Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Logik der Forderungssätze.Rose Rand - 1940 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 5 (1):41-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Contrary-to-duty obligations.Henry Prakken & Marek Sergot - 1996 - Studia Logica 57 (1):91 - 115.
    We investigate under what conditions contrary-to-duty (CTD) structures lacking temporal and action elements can be given a coherent reading. We argue, contrary to some recent proposals, that CTD is not an instance of defeasible reasoning, and that methods of nonmonotonic logics are inadequate since they are unable to distinguish between defeasibility and violation of primary obligations. We propose a semantic framework based on the idea that primary and CTD obligations are obligations of different kinds: a CTD obligation pertains to, or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • What can Logic do for Philosophy?K. R. Popper, W. C. Kneale & A. J. Ayer - 1948 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 22 (1):141-178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Open Society and its Enemies: The Spell of Plato.Karl Popper - 2002 - Routledge.
    ‘If in this book harsh words are spoken about some of the greatest among the intellectual leaders of mankind, my motive is not, I hope, to belittle them. It springs rather from my conviction that, if our civilization is to survive, we must break with the habit of deference to great men.’ - Karl Popper, from the Preface Written in political exile during the Second World War and first published in two volumes in 1945, Karl Popper’s The Open Society and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   138 citations  
  • Knowledge and Justification.John L. Pollock - 1974 - Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Edited by John Pollock.
    Princeton University Press, 1974. This book is out of print, but can be downloaded as a pdf file (5 MB).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   176 citations  
  • Knowledge and Justification.Robert L. Martin - 1976 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 36 (3):435-436.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Defeasible Reasoning.John L. Pollock - 1987 - Cognitive Science 11 (4):481-518.
    There was a long tradition in philosophy according to which good reasoning had to be deductively valid. However, that tradition began to be questioned in the 1960’s, and is now thoroughly discredited. What caused its downfall was the recognition that many familiar kinds of reasoning are not deductively valid, but clearly confer justification on their conclusions. Here are some simple examples.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   336 citations  
  • Dernières Pensées.Henri Poincaré - 1920 - CreateSpace.
    "Dernières pensées" de Henri Poincaré. Mathématicien, physicien et philosophe français (1854-1912).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Command and consequence.Josh Parsons - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 164 (1):61-92.
    An argument is usually said to be valid iff it is truth-preserving—iff it cannot be that all its premises are true and its conclusion false. But imperatives (it is normally thought) are not truth-apt. They are not in the business of saying how the world is, and therefore cannot either succeed or fail in doing so. To solve this problem, we need to find a new criterion of validity, and I aim to propose such a criterion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Cognitivism about imperatives.Josh Parsons - 2012 - Analysis 72 (1):49-54.
    Cognitivism about imperatives is the thesis that sentences in the imperative mood are truth-apt: have truth values and truth conditions. This allows cognitivists to give a simple and powerful account of consequence relations between imperatives. I argue that this account of imperative consequence has counterexamples that cast doubt on cognitivism itself.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Introduction.Donald Nute - 1981 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (2):127 - 147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Defeasible Deontic Logic.Donald Nute - 2000 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 6 (1):89-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Imperatives and their logics.Nicholas J. Moutafakis - 1975 - New Delhi: Sterling Publishers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Imperatives and their Logics.Brian F. Chellas - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (2):375-376.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Poincaré's rule (oder: Wie aus einer schlechten übersetzung eine legende entsteht).Edgar Morscher - 1972 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 10 (3):350-353.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Der praktische Syllogismus and das juridische Denken.Manfred Moritz - 1954 - Theoria 20 (1-3):78-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Clarke's principle of mood constancy.Edgar Morscher & Gerhard Zecha - 1971 - Philosophia 1 (3-4):209-217.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Russell's "Theory of Descriptions.".G. E. Moore - 1944 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 9 (3):78-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Truthmakers for negative truths.George Molnar - 2000 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78 (1):72 – 86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • The Principle of Mood Constancy.Alfred F. MacKay - 1971 - Analysis 31 (3):91 - 96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The principle of mood constancy.Alfred F. Mackay - 1971 - Analysis 31 (3):91-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Logical constants.John MacFarlane - 2008 - Mind.
    Logic is usually thought to concern itself only with features that sentences and arguments possess in virtue of their logical structures or forms. The logical form of a sentence or argument is determined by its syntactic or semantic structure and by the placement of certain expressions called “logical constants.”[1] Thus, for example, the sentences Every boy loves some girl. and Some boy loves every girl. are thought to differ in logical form, even though they share a common syntactic and semantic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Inferential Validity and Imperative Inference Rules.Alfred F. MacKay - 1969 - Analysis 29 (5):145 - 156.
    It would seem possible in principle … to reconstruct the ordinary sentential calculus in terms of phrastics only, and then apply it to indicatives and imperatives alike simply by adding the appropriate neustics.… It might be asked how we are to know, given two premisses in different moods, in what mood the conclusion is to be. The problem of the effect upon inferences of the moods of premisses and conclusion has been ignored by logicians who have not looked beyond the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Imperatives, reasons for action, and morals.Alasdair MacIntyre - 1965 - Journal of Philosophy 62 (19):513-524.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Logical Constants.K. Warmbrõd - 1999 - Mind 108 (431):503 - 538.
    There is as yet no settled consensus as to what makes a term a logical constant or even as to which terms should be recognized as having this status. This essay sets out and defends a rationale for identifying logical constants. I argue for a two-tiered approach to logical theory. First, a secure, core logical theory recognizes only a minimal set of constants needed for deductively systematizing scientific theories. Second, there are extended logical theories whose objectives are to systematize various (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Ifs and Oughts.Niko Kolodny & John MacFarlane - 2010 - Journal of Philosophy 107 (3):115-143.
    We consider a paradox involving indicative conditionals (‘ifs’) and deontic modals (‘oughts’). After considering and rejecting several standard options for resolv- ing the paradox—including rejecting various premises, positing an ambiguity or hidden contextual sensitivity, and positing a non-obvious logical form—we offer a semantics for deontic modals and indicative conditionals that resolves the paradox by making modus ponens invalid. We argue that this is a result to be welcomed on independent grounds, and we show that rejecting the general validity of modus (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   246 citations  
  • Review of Hans Kelsen: General theory of norms[REVIEW]Martin P. Golding - 1993 - Ethics 103 (4):824-827.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • General theory of norms.Hans Kelsen - 1990 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Hans Kelsen is considered by many to be the foremost legal thinker of the twentieth century. During the last decade of his life he was working on what he called a general theory of norms. Published posthumously in 1979 as Allgemeine Theorie der Normen, the book is here translated for the first time into English. Kelsen develops his "pure theory of law" into a "general theory of norms", and analyzes the applicability of logic to norms to offer an original and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Imperatives and logic.Jörgen Jörgensen - 1937 - Erkenntnis 7 (1):288-296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Which Modal Logic Is the Right One?John P. Burgess - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (1):81-93.
    The question, "Which modal logic is the right one for logical necessity?," divides into two questions, one about model-theoretic validity, the other about proof-theoretic demonstrability. The arguments of Halldén and others that the right validity argument is S5, and the right demonstrability logic includes S4, are reviewed, and certain common objections are argued to be fallacious. A new argument, based on work of Supecki and Bryll, is presented for the claim that the right demonstrability logic must be contained in S5, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Book Review: Stewart Shapiro. Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology. [REVIEW]John P. Burgess - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (2):283-291.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • A Reconsideration of an Argument against Compatibilism.Thomas J. McKay & David Johnson - 1996 - Philosophical Topics 24 (2):113-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Being Positive About Negative Facts.Mark Jago & Stephen Barker - 2012 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85 (1):117-138.
    Negative facts get a bad press. One reason for this is that it is not clear what negative facts are. We provide a theory of negative facts on which they are no stranger than positive atomic facts. We show that none of the usual arguments hold water against this account. Negative facts exist in the usual sense of existence and conform to an acceptable Eleatic principle. Furthermore, there are good reasons to want them around, including their roles in causation, chance-making (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Van Inwagen’s Consequence Argument.Michael Huemer - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (4):525-544.
    Peter van Inwagen ’s argument for incompatibilism uses a sentential operator, “N”, which can be read as “No one has any choice about the fact that....” I show that, given van Inwagen ’s understanding of the notion of having a choice, the argument is invalid. However, a different interpretation of “N” can be given, such that the argument is clearly valid, the premises remain highly plausible, and the conclusion implies that free will is incompatible with determinism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Van Inwagen’s Consequence Argument.Michael Huemer - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (4):525.
    Peter van Inwagen has presented a compelling argument for the incompatibility of free will and determinism, which he calls “the Consequence Argument.” This argument depends on a controversial inference rule, “rule beta,” which says.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Moral dilemmas and nonmonotonic logic.John F. Horty - 1994 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 23 (1):35 - 65.
    From a philosophical standpoint, the work presented here is based on van Fraassen [26]. The bulk of that paper is organized around a series of arguments against the assumption, built into standard deontic logic, that moral dilemmas are impossible; and van Fraassen only briefly sketches his alternative approach. His paper ends with the conclusion that “the problem of possibly irresolvable moral conflict reveals serious flaws in the philosophical and semantic foundations of ‘orthodox’ deontic logic, but also suggests a rich set (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Words and Deeds: Problems in the Theory of Speech Acts.David Holdcroft - 1978 - Oxford University Press.
    The book presents a theory of illocutionary acts. It argues that the study of speech acts initiatied by Austin complements the truth theoretic approach to speaker meaning. It is shown that there are aspects of speaker meaning which cannot be explained by truth theoretic approaches. Though the nature of a speech act is partially determined by the semantic type of the the sentence uttered the speaker's intention and context of utterance are important also.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Universal and Past-Tense Prescriptions: A Reply to Mr. Ibberson.R. M. Hake - 1979 - Analysis 39 (4):161 - 165.
    Properly universal prescriptions (necessary in analysis of value-judgments) entail past-tense imperatives. does the unusability of the latter rule out the former? no, because there are many usable rules which entail past-tense imperatives. else we could not point to past breaches when teaching the rule, which remains the same throughout the teaching process, or punish for past breaches of the same rule which is still in force. similar problem about imperatives in other than the second person succumbs to kenny's distinction between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Some alleged differences between imperatives and indicatives.R. M. Hare - 1967 - Mind 76 (303):309-326.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Propositional Structure and Illocutionary Force: A Study of the Contribution of Sentence Meaning to Speech Acts. [REVIEW]Robert M. Harnish & Jerrold J. Katz - 1983 - Philosophical Review 92 (1):103.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Is modal logic logic?Gilbert Harman - 1972 - Philosophia 2 (1-2):75-84.
    (1) modal logic is not needed, Since there are alternative accounts of modality. (2) modal logic does not function as logic even in the thinking of its advocates, As is revealed, E.G., When the semantics of modal logic is presented in an extensional metalanguage. Furthermore, (3) when a wider view is taken, One sees that modal logic treats as logical constants expressions that belong to a large and open syntactic class, Unlike other logical constants. Finally, (4) modal logic treats as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Zur Logik der Sollsaetze.Kurt Grelling - 1939 - Synthese 4 (1):A44-A47.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Conditional oughts and hypothetical imperatives.P. S. Greenspan - 1975 - Journal of Philosophy 72 (10):259-276.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • What Is Imperative Inference?André Gombay - 1967 - Analysis 27 (5):145 - 152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Truth and correct belief.Allan Gibbard - 2005 - Philosophical Issues 15 (1):338–350.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   124 citations  
  • Imperatives and indicatives (I).P. C. Gibbons - 1960 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 38 (2):107 – 119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Imperatives and indicatives (II).P. C. Gibbons - 1960 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 38 (3):207 – 217.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Imperatives and Indicatives: I.P. C. Gibbons - 1960 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 38:107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Imperative and deontic logic.Peter Geach - 1957 - Analysis 18 (3):49-56.
    The author contends that moral utterances and imperatives have different logical features. He discusses r m hare's "language of morals" in terms of his distinction between plain imperatives and deontic utterances. (staff).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Logic and the Basis of Ethics.W. K. Frankena - 1950 - Philosophical Review 59 (4):554.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations