Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Philosophical explanations.Robert Nozick - 1981 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Nozick analyzes fundamental issues, such as the identity of the self, knowledge and skepticism, free will, the foundations of ethics, and the meaning of life.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1092 citations  
  • Testimony, knowledge and belief.Michael Welbourne - 1994 - In A. Chakrabarti & B. K. Matilal (eds.), Knowing from Words. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 297--313.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Knowledge: Undefeated justified true belief.Keith Lehrer & Thomas Paxson - 1969 - Journal of Philosophy 66 (8):225-237.
    The recently offered, Purported counter-Examples to justified, True belief analyses of knowledge are looked at with some care and all found to be either incoherent or inconclusive. It is argued that justified, True belief analyses are based on sound insight into the concept of knowledge. The distinction between having been justified in claiming to know something and actually having known it is used in an effort to get the discussion of knowledge back on the right track.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   154 citations  
  • The Epistemology of Testimony.Elizabeth Fricker & David E. Cooper - 1987 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 61 (1):57 - 106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   136 citations  
  • Theory of knowledge.Roderick M. Chisholm - 1966 - Englewood Cliffs, N.J.,: Prentice-Hall.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   560 citations  
  • The Internalist Conception of Justification.Alvin Goldman - 1980 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5 (1):27-51.
    One possible aim of epistemology is to advise cognizers on the proper choice of beliefs or other doxastic attitudes. This aim has often been part of scientific methodology: to tell scientists when they should accept a given hypothesis, or give it a certain degree of credence. This regulative function is naturally linked to the notion of epistemic justification. It may well be suggested that a cognizer is justified in believing something just in case the rules of proper epistemic procedure prescribe (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Warrant and proper function.Alvin Plantinga - 1993 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this companion volume to Warrant: The Current Debate, Plantinga develops an original approach to the question of epistemic warrant; that is what turns true belief into knowledge. He argues that what is crucial to warrant is the proper functioning of one's cognitive faculties in the right kind of cognitive environment.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   592 citations  
  • Contemporary theories of knowledge.John L. Pollock - 1986 - London: Hutchinson.
    This new edition of the classic Contemporary Theories of Knowledge has been significantly updated to include analyses of the recent literature in epistemology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   542 citations  
  • Epistemology and cognition.Alvin I. Goldman - 1986 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Against the traditional view, Alvin Goldman argues that logic, probability theory, and linguistic analysis cannot by themselves delineate principles of rationality or justified belief. The mind's operations must be taken into account.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   843 citations  
  • Why believe what people say?Leslie Stevenson - 1993 - Synthese 94 (3):429 - 451.
    The basic alternatives seem to be either a Humean reductionist view that any particular assertion needs backing with inductive evidence for its reliability before it can retionally be believed, or a Reidian criterial view that testimony is intrinscially, though defeasibly, credible, in the absence of evidence against its reliability.Some recent arguments from the constraints on interpreting any linguistic performances as assertions with propositional content have some force against the reductionist view. We thus have reason to accept the criterial view, at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Critical notice: Telling and trusting: Reductionism and anti-reductionism in the epistemology of testimony.Elizabeth Fricker - 1995 - Mind 104 (414):393-411.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   154 citations  
  • Knowing and asserting.Timothy Williamson - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (4):489-523.
    This paper aims to identify the constitutive rule of assertion, conceived by analogy with the rules of a game. That assertion has such rules is by no means obvious; perhaps it is more like a natural phenomenon than it seems. One way to find out is by supposing that it has such rules, in order to see where the hypothesis leads and what it explains. That will be done here. The hypothesis is not perfectly clear, of course, but we have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   329 citations  
  • The community of knowledge.Michael Welbourne - 1981 - Philosophical Quarterly 31 (125):302-314.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Testimony, induction and folk psychology.Jack Lyons - 1997 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 75 (2):163 – 178.
    An influential argument for anti-reductionism about testimony, due to CAJ Coady, fails, because it assumes that an inductive global defense of testimony would proceed along effectively behaviorist lines. If we take seriously our wealth of non-testimonially justified folk psychological beliefs, the prospects for inductivism and reductionism look much better.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Elusive knowledge.David Lewis - 1996 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (4):549 – 567.
    David Lewis (1941-2001) was Class of 1943 University Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University. His contributions spanned philosophical logic, philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, philosophy of science, metaphysics, and epistemology. In On the Plurality of Worlds, he defended his challenging metaphysical position, "modal realism." He was also the author of the books Convention, Counterfactuals, Parts of Classes, and several volumes of collected papers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1040 citations  
  • Knowledge, causality, and defeasibility.Peter D. Klein - 1976 - Journal of Philosophy 73 (20):792-812.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • The role of trust in knowledge.John Hardwig - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (12):693-708.
    Most traditional epistemologists see trust and knowledge as deeply antithetical: we cannot know by trusting in the opinions of others; knowledge must be based on evidence, not mere trust. I argue that this is badly mistaken. Modern knowers cannot be independent and self-reliant. In most disciplines, those who do not trust cannot know. Trust is thus often more epistemically basic than empirical evidence or logical argument, for the evidence and the argument are available only through trust. Finally, since the reliability (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   258 citations  
  • What is testimony?Peter J. Graham - 1997 - Philosophical Quarterly 47 (187):227-232.
    C.A.J. Coady, in his book Testimony: A Philosophical Study (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), offers conditions on an assertion that p to count as testimony. He claims that the assertion that p must be by a competent speaker directed to an audience in need of evidence and it must be evidence that p. I offer examples to show that Coady’s conditions are too strong. Testimony need not be evidence; the speaker need not be competent; and, the statement need not be relevant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Solving the skeptical problem.Keith DeRose - 1995 - Philosophical Review 104 (1):1-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   639 citations  
  • Content preservation.Tyler Burge - 1993 - Philosophical Review 102 (4):457-488.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   602 citations  
  • Interlocution, perception, and memory.Tyler Burge - 1997 - Philosophical Studies 86 (1):21-47.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • Elusive Knowledge.David Lewis - 2000 - In Sven Bernecker & Fred I. Dretske (eds.), Knowledge: readings in contemporary epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   442 citations  
  • Knowledge: Undefeated Justified True Belief.T. Paxson & K. Lehrer - 2000 - In Sven Bernecker & Fred I. Dretske (eds.), Knowledge: readings in contemporary epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  • Knowledge, truth and evidence.Keith Lehrer - 1965 - Analysis 25 (5):168.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Testimony and memory.Michael Dummett - 1994 - In A. Chakrabarti & B. K. Matilal (eds.), Knowing from Words. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 251--272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Testimonial evidence.James F. Ross - 1975 - In Keith Lehrer (ed.), Analysis and Metaphysics. Springer. pp. 35-55.
    Knowledge through what others tell us not only forms a large part of the body of our knowledge but also originates the patterns of appraisal according to which we add beliefs to our present store of knowledge.1 I do not mean merely that what we add is often accepted from persons who have already contributed to our knowledge; beyond that, we have acquired habits of thought, tendencies to suspect and tendencies to approve both other-person-reports and purported perceptions, from our testimonial (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Critical Notice.Elizabeth Fricker - 1995 - Mind 104 (414):393 - 411.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  • Knowledge, Truth and Evidence.Keith Lehrer - 1965 - Analysis 25 (5):168 - 175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • How Do You Know?Ernest Sosa - 1974 - American Philosophical Quarterly 11 (2):113 - 122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The Place of Testimony in the Fabric of Knowledge and Justification.Robert Audi - 1997 - American Philosophical Quarterly 34 (4):405 - 422.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   130 citations  
  • ``Knowing and Asserting".Timothy Williamson - 1996 - Philosophical Review 105 (4):489-523.
    Assertions are praised as true, informative, relevant, sincere, warranted, well-phrased, or polite. They are criticized as false, uninformative, irrelevant, insincere, unwarranted, ill-phrased, or rude. Sometimes they deserve such praise or criticism. If any respect in which performances of an act can deserve praise or criticism is a norm for that act, then the speech act of assertion has many norms. So has almost any act; jumps can deserve praise as long or brave, criticism as short or cowardly. But it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   159 citations  
  • Reasons and knowledge.Marshall Swain - 1981 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Davidson's theism?Richard Foley & Richard Fumerton - 1985 - Philosophical Studies 48 (1):83 - 89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The transmission of knowledge.Michael Welbourne - 1979 - Philosophical Quarterly 29 (114):1-9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations