Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized.James Ladyman & Don Ross - 2007 - In James Ladyman & Don Ross, Every thing must go: metaphysics naturalized. New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book argues that the only kind of metaphysics that can contribute to objective knowledge is one based specifically on contemporary science as it really is, and not on philosophers' a priori intuitions, common sense, or simplifications of science. In addition to showing how recent metaphysics has drifted away from connection with all other serious scholarly inquiry as a result of not heeding this restriction, this book demonstrates how to build a metaphysics compatible with current fundamental physics, which, when combined (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   790 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The Existence of God.Richard Swinburne - 1979 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Richard Swinburne presents a substantially rewritten and updated edition of his most celebrated book. No other work has made a more powerful case for the probability of the existence of God. Swinburne gives a rigorous and penetrating analysis of the most important arguments for theism: the cosmological argument; arguments from the existence of laws of nature and the 'fine-tuning' of the universe; from the occurrence of consciousness and moral awareness; and from miracles and religious experience. He claims that while none (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   262 citations  
  • In defence of scientism.Don Ross, James Ladyman & David Spurrett - 2007 - In James Ladyman & Don Ross, Every thing must go: metaphysics naturalized. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   114 citations  
  • The Applicability of Mathematics as a Philosophical Problem.Mark Steiner - 2000 - Mind 109 (434):390-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • Should CSR Give Atheists Epistemic Assurance? On Beer-Goggles, BFFs, and Skepticism Regarding Religious Beliefs.Justin L. Barrett & Ian M. Church - 2013 - The Monist 96 (3):311-324.
    Recent work in cognitive science of religion (CSR) is beginning to converge on a very interesting thesis—that, given the ordinary features of human minds operating in typical human environments, we are naturally disposed to believe in the existence of gods, among other religious ideas (e.g., seeAtran [2002], Barrett [2004; 2012], Bering [2011], Boyer [2001], Guthrie [1993], McCauley [2011], Pyysiäinen [2004; 2009]). In this paper, we explore whether such a discovery ultimately helps or hurts the atheist position—whether, for example, it lends (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • How to be an Anti-Realist.Alvin Plantinga - 1982 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 56 (1):47 - 70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Divine necessity.Robert Merrihew Adams - 1983 - Journal of Philosophy 80 (11):741-752.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The Lord of Noncontradiction: An Argument for God from Logic.James N. Anderson & Greg Welty - 2011 - Philosophia Christi 13 (2):321 - 338.
    In this paper we offer a new argument for the existence of God. We contend that the laws of logic are metaphysically dependent on the existence of God, understood as a necessarily existent, personal, spiritual being; thus anyone who grants that there are laws of logic should also accept that there is a God. We argue that if our most natural intuitions about them are correct, and if they are to play the role in our intellectual activities that we take (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Against Naturalized Cognitive Propositions.Lorraine Juliano Keller - 2017 - Erkenntnis 82 (4):929-946.
    In this paper, I argue that Scott Soames’ theory of naturalized cognitive propositions faces a serious objection: there are true propositions for which NCP cannot account. More carefully, NCP cannot account for certain truths of mathematics unless it is possible for there to be an infinite intellect. For those who reject the possibility of an infinite intellect, this constitutes a reductio of NCP.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Consensus Gentium: Reflections on the 'Common Consent' Argument for the Existence of God.Thomas Kelly - 2011 - In Raymond VanArragon & Kelly James Clark, Evidence and Religious Belief. Oxford, US: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (5 other versions)Philosophical Explanations. [REVIEW]Robert Nozick - 1981 - Ethics 94 (2):326-327.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   741 citations  
  • The Argument from Consciousness.J. P. Moreland - 2009 - In William Lane Craig & J. P. Moreland, The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 282–343.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Section One: The Backdrop for Locating Consciousness in a Naturalist Ontology Section Two: The AC Section Three: John Searle and Contingent Correlation Section Four: Timothy O'Connor and Emergent Necessitation Section Five: Colin McGinn and Mysterian “Naturalism” Conclusion Further Reading References.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • (1 other version)Value and Existence.John Leslie - 1980 - Philosophy 55 (212):275-277.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The ontological argument and the motivational centres of lives.Alexander R. Pruss - 2010 - Religious Studies 46 (2):233-249.
