455-459.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   328 citations  
  • (1 other version)Review of D. Armstrong: What is a Law of Nature?[REVIEW]James Woodward - 1985 - Ethics 95 (4):949-951.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • (1 other version)A logical measure function.John G. Kemeny - 1953 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 18 (4):289-308.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Μεσσαταοσ.M. M. Gillies - 1927 - The Classical Review 41 (01):9-10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • A new theory of content I: Basic content. [REVIEW]Ken Gemes - 1994 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 23 (6):595 - 620.
    Philosophers of science as divergent as the inductivist Carnap and the deductivist Popper share the notion that the (logical) content of a proposition is given by its consequence class. I claim that this notion of content is (a) unintuitive and (b) inappropriate for many of the formal needs of philosophers of science. The basic problem is that given this notion of content, for any arbitrary p and q, [(p ∨ q)] will count as part of the content of both p (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Paradoxical consequences of Balzer's and gähde's criteria of theoreticity. Results of an application to ten scientific theories.Gerhard Schurz - 1990 - Erkenntnis 32 (2):161 - 214.
    It is shown that the criteria of T-theoreticity proposed by Balzer and Gähde lead to strongly counterintuitive and in this sense paradoxical results: most of the obviously empirical or at least nontheoretical terms come out as theoretical. This is demonstrated for a lot of theories in different areas. On the way, some improved and some new structuralist theory-reconstructions are given. The conclusion is drawn that the T-theoreticity of a term cannot possibly be proved on the basis of the mathematical structure (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Erklären und Verstehen in der Wissenschaft.G. Schurz - 1990 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 44 (4):671-675.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations