Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The generalizability crisis.Tal Yarkoni - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45:e1.
    Most theories and hypotheses in psychology are verbal in nature, yet their evaluation overwhelmingly relies on inferential statistical procedures. The validity of the move from qualitative to quantitative analysis depends on the verbal and statistical expressions of a hypothesis being closely aligned – that is, that the two must refer to roughly the same set of hypothetical observations. Here, I argue that many applications of statistical inference in psychology fail to meet this basic condition. Focusing on the most widely used (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Ontological Relativity and Other Essays.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1969 - New York: Columbia University Press.
    This volume consists of the first of the John Dewey Lectures delivered under the auspices of Columbia University's Philosophy Department as well as other essays by the author. Intended to clarify the meaning of the philosophical doctrines propounded by Professor Quine in 'Word and Objects', the essays included herein both support and expand those doctrines.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   786 citations  
  • From Bacteria to Bach and Back: The Evolution of Minds.Daniel Dennett - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   191 citations  
  • Nature's Capacities and Their Measurement.Tim Maudlin & Nancy Cartwright - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy 90 (11):599.
    This book on the philosophy of science argues for an empiricism, opposed to the tradition of David Hume, in which singular rather than general causal claims are primary; causal laws express facts about singular causes whereas the general causal claims of science are ascriptions of capacities or causal powers, capacities to make things happen. Taking science as measurement, Cartwright argues that capacities are necessary for science and that these can be measured, provided suitable conditions are met. There are case studies (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   150 citations  
  • Theory of Games and Economic Behavior.John von Neumann & Oskar Morgenstern - 1944 - Science and Society 9 (4):366-369.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   568 citations  
  • Brainstorms.Daniel Dennett - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 47 (2):326-327.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1044 citations  
  • (1 other version)Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes.Paul M. Churchland - 1981 - Journal of Philosophy 78 (2):67-90.
    Eliminative materialism is the thesis that our common-sense conception of psychological phenomena constitutes a radically false theory, a theory so fundamentally defective that both the principles and the ontology of that theory will eventually be displaced, rather than smoothly reduced, by completed neuroscience. Our mutual understanding and even our introspection may then be reconstituted within the conceptual framework of completed neuroscience, a theory we may expect to be more powerful by far than the common-sense psychology it displaces, and more substantially (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   902 citations  
  • Descartes’ error: Emotion, rationality and the human brain.Antonio Damasio - 1994 - New York: Putnam 352.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   789 citations  
  • Systematicity: The Nature of Science.Paul Hoyningen-Huene - 2013 - New York, US: Oxford University Press USA.
    In Systematicity, Paul Hoyningen-Huene answers the question "What is science?" by proposing that scientific knowledge is primarily distinguished from other forms of knowledge, especially everyday knowledge, by being more systematic. "Science" is here understood in the broadest possible sense, encompassing not only the natural sciences but also mathematics, the social sciences, and the humanities. The author develops his thesis in nine dimensions in which it is claimed that science is more systematic than other forms of knowledge: regarding descriptions, explanations, predictions, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Fact and Method.Richard W. Miller - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (3):159-162.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Introduction: Interdisciplinary model exchanges.Till Grüne-Yanoff & Uskali Mäki - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 48:52-59.
    The five studies of this special section investigate the role of models and similar representational tools in interdisciplinarity. These studies were all written by philosophers of science, who focused on interdisciplinary episodes between disciplines and sub-disciplines ranging from physics, chemistry and biology to the computational sciences, sociology and economics. The reasons we present these divergent studies in a collective form are three. First, we want to establish model-exchange as a kind of interdisciplinary event. The five case studies, which are summarized (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Skill of Perceiving Persons.Victoria McGeer - 2009 - Modern Schoolman 86 (3-4):289-318.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Psycho-practice, psycho-theory and the contrastive case of autism: How practices of mind become second-nature.Victoria McGeer - 2001 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 8 (5-7):109-132.
    In philosophy, the last thirty years or so has seen a split between 'simulation theorists' and 'theory-theorists', with a number of variations on each side. In general, simulation theorists favour the idea that our knowledge of others is based on using ourselves as a working model of what complex psychological creatures are like. Theory-theorists claim that our knowledge of complex psychological creatures, including ourselves, is theoretical in character and so more like our knowledge of the world in general. The body (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis.Jerry A. Fodor & Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1988 - Cognition 28 (1-2):3-71.
    This paper explores the difference between Connectionist proposals for cognitive a r c h i t e c t u r e a n d t h e s o r t s o f m o d e l s t hat have traditionally been assum e d i n c o g n i t i v e s c i e n c e . W e c l a i m t h a t t h (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1139 citations  
  • Real patterns.Daniel C. Dennett - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (1):27-51.
    Are there really beliefs? Or are we learning (from neuroscience and psychology, presumably) that, strictly speaking, beliefs are figments of our imagination, items in a superceded ontology? Philosophers generally regard such ontological questions as admitting just two possible answers: either beliefs exist or they don't. There is no such state as quasi-existence; there are no stable doctrines of semi-realism. Beliefs must either be vindicated along with the viruses or banished along with the banshees. A bracing conviction prevails, then, to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   638 citations  
  • Verbal behavior.Noam Chomsky & B. F. Skinner - 1959 - Language 35 (1):26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   637 citations  
  • The role of psychology in behavioral economics: The case of social preferences.Chiara Lisciandra - 2018 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 72:11-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Behavioral game theory: Plausible formal models that predict accurately.Colin F. Camerer - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (2):157-158.
    Many weaknesses of game theory are cured by new models that embody simple cognitive principles, while maintaining the formalism and generality that makes game theory useful. Social preference models can generate team reasoning by combining reciprocation and correlated equilibrium. Models of limited iterated thinking explain data better than equilibrium models do; and they self-repair problems of implausibility and multiplicity of equilibria.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • Enculturating folk psychologists.Victoria McGeer - 2020 - Synthese 199 (1-2):1039-1063.
    This paper argues that our folk-psychological expertise is a special case of extended and enculturated cognition where we learn to regulate both our own and others’ thought and action in accord with a wide array of culturally shaped folk-psychological norms. The view has three noteworthy features: it challenges a common assumption that the foundational capacity at work in folk-psychological expertise is one of interpreting behaviour in mentalistic terms, arguing instead that successful mindreading is largely a consequence of successful mindshaping; it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Foundations of Statistics.Leonard J. Savage - 1954 - Synthese 11 (1):86-89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   871 citations  
  • On Social Facts.Margaret Gilbert - 1989 - Ethics 102 (4):853-856.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   552 citations  
  • Kinds of Mind.Daniel C. Dennett - 2000 - Mind 109 (436):883-890.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • The evolution of individualistic norms.Don Ross - 2013 - In Kim Sterelny, Richard Joyce, Brett Calcott & Ben Fraser (eds.), Cooperation and its Evolution. MIT Press. pp. 17.
    It is generally recognized that descriptive and normative individualism are logically independent theses. This paper defends the stronger view that recognition of the falsehood of descriptive individualism is crucial to understanding the evolutionary and developmental basis of normative individualism. The argument given for this is not analytic; rather, it is based on empirical generalizations about the evolution of markets with specialized labor, about the nature of information processing in large markets, and about the socialization of human children.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The functions of consciousness.Bernard J. Baars - 1988 - In A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   561 citations  
  • Categories We Live By: Reply to Alcoff, Butler, and Roth. Ásta - 2021 - European Journal of Philosophy 31 (1):310-318.
    The author of Categories We Live By replies to critics Linda Martín Alcoff, Judith Butler, and Abraham Sesshu Roth.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Science and human behavior.B. F. Skinner - 1954 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 144:268-269.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   571 citations  
  • Picoeconomics.George Ainslie - 1992 - Behavior and Philosophy 20:89-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   196 citations  
  • Psychoneural Reduction (B. Hannan).J. Bickle - 2000 - Philosophical Books 41 (1):53-54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Explaining growth.Harold Kincaid - 2009 - In Don Ross & Harold Kincaid (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Economics. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 455--475.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Minding minds: evolving a reflexive mind by interpreting others.Radu J. Bogdan - 2000 - Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
    The theme of this essay is rather simple, though its demonstration is not. It is that humans think reflexively or metamentally because -- and often in the forms in which -- they interpret each other. In this essay ‘metamental’ means ‘about mental’ and ‘reflexive mind’ means ‘a mind thinking about its own thoughts.’ To think reflexively or metamentally is to think about thoughts deliberately and explicitly, as in thinking that my current thoughts about metamentation are right. Thinking about thoughts requires (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Models of Temporal Discounting 1937–2000: An Interdisciplinary Exchange between Economics and Psychology.Till Grüne-Yanoff - 2015 - Science in Context 28 (4):675-713.
    ArgumentToday's models of temporal discounting are the result of multiple interdisciplinary exchanges between psychology and economics. Although these exchanges did not result in an integrated discipline, they had important effects on all disciplines involved. The paper describes these exchanges from the 1930s onwards, focusing on two episodes in particular: an attempted synthesis by psychiatrist George Ainslie and others in the 1970s; and the attempted application of this new discounting model by a generation of economists and psychologists in the 1980s, which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Microcognition.Dan Lloyd & Andy Clark - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (3):706.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Social norms or social preferences?Ken Binmore - 2010 - Mind and Society 9 (2):139-157.
    Some behavioral economists argue that the honoring of social norms can be adequately modeled as the optimization of social utility functions in which the welfare of others appears as an explicit argument. This paper suggests that the large experimental claims made for social utility functions are premature at best, and that social norms are better studied as equilibrium selection devices that evolved for use in games that are seldom studied in economics laboratories.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • (1 other version)Behaviorism.John B. Watson - 1927 - Mind 36 (141):77-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   167 citations  
  • Phenomenal experience and functionalism.Anthony J. Marcel - 1988 - In Anthony J. Marcel & Edoardo Bisiach (eds.), Consciousness in Contemporary Science. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Psychologists should learn structural specification and experimental econometrics.Don Ross - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45.
    The most plausible of Yarkoni's paths to recovery for psychology is the least radical one: psychologists need truly quantitative methods that exploit the informational power of variance and heterogeneity in multiple variables. If they drop ambitions to explain entire behaviors, they could find a box full of design and econometric tools in the parts of experimental economics that don't ape psychology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Null. Null - 2016 - Philosophy Study 6 (9).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   388 citations  
  • Being There (Derek Browne).A. Clark - 1999 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 77 (4):524-525.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • (1 other version)Consciousness.Owen J. Flanagan - 1984 - In The Science of the Mind. MIT Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   199 citations