    Assuming S₅, the main controversial premise in modal ontological arguments is the possibility premise, such as that possibly a maximally great being exists. I shall offer a new way of arguing that the possibility premise is probably true.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Can Atheism Be Epistemically Responsible When So Many People Believe in God?Sébasten Réhault - 2015 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 7 (1):181--198.
    Nowadays the argument for the existence of God based on the common consent of mankind is taken to be so bad that contemporary atheists do not even bother to mention it. And it seems very few theists think that the argument is worth defending. In this paper I shall argue to the contrary: not only is the argument better than usually thought, but widespread belief in God constitutes a prima facie defeater for every reasonable atheist.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Value and Existence.William J. Wainwright - 1981 - Philosophical Review 90 (2):318.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • (1 other version)Infinite Minds: A Philosophical Cosmology.John Leslie - 2001 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 194 (4):491-491.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Theological realism, divine action, and divine location.Andrei A. Buckareff - 2016 - In Andrei A. Buckareff & Yujin Nagasawa, Alternative Concepts of God: Essays on the Metaphysics of the Divine. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Infinite Minds, a Philosophical Cosmology.John Leslie - 2001 - Philosophy 77 (302):625-634.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Regularities, Laws of Nature, and the Existence of God.John Foster - 2001 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 101 (1):145-161.
    The regularities in nature, simply by being regularities, call for explanation. There are only two ways in which we could, with any plausibility, try to explain them. One way would be to suppose that they are imposed on the world by God. The other would be to suppose that they reflect the presence of laws of nature, conceived of as forms of natural necessity. But the only way of making sense of the notion of a law of nature, thus conceived, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • A Modal-Epistemic Argument for the Existence of God.Emanuel Rutten - 2014 - Faith and Philosophy 31 (4):386-400.
    I propose a new argument for the existence of God. God is defined as a conscious being that is the first cause of reality. In its simplified initial form, the argument has two premises: all possible truths are knowable, and it is impossible to know that the proposition that God does not exist is true. From and it follows that the proposition that God exists is necessarily true. After introducing the argument in its crude initial form and laying out the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • By Whose Authority: A Political Argument for God's Existence.Tyler McNabb & Jeremy Neill - 2019 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 11 (2):163-189.
    In The Problem of Political Authority, Michael Huemer argues that the contractarian and consequentialist groundings of political authority are unsuccessful, and, in fact, that there are no adequate contemporary accounts of political authority. As such, the modern state is illegitimate and we have reasons to affirm political anarchism. We disagree with Huemer’s conclusion. But we consider Huemer’s critiques of contractarianism and consequentialism to be compelling. Here we will juxtapose, alongside Huemer’s critiques, a theistic account of political authority from Nicholas Wolterstorff’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is the fact that other people believe in God a reason to believe? Remarks on the consensus gentium argument.Marek Dobrzeniecki - 2018 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 10 (3):133-153.
    According to The Consensus Gentium Argument from the premise: “Everyone believes that God exists” one can conclude that God does exist. In my paper I analyze two ways of defending the claim that somebody’s belief in God is a prima facie reason to believe. Kelly takes the fact of the commonness of the belief in God as a datum to explain and argues that the best explanation has to indicate the truthfulness of the theistic belief. Trinkaus Zagzebski grounds her defence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Argument from Reason.Victor Reppert - 1999 - Philo 2 (1):33-45.
    In this paper I argue that the existence of human reason gives us good reason to suppose that God exists. If the world were as the materialist supposes it is, then we would not be able to reason to the conclusion that this is so. This contention is often challenged by the claim that mental and physical explanations can be given for the same event. But a close examination of the question of explanatory compatibility reveals that the sort of explanation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • No God, No Powers.James Orr - 2019 - International Philosophical Quarterly 59 (4):411-426.
    One common feature of debates about the best metaphysical analysis of putatively lawful phenomena is the suspicion that nomic realists who locate the modal force of such phenomena in quasi-causal necessitation relations between universals are working with a model of law that cannot convincingly erase its theological pedigree. Nancy Cartwright distills this criticism into slogan form: no God, no laws. Some have argued that a more plausible alternative for nomic realists who reject theism is to ground laws of nature in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • God and the Platonic Horde.Richard Davis - 2011 - Philosophia Christi 13 (2):289-303.
    In this paper I shall argue two things. First, it is plausible to think that Conceptualism holds with respect to propositions; in any event, it does a much better job than its closest competitors (Platonism and Nominalism) in accounting for the truthbearing nature of propositions. Secondly, it is wholly implausible (so I say) to take the added step and equate properties and relations with divine concepts. Here I offer additional reasons, beyond “divine bootstrapping,” for theists to resist this tempting reduction. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Omnificence.John Bigelow - 2005 - Analysis 65 (3):187-196.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Relations between universals,or divine laws?Richard Swinburne - 2006 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (2):179 – 189.
    Armstrong's theory of laws of nature as relations between universals gives an initially plausible account of why the causal powers of substances are bound together only in certain ways, so that the world is a very regular place. But its resulting theory of causation cannot account for intentional causation, since this involves an agent trying to do something, and trying is causing. This kind of causation is thus a state of an agent and does not involve the operation of a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • (1 other version)A Realist Conception of Truth.[author unknown] - 1997 - Philosophical Quarterly 47 (189):512-518.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Epistemic self-trust and the consensus gentium argument.Linda Zagzebski - 2011 - In Raymond VanArragon & Kelly James Clark, Evidence and Religious Belief. Oxford, US: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Does God Exist Because He Ought To Exist?William F. Vallicella - 2018 - In Mirosław Szatkowski, Ontology of Theistic Beliefs: Meta-Ontological Perspectives. De Gruyter. pp. 205-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • God and Modal Concretism.Richard Davis - 2008 - Philosophia Christi 10 (1):57-74.
    According to David Lewis, we all believe there are countless ways in which things might have been different from the way they are in fact. Surely, for example, the world could have existed even if, say, Quine had been a politician, or if there had been one less page in Word and Object, or indeed if there had been no such person as Quine at all. All these things, we are inclined to think, might have been the case. And thus (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Perceiving God through Natural Beauty.Ryan West & Adam C. Pelser - 2015 - Faith and Philosophy 32 (3):293-312.
    In Perceiving God, William Alston briefly suggests the possibility of perceiving God indirectly through the perception of another object. Following recent work by C. Stephen Evans, we argue that Thomas Reid’s notion of “natural signs” helpfully illuminates how people can perceive God indirectly through natural beauty. First, we explain how some natural signs enable what Alston labels “indirect perception.” Second, we explore how certain emotions make it possible to see both beauty and the excellence of the minds behind beauty. Finally, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Reality of Time and the Existence of God: The Project of Proving God's Existence.David BRAINE - 1988 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 178 (4):495-496.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Conceptualist Argument for God's Existence.Quentin Smith - 1994 - Faith and Philosophy 11 (1):38-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • No God, No Laws.Nancy Cartwright - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • What Is Naturalism? And Should We Be Naturalists?William Hasker - 2013 - Philosophia Christi 15 (1):21-34.
    It seems reasonable to seek a definition of naturalism, yet an accurate general definition proves to be elusive. After considering proposals from Quine, Nagel, and Chalmers, I propose that naturalism as understood by the majority of contemporary naturalists is best defined by the conjunction of mind-body supervenience, an understanding of the physical as mechanistic, and the causal closure of the physical domain. I then argue that naturalism so defined is in principle unable to account for the existence of rationality; it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A deontic argument for God's existence.Carl R. Kordig - 1981 - Noûs 15 (2):207-208.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Philosophical Theology.Rufus M. Jones & F. R. Tennant - 1930 - Philosophical Review 39 (1):96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Theism and epistemic truth-equivalences.Michael C. Rea - 2000 - Noûs 34 (2):291–301.
    This paper defends the conclusion that every epistemic truth equivalence entails "near theism"--the view that (i) there exists a necessarily existent rational community and (ii) necessarily, there exists an omnisicent community.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Riddle of Existence: An Essay in Idealistic Metaphysics. Nicholas Rescher.John Leslie - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (3):485-486.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Atheism and Theism.Hugh J. McCann, J. J. C. Smart & J. J. Haldane - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (3):462.
    In this volume, the sixth in Blackwell's Great Debates in Philosophy series, Smart and Haldane discuss the case for and against religious belief. The debate is unusual in beginning with the negative side. After a short jointly authored introduction, there is a fairly extended presentation of the atheist position by Smart. Haldane then offers an equally extended defense of theism. The authors respond to one another in the same order, and the book concludes with a brief co-authored treatment of antirealism, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Breaking Laws of Nature.Jeffrey Koperski - 2017 - Philosophia Christi 19 (1):83-101.
    One of the main arguments against interventionist views of special divine action is that God would not violate his own laws. But if intervention entails the breaking of natural law, what precisely is being broken? While the nature of the laws of nature has been widely explored by philosophers of science, important distinctions are often ignored in the science and religion literature. In this paper, I consider the three main approaches to laws: Humean anti-realism, supervenience on more fundamental aspects of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Theory That the World Exists Because It Should.John Leslie - 1970 - American Philosophical Quarterly 7 (4):286 - 298.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Scientific Outlook.Hugh Rice - 2000 - In Hugh Ashton Lawrence Rice, God and Goodness. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Argues that the ordinary scientific outlook is not characterized by the sort of metaphysical hygiene and epistemological security that are sometimes thought of as the goals of empiricism. It is committed to a belief in order; it is committed to a belief in rationality—that some reasons for beliefs are good reasons, and some bad; it is committed to explanation. These commitments, I shall be arguing, provide a foundation for a belief in God.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Propositions Supernaturalized.Lorraine Juliano Keller - 2018 - In J. Walls & T. Dougherty, Two Dozen (or so) Arguments for God. New York, New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 11-28.
    The Theistic Argument from Intentionality (TAI) is a venerable argument for the existence of God from the existence of eternal truths. The argument relies, inter alia, on the premises that (i) truth requires representation, and that (ii) non-derivative representation is a function of, and only of, minds. If propositions are the fundamental bearers of truth and falsity, then these premises entail that propositions (or at least their representational properties) depend on minds. Although it is widely thought that psychologism—the view that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Two ‘Proofs’ of God's Existence: A. C. EWING.A. C. Ewing - 1965 - Religious Studies 1 (1):29-45.
    I do not think that the existence of God can be proved or even that the main justification for the belief can be found in argument in the ordinary sense of that term, but I think two of the three which have, since Kant at least, been classified as the traditional arguments of natural theology have some force and are worthy of serious consideration. This consideration I shall now proceed to give. I cannot say this of the remaining one of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Law and Thomistic Exemplarism.John Peterson - 1996 - The Thomist 60 (1):81-108.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:LAW AND THOMISTIC EXEMPLARISM JOHN PETERSON University of Rhode Island Kingston, Rhode Island CIVIL LAW differs from empirical law in that the former prescribes regularities in human action while the latter describes and predicts regularities in the world apart from human action. By an empirical or descriptive law scientists mean a law that is knowable on the basis of observed regularities. An example is Boyle's law. That at a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Argument from Reason.Stewart Goetz - 2013 - Philosophia Christi 15 (1):47-62.
    This article attempts to clarify an “argument from reason” set forth by C. S. Lewis in his Miracles. While there are various contemporary interpretations of the argument, Lewis intended to expose the “cardinal difficulty of naturalism.” First, this article seeks to clarify both Lewis’s argument and the understanding of naturalism that it presupposes. Second, philosophers of religion—especially, William Hasker and Alvin Plantinga—have significantly contributed to the argument’s contemporary discussion, and so their views are addressed with the intent to show how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Argument from Desire.Robert Holyer - 1988 - Faith and Philosophy 5 (1):61-71.
    In this essay I offer a reformulation and defense of the argument from desire as it is presented in the works of C. S. Lewis. Specifically, I try to answer the criticisms of the argument made by John Beversluis in his recent book C. S. Lewis and the Search for Rational Religion. However, my concern is not so much Lewis as it is the argument itself, which I argue is worthy of serious and more extended philosophical treatment.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations