Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Laws of Scientific Change.Hakob Barseghyan - 2015 - Cham: Imprint: Springer.
    This book systematically creates a general descriptive theory of scientific change that explains the mechanics of changes in both scientific theories and the methods of their assessment. It was once believed that, while scientific theories change through time, their change itself is governed by a fixed method of science. Nowadays we know that there is no such thing as an unchangeable method of science; the criteria employed by scientists in theory evaluation also change through time. But if that is so, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Unconceived alternatives and conservatism in science: the impact of professionalization, peer-review, and Big Science.P. Kyle Stanford - 2015 - Synthese 196 (10):3915-3932.
    Scientific realists have suggested that changes in our scientific communities over the course of their history have rendered those communities progressively less vulnerable to the problem of unconcieved alternatives over time. I argue in response not only that the most fundamental historical transformations of the scientific enterprise have generated steadily mounting obstacles to revolutionary, transformative, or unorthodox scientific theorizing, but also that we have substantial independent evidence that the institutional apparatus of contemporary scientific inquiry fosters an exceedingly and increasingly theoretically (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Why the Realism Debate Matters for Science Policy: The Case of the Human Brain Project.Jamie Craig Owen Shaw - 2018 - Spontaneous Generations 9 (1):82-98.
    There has been a great deal of skepticism towards the value of the realism/anti-realism debate. More specifically, many have argued that plausible formulations of realism and anti-realism do not differ substantially in any way. In this paper, I argue against this trend by demonstrating how a hypothetical resolution of the debate, through deeper engagement with the historical record, has important implications for our criterion of theory pursuit and science policy. I do this by revisiting Arthur Fine’s ‘small handful’ argument for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Was Feyerabend an anarchist? The structure(s) of ‘anything goes’.Jamie Shaw - 2017 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 64:11-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (4 other versions)The Logic of Scientific Discovery.Karl Popper - 1959 - Studia Logica 9:262-265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1545 citations  
  • CCR: A Refutation: PHILOSOPHY.J. W. N. Watkins - 1971 - Philosophy 46 (175):56-61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Against Method.P. Feyerabend - 1975 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26 (4):331-342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   608 citations  
  • The Retreat to Commitment.William W. Bartley - 1966 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 17 (2):153-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The Logic of Liberty.Michael Polanyi - 1953 - Philosophy of Science 20 (1):81-81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • (1 other version)Explanation, Reduction and Empiricism.P. K. Feyerabend - 1967 - Critica 1 (2):103-106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   233 citations  
  • Two letters of Paul Feyerabend to Thomas S. Kühn on a draft of the structure of scientific revolutions.Paul Hoyningen-Huene - 1995 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 26 (3):353-387.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • The career of continental drift theory: An application of Imre Lakatos' analysis of scientific growth to the rise of drift theory.Henry Frankel - 1979 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 10 (1):21-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • On the Interpretation of Scientific Theories.Paul K. Feyerabend - 1960 - Atti Del XII Congresso Internazionale di Filosofia 5:151-159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • (1 other version)VIII. Classical Empiricism.Paul K. Feyerabend - 1971 - In John W. Davis & Robert E. Butts (eds.), The Methodological Heritage of Newton. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 150-170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • (1 other version)VIII.—An Attempt at a Realistic Interpretation of Experience.P. K. Feyerabend - 1958 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 58 (1):143-170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Was Feyerabend a Popperian? Methodological issues in the History of the Philosophy of Science.Matteo Collodel - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 57:27-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The Epistemic Benefit of Transient Diversity.Kevin J. S. Zollman - 2010 - Erkenntnis 72 (1):17-35.
    There is growing interest in understanding and eliciting division of labor within groups of scientists. This paper illustrates the need for this division of labor through a historical example, and a formal model is presented to better analyze situations of this type. Analysis of this model reveals that a division of labor can be maintained in two different ways: by limiting information or by endowing the scientists with extreme beliefs. If both features are present however, cognitive diversity is maintained indefinitely, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   220 citations  
  • Commercialization and the Limits of Well-Ordered Science.Manuela Fernández Pinto - 2015 - Perspectives on Science 23 (2):173-191.
    In recent decades, philosophers of science have become increasingly concerned with the social dimensions of scientific knowledge. Philosophers such as Helen Longino, Philip Kitcher, Miriam Solomon, Heather Douglas, and Janet Kourany have sought to incorporate the social aspects of science, while retaining the normative commitments of philosophy of science. Some of the major theoretical approaches in social epistemology of science, however, tend to ignore or underestimate the role that the current state of science organization plays in the production of scientific (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Epistemic Landscapes, Optimal Search, and the Division of Cognitive Labor.Jason McKenzie Alexander, Johannes Himmelreich & Christopher Thompson - 2015 - Philosophy of Science 82 (3):424-453,.
    This article examines two questions about scientists’ search for knowledge. First, which search strategies generate discoveries effectively? Second, is it advantageous to diversify search strategies? We argue pace Weisberg and Muldoon, “Epistemic Landscapes and the Division of Cognitive Labor”, that, on the first question, a search strategy that deliberately seeks novel research approaches need not be optimal. On the second question, we argue they have not shown epistemic reasons exist for the division of cognitive labor, identifying the errors that led (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • The Epistemic Division of Labor Revisited.Johanna Thoma - 2015 - Philosophy of Science 82 (3):454-472.
    Some scientists are happy to follow in the footsteps of others; some like to explore novel approaches. It is tempting to think that herein lies an epistemic division of labor conducive to overall scientific progress: the latter point the way to fruitful areas of research, and the former more fully explore those areas. Weisberg and Muldoon’s model, however, suggests that it would be best if all scientists explored novel approaches. I argue that this is due to implausible modeling choices, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • (1 other version)Kuhn’s Social Epistemology and the Sociology of Science.K. Brad Wray - 2015 - In William J. Devlin & Alisa Bokulich (eds.), Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions - 50 Years On. Cham: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol. 311. Springer. pp. 167-183.
    This chapter discusses Kuhn’s conception of the history of science by focussing on two respects in which Kuhn is an historicist historian and philosopher of science. I identify two distinct, but related, aspects of historicism in the work of Hegel and show how these are also found in Kuhn’s work. First, Kuhn held tradition to be important for understanding scientific change and that the tradition from which a scientific idea originates must be understood in evaluating that idea. This makes Kuhn (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)Pragmatism, a New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking, Popular Lectures.William James - 1907
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Global Health and the Scientific Research Agenda.Philip Kitcher James H. Flory - 2004 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 32 (1):36-65.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • What Kinds of Science Should Be Done?Philip Kitcher - 2004 - In Alan Lightman, Daniel Sarewitz & Christina Desser (eds.), Living with the Genie. Island Press. pp. 201-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Commensuration Bias in Peer Review.Carole J. Lee - 2015 - Philosophy of Science 82 (5):1272-1283,.
    To arrive at their final evaluation of a manuscript or grant proposal, reviewers must convert a submission’s strengths and weaknesses for heterogeneous peer review criteria into a single metric of quality or merit. I identify this process of commensuration as the locus for a new kind of peer review bias. Commensuration bias illuminates how the systematic prioritization of some peer review criteria over others permits and facilitates problematic patterns of publication and funding in science. Commensuration bias also foregrounds a range (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Proliferation: Is It a Good Thing?Peter Achinstein - 2000 - In John Preston, Gonzalo Munévar & David Lamb (eds.), The Worst Enemy of Science?: Essays in Memory of Paul Feyerabend. New York: Oup Usa.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On the critique of scientific reason.Paul K. Feyerabend - 1976 - In R. S. Cohen, P. K. Feyerabend & M. Wartofsky (eds.), Essays in Memory of Imre Lakatos. Reidel. pp. 109--143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • History, Praxis and the 'Third World'.Stephen Toulmin - 1976 - In R. S. Cohen, P. K. Feyerabend & M. Wartofsky (eds.), Essays in Memory of Imre Lakatos. Reidel. pp. 655--675.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Consolations for the Specialist.Paul Feyerabend - 1970 - In Imre Lakatos & Alan Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge [Eng.]: Cambridge University Press. pp. 197.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   144 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes.Imre Lakatos - 1970 - In Imre Lakatos & Alan Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge [Eng.]: Cambridge University Press. pp. 91-196.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   688 citations  
  • (2 other versions)The Logic of Liberty.D. Daiches Raphael & Michael Polanyi - 1953 - Philosophical Quarterly 3 (10):86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Two Millian Arguments: Using Helen Longino’s Approach to Solve the Problems Philip Kitcher Targeted with His Argument on Freedom of Inquiry.Jaana Eigi - 2012 - Studia Philosophica Estonica 5 (1):44-63.
    Philip Kitcher argued that the freedom to pursue one's version of the good life is the main aim of Mill's argument for freedom of expression. According to Kitcher, in certain scientific fields, political and epistemological asymmetries bias research toward conclusions that threaten this most important freedom of underprivileged groups. Accordingly, Kitcher claimed that there are Millian grounds for limiting freedom of inquiry in these fields to protect the freedom of the underprivileged. -/- I explore Kitcher's argument in light of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry.Helen E. Longino - 1990 - Princeton University Press.
    This is an important book precisely because there is none other quite like it.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1097 citations  
  • (1 other version)Biomedical research, neglected diseases, and well-ordered science.Julian Reiss & Philip Kitcher - 2009 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 24 (3):263-282.
    In this paper we make a proposal for reforming biomedical research that is aimed to align re-search more closely with the so-called fair-share principle according to which the proportions of global resources as-signed to different diseases should agree with the ratios of human suffering associated with those diseases.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Feyerabend and Scientific Values: Tightrope-walking Rationality.Robert P. Farrell - 2003 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    In this book it is argued that this picture of Feyerabend is false.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Relations Between Experimental Physics and Mathematical Physics.Henri Poincaré - 1902 - The Monist 12 (4):516-543.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The tyranny of science.Paul K. Feyerabend - 2011 - Malden, MA: Polity Press. Edited by Eric Oberheim.
    Conflict and harmony -- The disunity of science -- The abundance of nature -- Dehumanizing humans.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Economy of Peirce's Abduction.W. M. Brown - 1983 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 19 (4):397 - 411.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Review: Changing Patterns of Reconstruction. [REVIEW]Paul Feyerabend - 1977 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28 (4):351 - 369.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • More letters by Paul Feyerabend to Thomas S. Kuhn on Proto-Structure.Paul Hoyningen-Huene - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37 (4):610-632.
    The paper contains two yet unknown letters that Feyerabend wrote to Kuhn in 1960 or 1961 on a draft of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. In these letters, Feyerabend criticises both details of Kuhn's book and its general direction. The letters anticipate many of the arguments that were put forward in the public controversy against Kuhn's position, including some of the (numerous) misunderstandings. Feyerabend's assertions and arguments are very characteristic of his position in the early sixties.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • CCR: A Refutation.J. W. N. Watkins - 1971 - Philosophy 46 (175):56-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Well‐Ordered Science: Evidence for Use.Nancy Cartwright - 2006 - Philosophy of Science 73 (5):981-990.
    This article agrees with Philip Kitcher that we should aim for a well-ordered science, one that answers the right questions in the right ways. Crucial to this is to address questions of use: Which scientific account is right for which system in which circumstances? This is a difficult question: evidence that may support a scientific claim in one context may not support it in another. Drawing on examples in physics and other sciences, this article argues that work on the warrant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Book Review:The Poverty of Historicism. Karl R. Popper. [REVIEW]Leon J. Goldstein - 1957 - Ethics 68 (4):296-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   123 citations  
  • The Role of the Priority Rule in Science.Michael Strevens - 2003 - Journal of Philosophy 100 (2):55-79.
    Science's priority rule rewards those who are first to make a discovery, at the expense of all other scientists working towards the same goal, no matter how close they may be to making the same discovery. I propose an explanation of the priority rule that, better than previous explanations, accounts for the distinctive features of the rule. My explanation treats the priority system, and more generally, any scheme of rewards for scientific endeavor, as a device for achieving an allocation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   167 citations  
  • The poverty of historicism.Karl Raimund Popper - 1960 - London,: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
    Hailed on publication in 1957 as "probably the only book published this year that will outlive the century," this is a brilliant of the idea that there are ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   262 citations  
  • Against method: outline of an anarchistic theory of knowledge.Paul Feyerabend - 1974 - Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press.
    Paul Feyerabend's globally acclaimed work, which sparked and continues to stimulate fierce debate, examines the deficiencies of many widespread ideas about scientific progress and the nature of knowledge. Feyerabend argues that scientific advances can only be understood in a historical context. He looks at the way the philosophy of science has consistently overemphasized practice over method, and considers the possibility that anarchism could replace rationalism in the theory of knowledge. -- Amazon.com.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   226 citations  
  • Problems of empiricism.Paul Feyerabend - 1965 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Over the past thirty years Paul Feyerabend has developed an extremely distinctive and influentical approach to problems in the philosophy of science. The most important and seminal of his published essays are collected here in two volumes, with new introductions to provide an overview and historical perspective on the discussions of each part. Volume 1 presents papers on the interpretation of scientific theories, together with papers applying the views developed to particular problems in philosophy and physics. The essays in volume (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   103 citations  
  • Science, truth, and democracy.Philip Kitcher - 2001 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Striving to boldly redirect the philosophy of science, this book by renowned philosopher Philip Kitcher examines the heated debate surrounding the role of science in shaping our lives. Kitcher explores the sharp divide between those who believe that the pursuit of scientific knowledge is always valuable and necessary--the purists--and those who believe that it invariably serves the interests of people in positions of power. In a daring turn, he rejects both perspectives, working out a more realistic image of the sciences--one (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   464 citations  
  • The advancement of science: science without legend, objectivity without illusions.Philip Kitcher - 1993 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    During the last three decades, reflections on the growth of scientific knowledge have inspired historians, sociologists, and some philosophers to contend that scientific objectivity is a myth. In this book, Kitcher attempts to resurrect the notions of objectivity and progress in science by identifying both the limitations of idealized treatments of growth of knowledge and the overreactions to philosophical idealizations. Recognizing that science is done not by logically omniscient subjects working in isolation, but by people with a variety of personal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   746 citations  
  • Justice by lottery.Barbara Goodwin - 1992 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    In this imaginative and provocative book, Barbara Goodwin explores the question of how lottery systems can achieve egalitarian social justice in societies with seemingly ineradicable inequalities. She begins with the utopian fable of Aleatoria, a country not unlike our own in the not-too-distant-future, where most goods are distributed by lottery--even the right to have children. She then analyzes the philosophical arguments for and against lottery distribution and a comparison of "justice by lottery" with other contemporary theories of justice. Goodwin also (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations