Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Peirce: a guide for the perplexed.Cornelis De Waal - 2013 - New York: Bloomsbury Academic.
    Charles Sanders Peirce, the founder of pragmatism, is a hugely important and influential thinker in the history of American philosophy. His philosophical interests were broad and he made significant contributions in several different areas of thought. Moreover, his contributions are intimately connected and his philosophy designed to form a coherent and systematic whole. Contents: 1: Life and Work; Chapter 2: Logic; Chapter 3: The Doctrine of the Categories; Chapter 4: Semiotics; Chapter 5: Philosophy of Science; Chapter 6: Pragmatism but Not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Realism, Common Sense, and Science.Mario De Caro - 2015 - The Monist 98 (2):197-214.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Fundamental Problems. The Method of Philosophy as a systematic arrangement of Knowledge.Paul Carus - 1889 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 28:551-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Peirce's evolutionary pragmatic idealism.Arthur W. Burks - 1996 - Synthese 106 (3):323-372.
    In this paper I synthesize a unified system out of Peirce's life work, and name it Peirce's Evolutionary Pragmatic Idealism. Peirce developed this philosophy in four stages: His 1868–69 theory that cognition is a continuous and infinite social semiotic process, in which Man is a sign. His Popular Science Monthly pragmatism and frequency theory of probabilistic induction. His 1891–93 cosmic evolutionism of Tychism, Synechism, and Agapism. Pragmaticism: The doctrine of real potentialities, and Peirce's pragmatic program for developing concrete reasonableness. Peirce's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Charles Sanders Peirce: A Life.Joseph Brent - 1994 - American Journal of Theology and Philosophy 15 (3):337-342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Edward Drinker Cope and the Changing Structure of Evolutionary Theory.Peter Bowler - 1977 - Isis 68:249-265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Edward Drinker Cope and the Changing Structure of Evolutionary Theory.Peter J. Bowler - 1977 - Isis 68 (2):249-265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The Immortality of Infusoria.Alfred Binet - 1890 - The Monist 1 (1):21-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Réponse à M. Ch. Richet.Alfred Binet - 1888 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 25:220 - 224.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Double Consciousness.A. Binet - 1894 - Philosophical Review 3:763.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • La vie psychique Des micro-organismes.Alfred Binet - 1887 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 24:449 - 489.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Immortality of Infusoria.Alfred Binet - 1890 - The Monist 1 (1):21-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Cell and Protoplasm as Container, Object, and Substance, 1835–1861.Daniel Liu - 2017 - Journal of the History of Biology 50 (4):889-925.
    (Recipient of the 2020 Everett Mendelsohn Prize.) This article revisits the development of the protoplasm concept as it originally arose from critiques of the cell theory, and examines how the term “protoplasm” transformed from a botanical term of art in the 1840s to the so-called “living substance” and “the physical basis of life” two decades later. I show that there were two major shifts in biological materialism that needed to occur before protoplasm theory could be elevated to have equal status (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Genesis of Neo-Kantianism, 1796-1880.Frederick C. Beiser - 2014 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    Neo-Kantianism was an important movement in German philosophy of the late 19th century: Frederick Beiser traces its development back to the late 18th century, and explains its rise as a response to three major developments in German culture: the collapse of speculative idealism; the materialism controversy; and the identity crisis of philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • After Hegel: German Philosophy, 1840-1900.Frederick C. Beiser - 2014 - Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    Histories of German philosophy in the nineteenth century typically focus on its first half--when Hegel, idealism, and Romanticism dominated. By contrast, the remainder of the century, after Hegel's death, has been relatively neglected because it has been seen as a period of stagnation and decline. But Frederick Beiser argues that the second half of the century was in fact one of the most revolutionary periods in modern philosophy because the nature of philosophy itself was up for grabs and the very (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Bacteria are small but not stupid: cognition, natural genetic engineering and socio-bacteriology.J. A. Shapiro - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 38 (4):807-819.
    Forty years’ experience as a bacterial geneticist has taught me that bacteria possess many cognitive, computational and evolutionary capabilities unimaginable in the first six decades of the twentieth century. Analysis of cellular processes such as metabolism, regulation of protein synthesis, and DNA repair established that bacteria continually monitor their external and internal environments and compute functional outputs based on information provided by their sensory apparatus. Studies of genetic recombination, lysogeny, antibiotic resistance and my own work on transposable elements revealed multiple (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • andbook of Psychology. [REVIEW]James Mark Baldwin - 1891 - Ancient Philosophy (Misc) 2:467.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Virtue, Happiness, and Wellbeing.Mauro Rossi & Christine Tappolet - 2016 - The Monist 99 (2):112-127.
    What is the relation between virtue and wellbeing? Our claim is that, under certain conditions, virtue necessarily tends to have a positive impact on an individual’s wellbeing. This is so because of the connection between virtue and psychological happiness, on the one hand, and between psychological happiness and wellbeing, on the other hand. In particular we defend three claims: that virtue is constituted by a disposition to experience fitting emotions, that fitting emotions are constituents of fitting happiness, and that fitting (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Physiology of the Sense Organs and Early Neo-Kantian Conceptions of Objectivity: Helmholtz, Lange, Liebmann.Scott Edgar - 2015 - In Flavia Padovani, Alan Richardson & Jonathan Y. Tsou (eds.), Objectivity in Science: New Perspectives From Science and Technology Studies. Cham: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol. 310. Springer.
    The physiologist Johannes Müller’s doctrine of specific nerve energies had a decisive influence on neo-Kantian conceptions of the objectivity of knowledge in the 1850s - 1870s. In the first half of the nineteenth century, Müller amassed a body of experimental evidence to support his doctrine, according to which the character of our sensations is determined by the structures of our own sensory nerves, and not by the external objects that cause the sensations. Neo-Kantians such as Hermann von Helmholtz, F.A. Lange, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Metaphysical Club: A Story of Ideas in America.Louis Menand - 2001 - Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
    If past is prologue, then The Metaphysical Club by Louis Menand may suggest an intellectual course for the United States in the 21st century. At least Menand, a frequent contributor to The New Yorker and The New York Review of Books, thinks so. This enthralling study of Oliver Wendell Holmes, William James, Charles Sanders Peirce, and John Dewey shows how these four men developed a philosophy of pragmatism following the Civil War, a period Menand likens to post-cold-war ..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Amoebae as Exemplary Cells: The Protean Nature of an Elementary Organism. [REVIEW]Andrew Reynolds - 2008 - Journal of the History of Biology 41 (2):307 - 337.
    In the nineteenth century protozoology and early cell biology intersected through the nexus of Darwin's theory of evolution. As single-celled organisms, amoebae offered an attractive focus of study for researchers seeking evolutionary relationships between the cells of humans and other animals, and their primitive appearance made them a favourite model for the ancient ancestor of all living things. Their resemblance to human and other metazoan cells made them popular objects of study among morphologists, physiologists, and even those investigating animal behaviour. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Divide et Impera! William James’s Pragmatist Tradition in the Philosophy of Science.Alexander Klein - 2008 - Philosophical Topics 36 (1):129-166.
    ABSTRACT. May scientists rely on substantive, a priori presuppositions? Quinean naturalists say "no," but Michael Friedman and others claim that such a view cannot be squared with the actual history of science. To make his case, Friedman offers Newton's universal law of gravitation and Einstein's theory of relativity as examples of admired theories that both employ presuppositions (usually of a mathematical nature), presuppositions that do not face empirical evidence directly. In fact, Friedman claims that the use of such presuppositions is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Metaphysics and Logic of Psychology: Peirce's Reading of James's Principles.Mathias Girel - 2003 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 39 (2):163-203.
    The present paper deals thus with some fundamental agreements and disagreements between Peirce and James, on crucial issues such as perception and consciousness. When Peirce first read the Principles, he was sketching his theory of the categories, testing its applications in many fields of knowledge, and many investigations were launched, concerning indexicals, diagrams, growth and development. James's utterances led Peirce to make his own views clearer on a wide range of topics that go to the heart of the foundations of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The philosophy of Edmund Montgomery.Morris T. Keeton - 1950 - Dallas,: University Press in Dallas.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Lives of the Cell.J. Andrew Mendelsohn - 2003 - Journal of the History of Biology 36 (1):1-37.
    What is the relation between things and theories, the material world and its scientific representations? This is a staple philosophical problem that rarely counts as historically legitimate or fruitful. In the following dialogue, the interlocutors do not argue for or against realism. Instead, they explore changing relations between theories and things, between contested objects of knowledge and less contested, more everyday things. Widely seen as the life sciences' first general theory, the cell theory underwent dramatic changes during the nineteenth century. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)Peirce’s Progress From Nominalism Toward Realism.Max Fisch - 1967 - The Monist 51 (2):159-178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On small differences in sensation.C. S. Peirce & Joseph Jastrow - 1884 - Memoirs of the National Academy of Sciences 3:75-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Did Peirce Have a Cosmology?T. L. Short - 2010 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 46 (4):521-543.
    W. B. Gallie's words about Peirce's cosmology—"the black sheep or white elephant of his philosophical progeny" (1952, p. 216)—have often been quoted, usually as a preface to giving a better account of the animal. That he attributed the view to 'contemporary philosophers' and did not assert it himself has usually been ignored. True, Gallie did argue that the "cosmology is a failure, and an inevitable failure" (p. 236), but he also said that Peirce himself "recognized … that his work in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Protoplasmic Theory of Life and the Vitalist-Mechanist Debate.Gerald L. Geison - 1969 - Isis 60 (3):273-292.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (1 other version)Our Monism.Ernst Haeckel - 1892 - The Monist 2 (4):481-486.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Doctrine of Necessity Examined.Charles S. Peirce - 1892 - The Monist 2 (3):321-337.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • (1 other version)Charles S. Peirce's evolutionary philosophy.Carl R. Hausman - 1993 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    In this systematic introduction to the philosophy of Charles S. Peirce, the author focuses on four of Peirce's fundamental conceptions: pragmatism and Peirce's development of it into what he called 'pragmaticism'; his theory of signs; his phenomenology; and his theory that continuity is of prime importance for philosophy. He argues that at the centre of Peirce's philosophical project is a unique form of metaphysical realism, whereby continuity and evolutionary change are both necessary for our understanding of experience. In his final (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Reasoning and the logic of things: the Cambridge conferences lectures of 1898.Charles Sanders Peirce - 1992 - Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Edited by Kenneth Laine Ketner.
    This volume also contains a long introductory essay by Hilary Putnam on the mathematics of continuity.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Principles of Psychology.William James - 1890 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 11 (3):506-507.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1417 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Architecture of Theories.Charles S. Peirce - 1891 - The Monist 1 (2):161-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce.Charles Sanders Peirce, Charles Hartshorne & Paul Weiss - 1933 - International Journal of Ethics 43 (2):220-226.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   342 citations  
  • Catalayst for Controversy: Paul Carus of Open Court.Harold Henderson - 1994 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 30 (2):451-456.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Zend-Avesta oder über die Dinge des Himmels und des Jenseits.Gustav Theodor Fechner - 1925 - Annalen der Philosophie Und Philosophischen Kritik 5 (1):10-10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Some Questions of Psycho-Physics. A Discussion.Ernst Mach - 1891 - The Monist 1 (3):393-400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Some questions of psycho-physics. Sensations and the elements of reality.Ernst Mach - 1891 - The Monist 1 (3):393 - 400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • (1 other version)Modern Physiology.Max Verworn - 1894 - The Monist 4 (3):355-374.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The unity of the organic individual.Edmund Montgomery - 1880 - Mind 5 (19):318-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Un néo-lamarckien américain : Edward Drinker Cope (1840-1896).Goulven Laurent - 1979 - Revue de Synthèse 100 (95-96):297-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Metaphysical Club: a Story of Ideas in America.Louis Menand - 2003 - American Journal of Theology and Philosophy 24 (1):101-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • (1 other version)Self-Consciousness, Social Consciousness and Nature.Josiah Royce - 1895 - Philosophical Review 4 (5):465-485.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Making the case for orthogenesis: The popularization of definitely directed evolution.Mark A. Ulett - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 45 (1):124-132.
    Throughout the history of evolutionary theory a number of scientists have argued that evolution proceeds along a limited number of definite trajectories, a concept and group of theories known as “orthogenesis”. Beginning in the 1880s, influential evolutionists including Theodor Eimer, Edward Drinker Cope, and Leo Berg argued that a fully causal explanation of evolution must take into account the origin and nature of variation, an idea that implied orthogenesis in their views. This paper argues that these orthogenesis developed theories that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Bacteria are small but not stupid: Cognition, natural genetic engineering and socio-bacteriology.J. A. Shapiro - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 38 (4):807-819.
    Forty years’ experience as a bacterial geneticist has taught me that bacteria possess many cognitive, computational and evolutionary capabilities unimaginable in the first six decades of the twentieth century. Analysis of cellular processes such as metabolism, regulation of protein synthesis, and DNA repair established that bacteria continually monitor their external and internal environments and compute functional outputs based on information provided by their sensory apparatus. Studies of genetic recombination, lysogeny, antibiotic resistance and my own work on transposable elements revealed multiple (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Peirce.Christopher Hookway - 1987 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (1):117-119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Intellectual History and the History of Philosophy.Sarah Hutton - 2014 - History of European Ideas 40 (7):925-937.
    The issue which I wish to address in this paper is the widespread tendency in Anglophone philosophy to insist on a separation between the history of philosophy and the history of ideas or intellectual history. This separation reflects an anxiety on the part of philosophers lest the special character of philosophy will be dissolved into something else in the hands of historians. And it is borne of a fundamental tension between those who think of philosophy's past as a source of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Law of Mind.Charles S. Peirce - 1892 - The Monist 2 (4):533-559.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations