Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. (2 other versions)Moral Explanations.Nicholas Sturgeon - 1997 - In Thomas L. Carson & Paul K. Moser (eds.), Morality and the good life. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  • Qui peut sauver la morale? Essai de métaéthique.François Jaquet & Hichem Naar - 2019 - Paris: Ithaque. Edited by Hichem Naar.
    Vous pensez peut-être que la peine de mort est injuste ? Ou que l’avortement est moralement acceptable ? Se pourrait-il alors que vous vous trompiez ? C’est en tout cas l’avis des théoriciens de l’erreur. D’après ces philosophes, tous les jugements moraux sont faux parce qu’ils présupposent à tort l’existence de faits moraux à la fois objectifs et non naturels. Organisé autour de ce défi nihiliste, le présent ouvrage aborde les principales théories métaéthiques comme autant de tentatives, plus ou moins (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Norm and Action. A Logical Enquiry.Georg Henrik von Wright - 1965 - Philosophy 40 (151):77-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Moral Realism: Facts and Norms. [REVIEW]David O. BRINK - 1991 - Ethics 101 (3):610-624.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   479 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Language of Morals.Richard Mervyn Hare - 1952 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    Hare has written a clear, brief, and readable introduction to ethics which looks at all the fundamental problems of the subject.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   493 citations  
  • The representation of life.Michael Thompson - 1995 - In Rosalind Hursthouse, Gavin Lawrence & Warren Quinn (eds.), Virtues and Reasons: Philippa Foot and Moral Theory: Essays in Honour of Philippa Foot. Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 247--296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • (1 other version)Norm and Action: A Logical Enquiry.Georg Henrik von Wright - 1963 - New York, NY, USA: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
    This work has been selected by scholars as being culturally important and is part of the knowledge base of civilization as we know it. This work is in the public domain in the United States of America, and possibly other nations. Within the United States, you may freely copy and distribute this work, as no entity has a copyright on the body of the work. Scholars believe, and we concur, that this work is important enough to be preserved, reproduced, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   114 citations  
  • (1 other version)“How to Be a Moral Realist.Richard Boyd - 1988 - In Geoffrey Sayre-McCord (ed.), Essays on moral realism. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. pp. 181-228.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   513 citations  
  • An important aspect of humanism.Knut Erik Tranöy - 1957 - Theoria 23 (1):37-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (2 other versions)Modern Moral Philosophy.G. E. M. Anscombe - 1958 - Philosophy 33 (124):1 - 19.
    The author presents and defends three theses: (1) "the first is that it is not profitable for us at present to do moral philosophy; that should be laid aside at any rate until we have an adequate philosophy of psychology." (2) "the second is that the concepts of obligation, And duty... And of what is morally right and wrong, And of the moral sense of 'ought', Ought to be jettisoned if this is psychologically possible...." (3) "the third thesis is that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   764 citations  
  • Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong.John Leslie Mackie - 1977 - New York: Penguin Books.
    John Mackie's stimulating book is a complete and clear treatise on moral theory. His writings on normative ethics-the moral principles he recommends-offer a fresh approach on a much neglected subject, and the work as a whole is undoubtedly a major contribution to modern philosophy.The author deals first with the status of ethics, arguing that there are not objective values, that morality cannot be discovered but must be made. He examines next the content of ethics, seeing morality as a functional device, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1170 citations  
  • Natural goodness.Philippa Foot - 2001 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Philippa Foot has for many years been one of the most distinctive and influential thinkers in moral philosophy. Long dissatisfied with the moral theories of her contemporaries, she has gradually evolved a theory of her own that is radically opposed not only to emotivism and prescriptivism but also to the whole subjectivist, anti-naturalist movement deriving from David Hume. Dissatisfied with both Kantian and utilitarian ethics, she claims to have isolated a special form of evaluation that predicates goodness and defect only (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   349 citations  
  • On Virtue Ethics.Rosalind Hursthouse - 1999 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Virtue ethics is perhaps the most important development within late twentieth-century moral philosophy. Rosalind Hursthouse, who has made notable contributions to this development, here presents a full exposition and defense of her neo-Aristotelian version of virtue ethics. She shows how virtue ethics can provide guidance for action, illuminate moral dilemmas, and bring out the moral significance of the emotions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   640 citations  
  • Human morality.Samuel Scheffler - 1992 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Some people believe that the demands of morality coincide with the requirements of an enlightened self-interest. Others believe that morality is diametrically opposed to considerations of self-interest. This book argues that there is another position, intermediate between these extremes, which makes better sense of the totality of our moral thought and practice. Scheffler elaborates this position via an examination of morality's content, scope, authority, and deliberative role. Although conflicts between morality and self-interest do arise, according to this position, nevertheless morality (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • `Ought' conversationally implies `can'.Walter Sinnott-Armstrong - 1984 - Philosophical Review 93 (2):249-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • (1 other version)How to derive "ought" from "is".John R. Searle - 1964 - Philosophical Review 73 (1):43-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   184 citations  
  • Realism and reduction: The Quest for robustness.Mark Schroeder - 2005 - Philosophers' Imprint 5:1-18.
    It doesn’t seem possible to be a realist about the traditional Christian God while claiming to be able to reduce God talk in naturalistically acceptable terms. Reduction, in this case, seems obviously eliminativist. Many philosophers seem to think that the same is true of the normative—that reductive “realists” about the normative are not really realists about the normative at all, or at least, only in some attenuated sense. This paper takes on the challenge of articulating what it is that makes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Moral realism.Peter Railton - 1986 - Philosophical Review 95 (2):163-207.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   552 citations  
  • Ought-implies-can: Erasmus Luther and R.m. Hare.Charles R. Pigden - 1990 - Sophia 29 (1):2-30.
    l. There is an antinomy in Hare's thought between Ought-Implies-Can and No-Indicatives-from-Imperatives. It cannot be resolved by drawing a distinction between implication and entailment. 2. Luther resolved this antinomy in the l6th century, but to understand his solution, we need to understand his problem. He thought the necessity of Divine foreknowledge removed contingency from human acts, thus making it impossible for sinners to do otherwise than sin. 3. Erasmus objected (on behalf of Free Will) that this violates Ought-Implies-Can which he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The naturalistic fallacy.W. K. Frankena - 1939 - Mind 48 (192):464-477.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  • (1 other version)More bad news for the logical autonomy of ethics.Mark T. Nelson - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (2):203-216.
    Are there good arguments from Is to Ought? Toomas Karmo has claimed that there are trivially valid arguments from Is to Ought, but no sound ones. I call into question some key elements of Karmo’s argument for the “logical autonomy of ethics”, and show that attempts to use it as part of an overall case for moral skepticism would be self-defeating.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • (1 other version)Identity and necessity.Saul A. Kripke - 1971 - In Milton Karl Munitz (ed.), Identity and individuation. New York,: New York University Press. pp. 135-164.
    are synthetic a priori judgements possible?" In both cases, i~thas usually been t'aken for granted in fife one case by Kant that synthetic a priori judgements were possible, and in the other case in contemporary,'d-". philosophical literature that contingent statements of identity are ppss. ible. I do not intend to deal with the Kantian question except to mention:ssj~".
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   435 citations  
  • From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis.Frank Jackson - 1998 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Frank Jackson champions the cause of conceptual analysis as central to philosophical inquiry. In recent years conceptual analysis has been undervalued and widely misunderstood, suggests Jackson. He argues that such analysis is mistakenly clouded in mystery, preventing a whole range of important questions from being productively addressed. He anchors his argument in discussions of specific philosophical issues, starting with the metaphysical doctrine of physicalism and moving on, via free will, meaning, personal identity, motion, and change, to ethics and the philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1051 citations  
  • (1 other version)From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis.Timothy Williamson & Frank Jackson - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (3):625.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   112 citations  
  • (1 other version)From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis.Frank Jackson - 1999 - Philosophical Quarterly 49 (197):539-542.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   812 citations  
  • The meaning of 'ought'.Ralph Wedgwood - 2006 - In Russ Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics: Volume 1. Oxford University Press. pp. 127-160.
    In this paper, I apply the "conceptual role semantics" approach that I have proposed elsewhere (according to which the meaning of normative terms is given by their role in practical reasoning or deliberation) to the meaning of the term 'ought'. I argue that this approach can do three things: It can give an adequate explanation of the special connection that normative judgments have to practical reasoning and motivation for action. It can give an adequate account of why the central principles (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Good and Evil.Peter Geach - 1956 - Analysis 17 (2):33 - 42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   312 citations  
  • (1 other version)Morality: an introduction to ethics.Bernard Arthur Owen Williams - 1972 - New York,: Harper & Row.
    In Morality Bernard Williams confronts the problems of writing moral philosophy, and offers a stimulating alternative to more systematic accounts which seem nevertheless to have left all the important issues somewhere off the page.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • L'erreur de Hume.Jean-Louis Gardies - 1990 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 44 (1):155-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The autonomy of ethics.A. N. Prior - 1960 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 38 (3):199 – 206.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong.Fred Feldman & J. L. Mackie - 1979 - Philosophical Review 88 (1):134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   675 citations  
  • Human Morality by Samuel Scheffler. [REVIEW]Jonathan Lear - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy 90 (4):205-211.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Le rasoire de Kant.Ruwen Ogien - 2001 - Philosophiques 28 (1):9-25.
    Dans cet article, je m'intéresse à quelques problèmes liés à la justification de méta-normes telles que « devoir » implique « pouvoir ». Je soutiens, d'abord, que des méta-normes différentes sont justifiées par des principes différents. La méta-norme « devoir » implique « pouvoir » est justifiée par un principe d'humanité qui nous demande d'exclure les normes trop exigeantes. La métanorme selon laquelle ce serait une sottise d'ordonner à quelqu'un ce qu'il veut inévitablement de lui-même est justifiée par un principe (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Who Needs Valid Moral Arguments?Mark T. Nelson - 2003 - Argumentation 17 (1):35-42.
    Why have so many philosophers agonised over the possibility of valid arguments from factual premises to moral conclusions? I suggest that they have done so, because of worries over a sceptical argument that has as one of its premises, `All moral knowledge must be non-inferential, or, if inferential, based on valid arguments or strong inductive arguments from factual premises'. I argue that this premise is false.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Norm and Action. A Logical Enquiry.Georg Henrik von Wright & A. J. Ayer - 1964 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 19 (3):492-492.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (1 other version)Natural Goodness.Philippa Foot - 2001 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 64 (3):604-606.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   373 citations  
  • (1 other version)More Bad News For The Logical Autonomy of Ethics.Mark T. Nelson - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (2):203-216.
    Since the time of Hume, many philosophers have thought it impossible to deduce an ‘Ought’ from an ‘Is,’ or in general to deduce ‘ethical sentences’ from purely ‘factual sentences.’ This is the thesis of the logical autonomy of ethics. I consider a more recent argument by Toomas Karmo in support of the autonomism, but show its limitations in the context of justification skepticism about ethics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • La normativité des concepts évaluatifs.Christine Tappolet - 2011 - Philosophiques 38 (1):157-176.
    On admet en général qu’il y a deux sortes de concepts normatifs : les concepts évaluatifs, comme bon, et les concepts déontiques, comme devoir. La question que soulève cette distinction est celle de savoir comment il est possible d’affirmer que les concepts évaluatifs sont normatifs. En effet, comme les concepts déontiques semblent constituer le coeur du domaine normatif, plus le fossé entre les deux sortes de concepts est grand, moins il paraîtra plausible d’affirmer que les concepts évaluatifs sont normatifs. Après (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Is it Always Fallacious to Derive Values From Facts?Mark T. Nelson - 1995 - Argumentation 9 (4):553-562.
    Charles Pigden has argued for a logical Is/Ought gap on the grounds of the conservativeness of logic. I offer a counter-example which shows that Pigden’s argument is unsound and that there need be no logical gap between Is-premises and an Ought-conclusion. My counter-example is an argument which is logically valid, has only Is-premises and an Ought-conclusion, does not purport to violate the conservativeness of logic, and does not rely on controversial assumptions about Aristotelian biology or 'institutional facts.'.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (2 other versions)A Theory of the Good and the Right.Richard B. Brandt - 1979 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 44 (1):181-182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   247 citations  
  • (1 other version)Précis of Human Morality.Samuel Scheffler - 1995 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (4):939-940.
    In Human Morality, I attempt to do two things. The first is to distinguish carefully among questions concerning morality’s scope, content, authority, and deliberative role, and to emphasize the importance of addressing all four of these topics if we are to understand the relation between morality and the point of view of the individual agent. The second is to explore each of these topics myself, and, in so doing, to sketch one interpretation of the place of moral concerns in human (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • (2 other versions)A Theory of the Good and the Right.Richard B. Brandt - 1979 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 35 (2):307-310.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   275 citations  
  • Deontic Logic and its Philosophical Morals.Jaakko Hintikka - 1969 - In Models for Modalities: Selected Essays. Dordrecht: Springer. pp. 184--214.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (2 other versions)A Theory of the Good and the Right.Richard B. Brandt - 1979 - Philosophy 55 (213):412-414.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   218 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The Autonomy of Ethics.A. Prior - 1960 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 38:197.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Une conception de l'objectivité du mal.Daniel Schulthess - 1986 - In J. Hainard & Rudolf Kaehr (eds.), Le mal et la douleur. Musée d'ethnographie. pp. p.171-180.
    The article sketches a possible argument for the objectivity of the evil. In a first stage the author deals with the emotivist thesis according to which evaluative judgments are nothing other than the expression of our positive or negative emotions toward an object. Although this thesis is rejected, the idea that emotions play a central role by the uttering of an evaluative judgement is retained. It is only by critically examining such judgments that one can eviscerate the objective core they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation