Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Scientific reasoning: the Bayesian approach.Peter Urbach & Colin Howson - 1993 - Chicago: Open Court. Edited by Peter Urbach.
    Scientific reasoning is—and ought to be—conducted in accordance with the axioms of probability. This Bayesian view—so called because of the central role it accords to a theorem first proved by Thomas Bayes in the late eighteenth ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   573 citations  
  • Bayesian Epistemology.Luc Bovens & Stephan Hartmann - 2003 - Oxford: Oxford University Press. Edited by Stephan Hartmann.
    Probabilistic models have much to offer to philosophy. We continually receive information from a variety of sources: from our senses, from witnesses, from scientific instruments. When considering whether we should believe this information, we assess whether the sources are independent, how reliable they are, and how plausible and coherent the information is. Bovens and Hartmann provide a systematic Bayesian account of these features of reasoning. Simple Bayesian Networks allow us to model alternative assumptions about the nature of the information sources. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   339 citations  
  • Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems: Networks of Plausible Inference.Judea Pearl - 1988 - Morgan Kaufmann.
    The book can also be used as an excellent text for graduate-level courses in AI, operations research, or applied probability.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   424 citations  
  • Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology.Rudolf Carnap - 1950 - Bobbs-Merrill.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   392 citations  
  • [no title].Jeremy Butterfield & John Earman - 1977
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   367 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Structure of Science.Ernest Nagel - 1961 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 17 (2):275-275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   888 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology.Rudolf Carnap - 1950 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 4 (11):20-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   562 citations  
  • General semantics.David K. Lewis - 1970 - Synthese 22 (1-2):18--67.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   640 citations  
  • Discovery and explanation in biology and medicine.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1993 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    Kenneth F. Schaffner compares the practice of biological and medical research and shows how traditional topics in philosophy of science—such as the nature of theories and of explanation—can illuminate the life sciences. While Schaffner pays some attention to the conceptual questions of evolutionary biology, his chief focus is on the examples that immunology, human genetics, neuroscience, and internal medicine provide for examinations of the way scientists develop, examine, test, and apply theories. Although traditional philosophy of science has regarded scientific discovery—the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   230 citations  
  • Biological Complexity and Integrative Pluralism.Sandra D. Mitchell - 2003 - Cambridge University Press.
    This fine collection of essays by a leading philosopher of science presents a defence of integrative pluralism as the best description for the complexity of scientific inquiry today. The tendency of some scientists to unify science by reducing all theories to a few fundamental laws of the most basic particles that populate our universe is ill-suited to the biological sciences, which study multi-component, multi-level, evolved complex systems. This integrative pluralism is the most efficient way to understand the different and complex (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   197 citations  
  • Philosophy of Natural Science.Carl G. Hempel - 1967 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 18 (1):70-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   582 citations  
  • Philosophy of Experimental Biology.Marcel Weber - 2004 - Cambridge University Press.
    Philosophy of Experimental Biology explores some central philosophical issues concerning scientific research in experimental biology, including genetics, biochemistry, molecular biology, developmental biology, neurobiology, and microbiology. It seeks to make sense of the explanatory strategies, concepts, ways of reasoning, approaches to discovery and problem solving, tools, models and experimental systems deployed by scientific life science researchers and also integrates developments in historical scholarship, in particular the New Experimentalism. It concludes that historical explanations of scientific change that are based on local laboratory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   168 citations  
  • (1 other version)The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English.Richard Montague - 1973 - In Patrick Suppes, Julius Moravcsik & Jaakko Hintikka, Approaches to Natural Language. Dordrecht. pp. 221--242.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   364 citations  
  • Universal grammar.Richard Montague - 1970 - Theoria 36 (3):373--398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   327 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Proper Treatment of Quantification in Ordinary English.Richard Montague - 1974 - In Richmond H. Thomason, Formal Philosophy. Yale University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   425 citations  
  • Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems: Networks of Plausible Inference.J. Pearl, F. Bacchus, P. Spirtes, C. Glymour & R. Scheines - 1988 - Synthese 104 (1):161-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   254 citations  
  • Interfield theories.Lindley Darden & Nancy Maull - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (1):43-64.
    This paper analyzes the generation and function of hitherto ignored or misrepresented interfield theories , theories which bridge two fields of science. Interfield theories are likely to be generated when two fields share an interest in explaining different aspects of the same phenomenon and when background knowledge already exists relating the two fields. The interfield theory functions to provide a solution to a characteristic type of theoretical problem: how are the relations between fields to be explained? In solving this problem (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   270 citations  
  • English as a Formal Language.Richard Montague - 1970 - In B. Visentini, Linguaggi Nella Societ\'{a} e Nella Tecnica'. Edizioni di Communita. pp. 188-221.
    I reject the contention that an important theoretical difference exists between formal and natural languages.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   183 citations  
  • Approaches to reduction.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1967 - Philosophy of Science 34 (2):137-147.
    Four current accounts of theory reduction are presented, first informally and then formally: (1) an account of direct theory reduction that is based on the contributions of Nagel, Woodger, and Quine, (2) an indirect reduction paradigm due to Kemeny and Oppenheim, (3) an "isomorphic model" schema traceable to Suppes, and (4) a theory of reduction that is based on the work of Popper, Feyerabend, and Kuhn. Reference is made, in an attempt to choose between these schemas, to the explanation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   231 citations  
  • The plurality of bayesian measures of confirmation and the problem of measure sensitivity.Branden Fitelson - 1999 - Philosophy of Science 66 (3):378.
    Contemporary Bayesian confirmation theorists measure degree of (incremental) confirmation using a variety of non-equivalent relevance measures. As a result, a great many of the arguments surrounding quantitative Bayesian confirmation theory are implicitly sensitive to choice of measure of confirmation. Such arguments are enthymematic, since they tacitly presuppose that certain relevance measures should be used (for various purposes) rather than other relevance measures that have been proposed and defended in the philosophical literature. I present a survey of this pervasive class of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   261 citations  
  • Who’s Afraid of Nagelian Reduction?Foad Dizadji-Bahmani, Roman Frigg & Stephan Hartmann - 2010 - Erkenntnis 73 (3):393-412.
    We reconsider the Nagelian theory of reduction and argue that, contrary to a widely held view, it is the right analysis of intertheoretic reduction. The alleged difficulties of the theory either vanish upon closer inspection or turn out to be substantive philosophical questions rather than knock-down arguments.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • Logics and Languages.Max Cresswell - 1973 - London, England: Routledge.
    Originally published in 1973, this book shows that methods developed for the semantics of systems of formal logic can be successfully applied to problems about the semantics of natural languages; and, moreover, that such methods can take account of features of natural language which have often been thought incapable of formal treatment, such as vagueness, context dependence and metaphorical meaning. Parts 1 and 2 set out a class of formal languages and their semantics. Parts 3 and 4 show that these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  • (1 other version)A formulation of the simple theory of types.Alonzo Church - 1940 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 5 (2):56-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   228 citations  
  • (1 other version)Discovery and Explanation in Biology and Medicine.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1995 - Journal of the History of Biology 28 (1):172-174.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  • (1 other version)On reduction.John Kemeny & Paul Oppenheim - 1956 - Philosophical Studies 7 (1-2):6 - 19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   131 citations  
  • (1 other version)Discovery and Explanation in Biology and Medicine.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1995 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46 (4):621-623.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   158 citations  
  • (1 other version)A Formulation of the Simple Theory of Types.Alonzo Church - 1940 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 5 (3):114-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   150 citations  
  • (1 other version)Logische Syntax der Sprache.R. Carnap - 1936 - Philosophy 11 (41):110-114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  • (1 other version)Models and Stories in Hadron Physics.Stephan Hartmann - 1999 - In Mary S. Morgan & Margaret Morrison, Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science. Cambridge University Press. pp. 52--326.
    Fundamental theories are hard to come by. But even if we had them, they would be too complicated to apply. Quantum chromodynamics is a case in point. This theory is supposed to govern all strong interactions, but it is extremely hard to apply and test at energies where protons, neutrons and ions are the effective degrees of freedom. Instead, scientists typically use highly idealized models such as the MIT Bag Model or the Nambu Jona-Lasinio Model to account for phenomena in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • (1 other version)Undecidable Theories.Alfred Tarski, Andrzej Mostowski & Raphael M. Robinson - 1953 - Philosophy 30 (114):278-279.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  • Bayesian Epistemology.Stephan Hartmann & Jan Sprenger - 2010 - In Sven Bernecker & Duncan Pritchard, The Routledge Companion to Epistemology. New York: Routledge. pp. 609-620.
    Bayesian epistemology addresses epistemological problems with the help of the mathematical theory of probability. It turns out that the probability calculus is especially suited to represent degrees of belief (credences) and to deal with questions of belief change, confirmation, evidence, justification, and coherence. Compared to the informal discussions in traditional epistemology, Bayesian epis- temology allows for a more precise and fine-grained analysis which takes the gradual aspects of these central epistemological notions into account. Bayesian epistemology therefore complements traditional epistemology; it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • (1 other version)Logics and Languages.M. J. Cresswell - 1973 - Synthese 40 (2):375-387.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • Goal-directed processes in biology.Ernest Nagel - 1977 - Journal of Philosophy 74 (5):261-279.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • Teleology Revisited.Ernest Nagel - 1977 - Journal of Philosophy 74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • Categorial Type Logics.Michael Moortgat - 1997 - In J. F. A. K. Van Benthem, Johan van Benthem & Alice G. B. Ter Meulen, Handbook of Logic and Language. Elsevier.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Formal Philosophy: Selected Papers of Richard Montague.Richmond H. Thomason & Richard Montague - 1976 - Foundations of Language 14 (3):413-418.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • Semantics and property theory.Gennaro Chierchia & Raymond Turner - 1988 - Linguistics and Philosophy 11 (3):261 - 302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • Bayesian Epistemology.Alan Hájek & Stephan Hartmann - 1992 - In Jonathan Dancy & Ernest Sosa, A Companion to Epistemology. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    Bayesianism is our leading theory of uncertainty. Epistemology is defined as the theory of knowledge. So “Bayesian Epistemology” may sound like an oxymoron. Bayesianism, after all, studies the properties and dynamics of degrees of belief, understood to be probabilities. Traditional epistemology, on the other hand, places the singularly non-probabilistic notion of knowledge at centre stage, and to the extent that it traffics in belief, that notion does not come in degrees. So how can there be a Bayesian epistemology?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • (1 other version)Logics and Language.M. J. Cresswell - 1973 - Mind 84 (336):623-625.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Confirmation and Reduction: a Bayesian Account.Foad Dizadji-Bahmani, Roman Frigg & Stephan Hartmann - 2010 - Synthese 179 (2):321-338.
    Various scientific theories stand in a reductive relation to each other. In a recent article, we have argued that a generalized version of the Nagel-Schaffner model (GNS) is the right account of this relation. In this article, we present a Bayesian analysis of how GNS impacts on confirmation. We formalize the relation between the reducing and the reduced theory before and after the reduction using Bayesian networks, and thereby show that, post-reduction, the two theories are confirmatory of each other. We (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Reductionism in Biology: Prospects and Problems.Kenneth F. Schaffner - 1974 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1974:613 - 632.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • (1 other version)Montague Grammar.H. L. W. Hendriks & B. Partee - 1997 - In J. F. A. K. Van Benthem, Johan van Benthem & Alice G. B. Ter Meulen, Handbook of Logic and Language. Elsevier. pp. 5-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • (1 other version)Comments and Criticism: Measuring Confirmation and Evidence.Ellery Eells & Branden Fitelson - 2000 - Journal of Philosophy 97 (12):663-672.
    Bayesian epistemology suggests various ways of measuring the support that a piece of evidence provides a hypothesis. Such measures are defined in terms of a subjective probability assignment, pr, over propositions entertained by an agent. The most standard measure (where “H” stands for “hypothesis” and “E” stands for “evidence”) is: the difference measure: d(H,E) = pr(H/E) - pr(H).0 This may be called a “positive (probabilistic) relevance measure” of confirmation, since, according to it, a piece of evidence E qualitatively confirms a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • (1 other version)Montague Grammar.Barbara H. Partee - 1980 - Journal of Philosophy 77 (5):278-312.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Replacing one theory by another under preservation of a given feature.Rolf A. Eberle - 1971 - Philosophy of Science 38 (4):486-501.
    The conditions are examined under which one theory is said to be replaceable by another, while preserving those features of the original theory which made it serviceable for a given purpose. Among such replacements, special attention is given to ones which qualify as so-called reductions of a theory, and some theorems are proved concerning the notion of a reduction.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Dialectics and reductionism in ecology.Richard Levins & Richard Lewontin - 1980 - Synthese 43 (1):47 - 78.
    Biology above the level of the individual organism ? population ecology and genetics, community ecology, biogeography and evolution ? requires the study of intrinsically complex systems. But the dominant philosophies of western science have proven to be inadequate for the study of complexity:(1)The reductionist myth of simplicity leads its advocates to isolate parts as completely as possible and study these parts. It underestimates the importance of interactions in theory, and its recommendations for practice (in agricultural programs or conservation and environmental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Semantic Structures.Renate Bartsch & Theo Vennemann - 1974 - Foundations of Language 12 (2):287-289.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • (1 other version)Models and stories in Hadron physics.Stephan Hartmann - 1999 - In Mary S. Morgan & Margaret Morrison, Models as Mediators: Perspectives on Natural and Social Science. Cambridge University Press. pp. 326-346.
    Fundamental theories are hard to come by. But even if we had them, they would be too complicated to apply. Quantum chromodynamics (QCD) is a case in point. This theory is supposed to govern all strong interactions, but it is extremely hard to apply and test at energies where protons, neutrons and ions are the effective degrees of freedom. Instead, scientists typically use highly idealized models such as the MIT Bag Model or the Nambu Jona-Lasinio Model to account for phenomena (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • An Extension of Classical Transformational Grammar.Emmon Bach - unknown
    0. Introductory remarks. I assume that every serious theory of language must give some explicit account of the relationship between expressions in the language described and expressions in some interpreted language which spells out the semantics of the language.1 Let's call this relationship the translation relation. Theories differ as to how this relation is specified. In the Aspects theory of syntax, taken together with a Katz-Postal view of "semantic rules", it was assumed that the relation was defined on deep structures. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Matter of the Mind: Philosophical Essays on Psychology, Neuroscience and Reduction.Maurice Schouten & Huib Looren de Jong (eds.) - 2007 - Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
    The _Matter of the Mind_ addresses and illuminates the relationship between psychology and neuroscience by focusing on the topic of reduction. Written by leading philosophers in the field Discusses recent theorizing in the mind-brain sciences and reviews and weighs the evidence in favour of reductionism against the backdrop of recent important advances within psychology and the neurosciences Collects the latest work on central topics where neuroscience is now making inroads in traditional psychological terrain, such as adaptive behaviour, reward systems, consciousness, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations