Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Galilean Idealization.Ernan McMullin - 1985 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 16 (3):247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   316 citations  
  • (1 other version)Ernst Mach and the Fortunes of Positivism in America.Gerald Holton - 1992 - Isis 83 (1):27-60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Postpositivism and Educational Research.D. C. Phillips & Nicholas C. Burbules - 2001 - British Journal of Educational Studies 49 (1):109-111.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • On the Constitution of Atoms and Molecules, Part I.Niels Bohr - 1913 - Philosophical Magazine 26:1--25.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Galileo, Viviani and the tower of Pisa.Michael Segre - 1989 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 20 (4):435-451.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • An appraisal of Mendeleev’s contribution to the development of the periodic table.Mansoor Niaz, María A. Rodríguez & Angmary Brito - 2004 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 35 (2):271-282.
    Historians and philosophers of science generally conceptualize scientific progress to be dichotomous, viz., experimental observations lead to scientific laws, which later facilitate the elaboration of explanatory theories. There is considerable controversy in the literature with respect to Mendeleev’s contribution to the origin, nature, and development of the periodic table. The objectives of this study are to explore and reconstruct: a) periodicity in the periodic table as a function of atomic theory; b) role of predictions in scientific theories and its implications (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • An appraisal of the controversial nature of the oil drop experiment: Is closure possible?Mansoor Niaz - 2005 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56 (4):681-702.
    Acceptance of the quantization of the elementary electrical charge was preceded by a bitter dispute between Robert Millikan and Felix Ehrenhaft, which lasted for many years. Both Millikan and Ehrenhaft obtained very similar experimental results and yet Millikan was led to formulate the elementary electrical charge and Ehrenhaft to fractional charges. There have been four major attempts to reconstruct the historical events that led to the controversy: Holton ; Franklin ; Barnes et al. ; Goodstein. So we have the controversy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)A view from somewhere: Explaining the paradigms of educational research.Hanan A. Alexander - 2006 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 40 (2):205–221.
    In this paper I ask how educational researchers can believe the subjective perceptions of qualitative participant-observers given the concern for objectivity and generalisability of experimental research in the behavioural and social sciences. I critique the most common answer to this question within the educational research community, which posits the existence of two (or more) equally legitimate epistemological paradigms—positivism and constructivism—and offer an alternative that places a priority in educational research on understanding the purposes and meanings humans attribute to educational practices. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science.Nancy Cartwright - 1999 - Philosophy 75 (294):613-616.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   582 citations  
  • Kuhn reconstructed: Incommensurability without relativism.Michael E. Malone - 1991 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 24 (1):69-93.
    The standard reading of Kuhn's philosophy attributes to him the view that the incommensurability of rival theories and theory-ladenness of observation make rational debate about competing paradigms nearly impossible. If this reflects his real view, then he has claimed something prima facie absurd, and easily refuted with historical counter-examples. It is not the incommensurability thesis per se that is easily refutable, but Kuhn's gestelt interpretation of it. The gestalt interpretation, moreover misrepresents his more fundamental ideas on paradigms, and is in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Corpuscles, Electrons and Cathode Rays: J.J. Thomson and the ‘Discovery of the Electron’.Isobel Falconer - 1987 - British Journal for the History of Science 20 (3):241-276.
    On 30 April, 1897, J. J. Thomson announced the results of his previous four months' experiments on cathode rays. The rays, he suggested, were negatively charged subatomic particles. He called the particles ‘corpuscles’. They have since been re-named ‘electrons’ and Thomson has been hailed as their ‘discoverer’. Contrary to the accounts of most later writers, I show that this discovery was not the outcome of a concern with the nature of cathode rays which had occupied Thomson since 1881 and had (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes.Imre Lakatos - 1970 - In Imre Lakatos & Alan Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge [Eng.]: Cambridge University Press. pp. 91-196.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   687 citations  
  • Nature's Capacities and Their Measurement.Tim Maudlin & Nancy Cartwright - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy 90 (11):599.
    This book on the philosophy of science argues for an empiricism, opposed to the tradition of David Hume, in which singular rather than general causal claims are primary; causal laws express facts about singular causes whereas the general causal claims of science are ascriptions of capacities or causal powers, capacities to make things happen. Taking science as measurement, Cartwright argues that capacities are necessary for science and that these can be measured, provided suitable conditions are met. There are case studies (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   147 citations  
  • Précis of Unified theories of cognition.Allen Newell - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):425-437.
    The book presents the case that cognitive science should turn its attention to developing theories of human cognition that cover the full range of human perceptual, cognitive, and action phenomena. Cognitive science has now produced a massive number of high-quality regularities with many microtheories that reveal important mechanisms. The need for integration is pressing and will continue to increase. Equally important, cognitive science now has the theoretical concepts and tools to support serious attempts at unified theories. The argument is made (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • (1 other version)The contested nature of empirical educational research (and why philosophy of education offers little help).D. C. Phillips - 2005 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 39 (4):577–597.
    This paper suggests that empirical educational research has not, on the whole, been treated well by philosophers of education. A variety of criticisms have been offered, ranging from triviality, conceptual confusion and the impossibility of empirically studying normative processes. Furthermore, many of those who criticise, or dismiss, empirical research do so without subjecting any specific examples to careful scholarly scrutiny. It is suggested that both philosophy of education, and the empirical research enterprise, stand to profit if philosophers pay more attention (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Genetic epistemology, equilibration and the rationality of scientific change.Richard F. Kitchener - 1987 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 18 (3):339-366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Psychology Down the Ages.C. Spearman - 1938 - Mind 47 (187):377-384.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Piaget's Theory of Knowledge: Genetic Epistemology and Scientific Reason.R. F. KITCHENER - 1985
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The stage question in cognitive-developmental theory.Charles J. Brainerd - 1978 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1 (2):173-182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   182 citations  
  • (1 other version)The quantitative-qualitative distinction and the Null hypothesis significance testing procedure.Nimal Ratnesar & Jim Mackenzie - 2006 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 40 (4):501–509.
    Conventional discussion of research methodology contrast two approaches, the quantitative and the qualitative, presented as collectively exhaustive. But if qualitative is taken as the understanding of lifeworlds, the two approaches between them cover only a tiny fraction of research methodologies; and the quantitative, taken as the routine application to controlled experiments of frequentist statistics by way of the Null Hypothesis Significance Testing Procedure, is seriously flawed. It is contrary to the advice both of Fisher and of Neyman and Pearson, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Can we integrate qualitative and quantitative research in science education?Mansoor Niaz - 1997 - Science & Education 6 (3):291-300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • From cathode rays to alpha particles to quantum of action: A rational reconstruction of structure of the atom and its implications for chemistry textbooks.Mansoor Niaz - 1998 - Science Education 82 (5):527-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • (1 other version)'What it makes sense to say': Education, philosophy and Peter Winch on social science.Paul Smeyers - 2006 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 40 (4):463–485.
    This paper sets out Peter Winch's central ideas about the nature of the social sciences, and reappraises their potential for educational research. It is argued that the dichotomy between ‘reasons’ and ‘causes’ has done much harm, and that the important matter of understanding ‘what is real for us’ has recently been neglected. Winch's philosophy suggests a more adequate framework for educational research: one that embraces a pluralistic interpretive position, accommodating various methods and various kinds of understanding of the social, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (1 other version)‘What it Makes Sense to Say’: Education, Philosophy and Peter Winch on Social Science.Paul Smeyers - 2006 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 40 (4):463-485.
    This paper sets out Peter Winch’s central ideas about the nature of the social sciences, and reappraises their potential for educational research. It is argued that the dichotomy between ‘reasons’ and ‘causes’ has done much harm, and that the important matter of understanding ‘what is real for us’ has recently been neglected. Winch’s philosophy suggests a more adequate framework for educational research: one that embraces a pluralistic interpretive position, accommodating various methods and various kinds of understanding of the social, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Quantitative-Qualitative Distinction and the Null Hypothesis Significance Testing Procedure.Nimal Ratnesar & Jim Mackenzie - 2006 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 40 (4):501-509.
    Conventional discussion of research methodology contrast two approaches, the quantitative and the qualitative, presented as collectively exhaustive. But if qualitative is taken as the understanding of lifeworlds, the two approaches between them cover only a tiny fraction of research methodologies; and the quantitative, taken as the routine application to controlled experiments of frequentist statistics by way of the Null Hypothesis Significance Testing Procedure, is seriously flawed. It is contrary to the advice both of Fisher and of Neyman and Pearson, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Contested Nature of Empirical Educational Research (and Why Philosophy of Education Offers Little Help).D. C. Phillips - 2005 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 39 (4):577-597.
    This paper suggests that empirical educational research has not, on the whole, been treated well by philosophers of education. A variety of criticisms have been offered, ranging from triviality, conceptual confusion and the impossibility of empirically studying normative processes. Furthermore, many of those who criticise, or dismiss, empirical research do so without subjecting any specific examples to careful scholarly scrutiny. It is suggested that both philosophy of education, and the empirical research enterprise, stand to profit if philosophers pay more attention (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • (1 other version)A View from Somewhere: Explaining the Paradigms of Educational Research.Hanan A. Alexander - 2006 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 40 (2):205-221.
    In this paper I ask how educational researchers can believe the subjective perceptions of qualitative participant-observers given the concern for objectivity and generalisability of experimental research in the behavioural and social sciences. I critique the most common answer to this question within the educational research community, which posits the existence of two (or more) equally legitimate epistemological paradigms—positivism and constructivism—and offer an alternative that places a priority in educational research on understanding the purposes and meanings humans attribute to educational practices. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Mathematical Epistemology and Psychology.E. V. BETH - 1966
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations