Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Kant's Gesammelte Schriften.Immanuel Kant, Akademie der Wissenschaften, Kant-Gesellschaft, D. D. R. Akademie der Wissenschaften der & Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin - 1928
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • (1 other version)Peirce’s Progress From Nominalism Toward Realism.Max Fisch - 1967 - The Monist 51 (2):159-178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce: Pragmatism and pragmaticism and Scientific metaphysics.Charles Sanders Peirce - 1960 - Cambridge: Belknap Press.
    Charles Sanders Peirce has been characterized as the greatest American philosophic genius. He is the creator of pragmatism and one of the founders of modern logic. James, Royce, Schroder, and Dewey have acknowledged their great indebtedness to him. A laboratory scientist, he made notable contributions to geodesy, astronomy, psychology, induction, probability, and scientific method. He introduced into modern philosophy the doctrine of scholastic realism, developed the concepts of chance, continuity, and objective law, and showed the philosophical significance of the theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   515 citations  
  • The Logic of Hegel's 'Logic': An Introduction.John W. Burbidge - 2006 - Peterborough, CA: Broadview Press.
    George Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel has seldom been considered a major figure in the history of logic. His two texts on logic, both called The Science of Logic, both written in Hegel's characteristically dense and obscure language, are often considered more as works of metaphysics than logic. But in this highly readable book, John Burbidge sets out to reclaim Hegel's Science of Logic as logic and to get right at the heart of Hegel's thought. Burbidge examines the way Hegel moves from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Correspondance.Immanuel Kant, Marie-Christine Challiol, Michèle Halimi, Valérie Séroussi, Nicolas Aumonier & Marc B. de Launay - 1993 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 98 (1):277-279.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Critique of Pure Reason.I. Kant - 1787/1998 - Philosophy 59 (230):555-557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1906 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Critique of Pure Reason.Immanuel Kant - 1929 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Edited by J. M. D. Meiklejohn. Translated by Paul Guyer & Allen W. Wood.
    This entirely new translation of Critique of Pure Reason by Paul Guyer and Allan Wood is the most accurate and informative English translation ever produced of this epochal philosophical text. Though its simple, direct style will make it suitable for all new readers of Kant, the translation displays a philosophical and textual sophistication that will enlighten Kant scholars as well. This translation recreates as far as possible a text with the same interpretative nuances and richness as the original.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   411 citations  
  • An Hegelian in Strange Costume? On Peirce’s Relation to Hegel II.Robert Stern - 2013 - Philosophy Compass 8 (1):63-72.
    In this paper, which is the second in a series, I continue to consider the relation between the American pragmatist Charles Sanders Peirce and the German idealist G. W. F. Hegel. This article focuses on their views of epistemology and inquiry, and their accounts of the relation between language and thought. As with the earlier paper, it is argued that fruitful similarities between their positions on these issues can be found.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • ‘Can Pragmatic Realists Argue Transcendentally?’.Kenneth R. Westphal - 2003 - In John R. Shook (ed.), Pragmatic Naturalism and Realism. Prometheus.
    Kant’s and Hegel’s transcendental argument for mental-content externalism breaks the deadlock between ‘internal’ and genuine realists. This argument shows that human beings can only be self-conscious in a world that provides a humanly recognizable regularity and variety among the things (or events) we sense. This feature of the world cannot result from human thought or language. Hence semantic arguments against realism can only be developed if realism about the world is true. Some of Putnam’s arguments for internal realism are taken (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Peirce as Educator: On Some Hegelisms.Kipton E. Jensen - 2004 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 40 (2):271 - 288.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Was pragmatism the successor to idealism?Terry Pinkard - 2007 - In Cheryl Misak (ed.), New pragmatists. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Hegel and realism.Kenneth R. Westphal - 2006 - In John R. Shook & Joseph Margolis (eds.), A Companion to Pragmatism. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 177–183.
    This article summarizes the systematic importance of Hegel’s philosophy for pragmatism, and in particular for the contemporary revival of pragmatic realism. Key points lie in Hegel’s internal critique of Kant’s transcendental idealism, on the basis of which Hegel demonstrates that we can be self-conscious only if we are conscious of nature. This insight enables Hegel to develop genuinely transcendental proofs without invoking transcendental idealism. Hegel uses this result to defend realism about the molar objects of empirical knowledge against Pyrrhonian, Cartesian, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The continuity of Peirce's thought.Kelly A. Parker - 1998 - Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press.
    A comprehensive and systematic reconstruction of the philosophy of Charles S. Peirce, perhaps America's most far-ranging and original philosopher, which reveals the unity of his complex and influential body of thought. We are still in the early stages of understanding the thought of C. S. Peirce (1839-1914). Although much good work has been done in isolated areas, relatively little considers the Peircean system as a whole. Peirce made it his life's work to construct a scientifically sophisticated and logically rigorous philosophical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Lectures on the history of philosophy (selections).G. W. F. Hegel - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   173 citations  
  • Desire and natural classification: Aristotle and Peirce on final cause.Stephen B. Hawkins - 2007 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 43 (3):521 - 541.
    Peirce was greatly influenced by Aristotle, particularly on the topic of final cause. Commentators are therefore right to draw on Aristotle in the interpretation of Peirce's teleology. But these commentators sometimes fail to distinguish clearly between formal cause and final cause in Aristotle's philosophy. Unless form and end are clearly distinguished, no sense can be made of Peirce's important claim that 'desires create classes.' Understood in the context of his teleology, this claim may be considered Peirce's answer to nominalists and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Language, Objects, and the Missing Link: Toward a Hegelean Theory of Reference.Katharina Dulckeit - 2006 - In Jere O'Neill Surber (ed.), Hegel and Language. State University of New York Press. pp. 145-164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Can Hegel Refer to Particulars?Patricia Jagentowicz Mills, Robert D. Walsh, Gary Shapiro, Katharina Dulckeit, George Armstrong Kelly, Merold Westphal, William Desmond, Joseph Fitzer, William Leon McBride & Thomas F. O'Meara - 1986 - The Owl of Minerva 17 (2):181-194.
    Hegel introduced the Phenomenology of Mind as a work on the problem of knowledge. In the first chapter, entitled “Sense Certainty, or the This and Meaning,” he concluded that knowledge cannot consist of an immediate awareness of particulars ). The tradition discusses sense certainty in terms of this failure of immediate knowledge without, however, specifically addressing the problem of reference. Yet reference is distinct from knowledge in the sense that while there can be no knowledge of objects without reference, there (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Hegel’s Epistemology: A Philosophical Introduction to the Phenomenology of Spirit.Kenneth R. Westphal - 2003 - Hackett.
    Though concise and introductory, this book argues inter alia that Dretske’s information-theoretic epistemology must take into account that many of our information channels are socially constructed, not least through learning concepts and information. These social aspects of human knowledge are consistent with realism about the objects of our empirical knowledge. It further argues that, though important, Margaret Gilbert’s social ontology in principle can neither accommodate nor account for the most fundamental social dimensions of human cognition.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Hegel, Peirce, and Royce on the Concept of Essence.John Kaag - 2011 - Dialogue 50 (3):557-575.
    ABSTRACT: This article focuses on the role that Hegels discussion of Hegel and Peirce by claiming that the second book of HegelThe Doctrine of Essence,s attempt to account for the experimental and turbulent character of human experience, a character that Peirce would term While Pierce remained dissatisfied with Hegels detailed understanding of Hegel.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Perspectives on pragmatism: classical, recent, and contemporary.Robert Brandom - 2011 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Classical American pragmatism: the pragmatist -- Enlightenment-and its problematic semantics -- Analyzing pragmatism: pragmatics and pragmatisms -- A Kantian rationalist pragmatism: pragmatism -- Inferentialism, and modality in Sellars's arguments against -- Empiricism -- Linguistic pragmatism and pragmatism about norms: an arc of -- Thought from Rorty's eliminative materialism to his pragmatism -- Vocabularies of pragmatism: synthesizing naturalism and -- Historicism -- Towards an analytic pragmatism: meaning-use analysis -- Pragmatism, expressivism, and anti-representationalism: -- Local and global possibilities.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Peirce on Hegel: Nominalist or Realist.R. Stern - 2005 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 41 (1):65-99.
    My aim in this paper is to consider one of Peirce's criticisms of Hegel, namely, that Hegel was a nominalist. Of the various criticisms of Hegel that Peirce offers, this has been little discussed, perhaps because it is puzzling to find Peirce making it at all. For, Peirce also criticises Hegel for his overzealous enthusiasm for Thirdness, where it is then hard to see how Hegel can have both faults: how can anyone who acknowledges the significance of Thirdness in Peirce's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Charles Peirce and scholastic realism.John F. Boler - 1963 - Seattle,: University of Washington Press.
    IN 1903, commenting on an article he had written more than thirty years before, Charles Peirce said that he had changed his mind on many issues at least a half-dozen times but had "never been able to think differently on that question of nominalism and realism" (1.20). For anyone acquainted with Peirce's writings, this remark alone could justify a study of "that question.".
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Peirce's Debt to F. E. Abbot.Daniel D. O'Connor - 1964 - Journal of the History of Ideas 25 (4):543.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (3 other versions)Charles Sanders Peirce: A Life.Joseph Brent - 1993 - History and Philosophy of Logic 14 (2):531-538.
    Charles Sanders Peirce was born in September 1839 and died five months before the guns of August 1914. He is perhaps the most important mind the United States has ever produced. He made significant contributions throughout his life as a mathematician, astronomer, chemist, geodesist, surveyor, cartographer, metrologist, engineer, and inventor. He was a psychologist, a philologist, a lexicographer, a historian of science, a lifelong student of medicine, and, above all, a philosopher, whose special fields were logic and semiotics. He is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings Vol. 1.Charles Peirce, Christian S. & Nathan House J. W. Kloesel - 1992 - Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • (1 other version)Can Hegel Refer to Particulars?Katharina Dulckeit - 1986 - The Owl of Minerva 17 (2):181-194.
    Hegel introduced the Phenomenology of Mind as a work on the problem of knowledge. In the first chapter, entitled “Sense Certainty, or the This and Meaning,” he concluded that knowledge cannot consist of an immediate awareness of particulars ). The tradition discusses sense certainty in terms of this failure of immediate knowledge without, however, specifically addressing the problem of reference. Yet reference is distinct from knowledge in the sense that while there can be no knowledge of objects without reference, there (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Naturalizing the transcendental: a pragmatic view.Sami Pihlström - 2003 - Amherst, N.Y.: Humanity Books.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Peirce.Christopher Hookway - 1985 - New York: Routledge. Edited by Ted Honderich.
    This book is available either individually, or as part of the specially-priced Arguments of the Philosphers Collection.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Peirce and the Threat of Nominalism.Paul Forster - 2011 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Charles Peirce, the founder of pragmatism, was a thinker of extraordinary depth and range - he wrote on philosophy, mathematics, psychology, physics, logic, phenomenology, semiotics, religion and ethics - but his writings are difficult and fragmentary. This book provides a clear and comprehensive explanation of Peirce's thought. His philosophy is presented as a systematic response to 'nominalism', the philosophy which he most despised and which he regarded as the underpinning of the dominant philosophical worldview of his time. The book explains (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Charles S. Peirce: from pragmatism to pragmaticism.Karl-Otto Apel - 1981 - Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press.
    Reflecting a revival of Peirce studies and the rediscovery of the pragmatist tradition in American philosophical thinking, this study articulates a contemporary and relevant interpretation that may offer a challenge to neo-pragmatists.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • (1 other version)Peirce’s Progress From Nominalism Toward Realism.Max Fisch - 1967 - The Monist 51 (2):159-178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The pragmatism of Peirce and Hegel.H. G. Townsend - 1928 - Philosophical Review 37 (4):297-303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Peirce, Hegel, and the category of secondness.Robert Stern - 2007 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 50 (2):123 – 155.
    This paper focuses on one of C. S. Peirce's criticisms of G. W. F. Hegel: namely, that Hegel neglected to give sufficient weight to what Peirce calls "Secondness", in a way that put his philosophical system out of touch with reality. The nature of this criticism is explored, together with its relevant philosophical background. It is argued that while the issues Peirce raises go deep, in some respects Hegel's position is closer to his own than he may have realised, whilst (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Peirce's Objective Idealism: A Defense.Claudine Tiercelin - 1998 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 34 (1):1 - 28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Peirce's Critique of Hegel's Phenomenology and Dialectic.Gary Shapiro - 1981 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 17 (3):269 - 275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Science of Logic.M. J. Petry, G. W. F. Hegel, A. V. Miller & J. N. Findlay - 1970 - Philosophical Quarterly 20 (80):273.
    First published in 2002. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   239 citations  
  • Peirce and the Threat of Nominalism.Paul D. Forster - 1992 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 28 (4):691.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Peirce and Leibniz.Max H. Fisch - 1972 - Journal of the History of Ideas 33 (3):485.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Scientific Theism.Francis Ellingwood Abbot - 1886 - Mind 11 (43):409-414.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Scientific Theism.Francis Ellingwood Abbott - 1887 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 23:645-653.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations