Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. One more time on the alleged repugnance of Kant's ethics? Schiller's Kallias letters and the entirety of the human being.Antonino Falduto - 2020 - European Journal of Philosophy 29 (4):795-810.
    European Journal of Philosophy, Volume 29, Issue 4, Page 795-810, December 2021.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Schiller on Freedom and Aesthetic Value: Part I.Samantha Matherne & Nick Riggle - 2020 - British Journal of Aesthetics 60 (4):375-402.
    In his Letters on the Aesthetic Education of Man, Friedrich Schiller draws a striking connection between aesthetic value and individual and political freedom, claiming that, ‘it is only through beauty that man makes his way to freedom’. However, contemporary ways of thinking about freedom and aesthetic value make it difficult to see what the connection could be. Through a careful reconstruction of the Letters, we argue that Schiller’s theory of aesthetic value serves as the key to understanding not only his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Authority and Coercion.Arthur Ripstein - 2004 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 32 (1):2-35.
    I am grateful to Donald Ainslie, Lisa Austin, Michael Blake, Abraham Drassinower, David Dyzenhaus, George Fletcher, Robert Gibbs, Louis-Philippe Hodgson, Sari Kisilevsky, Dennis Klimchuk, Christopher Morris, Scott Shapiro, Horacio Spector, Sergio Tenenbaum, Malcolm Thorburn, Ernest Weinrib, Karen Weisman, and the Editors of Philosophy & Public Affairs for comments, and audiences in the UCLA Philosophy Department and Columbia Law School for their questions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • An Unfamiliar and Positive Law: On Kant and Schiller.Reed Winegar - 2013 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 95 (3):275-297.
    A familiar post-Kantian criticism contends that Kant enslaves sensibility under the yoke of practical reason. Friedrich Schiller advanced a version of this criticism to which Kant publicly responded. Recent commentators have emphasized the role that Kant’s reply assigns to the pleasure that accompanies successful moral action. In contrast, I argue that Kant’s reply relies primarily on the sublime feeling that arises when we merely contemplate the moral law. In fact, the pleasures emphasized by other recent commentators depend on this sublime (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Inclusive Interpretation of Kant's Aesthetic Ideas.Samantha Matherne - 2013 - British Journal of Aesthetics 53 (1):21-39.
    In the Critique of the Power of Judgment, Kant offers a theory of artistic expression in which he claims that a work of art is a medium through which an artist expresses an ‘aesthetic idea’. While Kant’s theory of aesthetic ideas often receives rather restrictive interpretations, according to which aesthetic ideas can either present only moral concepts, or only moral concepts and purely rational concepts, in this article I offer an ‘inclusive interpretation’ of aesthetic ideas, according to which they can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The Aesthetics of Morality: Schiller’s Critique of Kantian Rationalism.Anne Margaret Baxley - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (12):1084-1095.
    Philosophers often mention Friedrich Schiller as the author of a famous epigram taking aim at Kant’s account of moral motivation: Gladly I serve my friends, but alas I do it with pleasure. Hence I am plagued with doubt that I am not a virtuous person. To this, the answer is given: Surely, your only resource is to try to despise them entirely, And then with aversion do what your duty enjoins. These joking lines capture a natural objection to Kant’s rationalist (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Schiller and the dance of beauty.Stephen Houlgate - 2008 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 51 (1):37 – 49.
    Frederick Beiser’s study, Schiller as Philosopher, is a work of outstanding philosophical intelligence and exemplary scholarship. This is good news for the student of Schiller. It is, however, somewhat less good news for the aspiring critic of Beiser—at least for this aspiring critic, for there is little that I disagree with, and a very great deal that I admire, in Beiser’s book. Particularly valuable—to mention just one of the book’s many merits—is Beiser’s subtle and illuminating account of the relation between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • "The beautiful is the symbol of the morally-good": Kant's philosophical basis of proof for the idea of the morally-good.G. Felicitas Munzel - 1995 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (2):301-330.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Aesthetics from Classical Greece to the Present: A Short History.Monroe C. Beardsley - 1966 - Philosophy 43 (163):63-65.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Ideology of the Aesthetic.Terry Eagleton - 1991 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 49 (3):259-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • Aesthetic Education for Morality: Schiller and Kant.Zvi Tauber - 2006 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 40 (3):22-47.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Schiller as philosopher: A reply to my critics.Frederick Beiser - 2008 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 51 (1):63 – 78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Beautiful Soul and the Autocratic Agent: Schiller's and Kant's "Children of the House".Anne Margaret Baxley - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (4):493-514.
    In his extended essay "On Grace and Dignity," Friedrich Schiller sets out an important challenge to Kant when he argues that sensibility must play a constitutive role in the ethical life. This paper argues that there is much we can learn from Schiller's "corrective" to Kant's moral theory and Kant's reply to this critique, for what is at stake in their debate are rival conceptions of the proper state of moral health for us as finite rational beings and competing political (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • “Constrained neither physically nor morally”: Schiller, Aesthetic Freedom, and the Power of Play.Karen E. Davis - 2021 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 55 (2):36-50.
    The general conceit of Schiller’s aesthetic education is that our experiences with art and beauty set us free from internal and external constraints and allow us to embrace our full humanity as rational and sensuous beings. Experiencing the aesthetic, or the play impulse, puts one in a state of aesthetic determinacy—or rather indeterminacy—that Schiller calls the highest sense of freedom, aesthetic freedom. Gail K. Hart examines Anthony Burgess’s A Clockwork Orange as an example of what Schillerian aesthetic education might look (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Heautonomy: Schiller on freedom of the will.Jörg Noller - 2020 - European Journal of Philosophy 29 (2):339-353.
    In his book “Schiller as Philosopher”, Frederick Beiser laments that “contemporary Kant scholars have been intent on ignoring him. If they know anything at all about Schiller, it is only as the author of an epigram satirizing Kant”. Therefore, Beiser calls us “to consider Schiller as a philosopher, to reconstruct and appraise the arguments of his philosophical writings” (Beiser, 2005, p. vii). In this paper, I shall argue that it is Schiller's conception of freedom of the will as “heautonomy” that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Schiller's aesthetic republicanism.Douglas Moggach - 2007 - History of Political Thought 28 (3):520-541.
    The paper examines the political implications of Schiller's On the Aesthetic Education of Man (1795). Schiller's thought has frequently been depicted as a flight from contemporary conditions of revolution and war, but his aesthetic ideas are closely connected to his assessment of political emancipation and they contribute to a new kind of republican thought. While earlier eighteenth-century republicanisms had presupposed, or attempted to enforce, homogeneity of interest among the citizen body, Schiller acknowledges modern diversity, resulting from new relationships in civil (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Friedrich Schiller on republican virtue and the tragic exemplar.Jeffrey Church - 2014 - European Journal of Political Theory 13 (1):95-118.
    Scholars have recently argued that Friedrich Schiller makes a signal contribution to republican political theory in his view of “aesthetic education,” which offers a means of elevating self-interest to virtue. However, though this education is lauded in theory, it has been denigrated as implausible, irresponsible, or dangerous in practice. This paper argues that the criticisms rest on a faulty assumption that artistic objects constitute the sole substance of this “aesthetic education.” Through a reading of Schiller’s work throughout the 1790s, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Freedom and Autonomy in Schiller.Sabine Roehr - 2003 - Journal of the History of Ideas 64 (1):119-134.
    This essay provides a systematic as well as chronological account of Schiller's concepts of freedom and autonomy. Its main thesis is that the duality of Schiller's moral/aesthetic ideal in the Letters on the Aesthetic Education of Man - of beauty and the sublime, of play and the moral law - is a result of his use of conflicting concepts of autonomy. While it is widely accepted that Schiller took over Kant's concept of autonomy, I argue that he simultaneously employed another (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The liberty of the ancients? Friedrich Schiller and aesthetic republicanism.Alexander Schmidt - 2009 - History of Political Thought 30 (2):286-314.
    Schiller's political thought has been subject to conflicting interpretations. Taking Schiller's historical essay The Legislation of Lycurgus and Solon as a point of departure, this article locates him more precisely within the context of eighteenth-century debates on republicanism and moral philosophy. One of Schiller's central criteria in the evaluation of different republics is the question of how they comply with man's sensual and passionate nature. By attacking Sparta's constitution as despotic and unfit to meet human self-realization, he dissociated himself from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Schiller, scots and germans: Freedom and diversity in the aesthetic education of man.Douglas Moggach - 2008 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 51 (1):16 – 36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Aesthetic Dimension.John Fisher & Herbert Marcuse - 1979 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 13 (2):119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Pleasure, freedom and grace: Schiller's “completion” of Kant's ethics.Anne Margaret Baxley - 2008 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 51 (1):1 – 15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Grace as Guide to Morals? Schiller's Aesthetic Turn in Ethics.Katerina Deligiorgi - 2006 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 23 (1):1 - 20.
    Our philosophical moral vocabulary expresses a predilection for depth; we customarily probe feelings, intentions, reasons for action. Friedrich Schiller's concept of grace offers an alternative: moral guidance is best sought in what we train ourselves to set aside, facial expression, sound of voice, movement. This surprising proposal merits our attention and speaks to some of our current concerns.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations