Switch to: References

Citations of:

Nicomachean Ethics

New York: Hackett Publishing Company. Edited by C. C. W. Taylor (1911)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Conditions for ‘Upbuilding’: A Reply to Nigel Tubbs’ Reading of Kierkegaard.Stein M. Wivestad - 2011 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 45 (4):613-625.
    A Special Issue of the Journal of Philosophy of Education, 2005, issue 2, contains an interesting ‘Philosophy of the Teacher’ by Nigel Tubbs. It rejects attempts in pedagogical traditions to ignore or avoid the contradiction between the teacher as master and as servant, and ends with an interpretation of ‘upbuilding’, a central concept in Søren Kierkegaard’s writings. According to Tubbs’ reading, the teacher’s patient struggle with herself in doubt is the basic condition for upbuilding, whereby the eternal’s perfect gift of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Corporate profit, entrepreneurship theory and business ethics.Radu Vranceanu - 2014 - Business Ethics, the Environment and Responsibility 23 (1):50-68.
    Economic profit is produced by entrepreneurs, those special individuals able to detect and seize as yet unexploited market opportunities. Many large capitalist firms manage to deliver positive profits even in the most competitive environments. They can do so, thanks to internal entrepreneurs, a subset of their employees able to drive change and develop innovation in the workplace. This paper argues that the goal of increasing economic profit is fully consistent with the corporation doing good for society. However, there is little (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Against Parsimony: Three Easy Ways of Complicating some Categories of Economic Discourse.Albert O. Hirschman - 1985 - Economics and Philosophy 1 (1):7-21.
    Economics as a science of human behavior has been grounded in a remarkably parsimonious postulate: that of the self-interested, isolated individual who chooses freely and rationally between alternative courses of action after computing their prospective costs and benefits. In recent decades, a group of economists has shown considerable industry and ingenuity in applying this way of interpreting the social world to a series of ostensibly noneconomic phenomena, from crime to the family, and from collective action to democracy. The “economic” or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Britishness, Belonging and the Ideology of Conflict: Lessons from the Polis.Derek Edyvane - 2011 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 45 (1):75-93.
    A central aspiration of the ‘Britishness’ agenda in UK politics is to promote community through the teaching of British values in schools. The agenda’s justification depends in part on the suppositions that harmony arising from agreement on certain values is a necessary condition of social health and that conflict arising from pluralism connotes a form of dysfunction in social life. These perceptions of harmony and conflict are traceable to the ancient Greeks. Plato used the device of the soul-city analogy to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • “Instincts into sacred cows”: Are hermeneutical universalsreducibleto agreement? Reply to Friedman.Ingrid Harris - 1994 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 8 (1):113-136.
    Jeffrey Friedman's claim that arbitrariness is the inevitable result of the rejection of objectivist notions of truth misses its mark because it is based on a sense of ?agreement? that is radically at odds with the concept of agreement at work in hermeneutical practice. The rationalist notion of truth Friedman upholds cannot escape the need for agreement any more than the hermeneutical notion; the central distinction between the two senses of ?agreement? is the distinction between coercion and consent. Hermeneutical practice (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Moral courage in the workplace: Moving to and from the desire and decision to act.Leslie E. Sekerka & Richard P. Bagozzi - 2007 - Business Ethics, the Environment and Responsibility 16 (2):132–149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Nietzsche on art and freedom.Aaron Ridley - 2007 - European Journal of Philosophy 15 (2):204–224.
    There are passages in Nietzsche that can be read as contributions to the free will/determinism debate. When read in that way, they reveal a fairly amateurish metaphysician with little of real substance or novelty to contribute; and if these readings were apt or perspicuous, it seems to me, they would show that Nietzsche's thoughts about freedom were barely worth pausing over. They would simply confirm the impression—amply bolstered from other quarters—that Nietzsche was not at his best when addressing the staple (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Ethical codes, independence and the conservation of ambiguity.Michael Page & Laura F. Spira - 2005 - Business Ethics, the Environment and Responsibility 14 (3):301–316.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On the varieties of phronesis.Jand Noel - 1999 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 31 (3):273–289.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Teaching right and wrong: A somewhat irritating expression.Bruce Maxwell - 2006 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 40 (3):405–412.
    This article critically reviews Colin Wringe's Moral Education: Beyond the Teaching of Right and Wrong. The book has three broad aims. The first is to illustrate the philosophical deficiencies of the conceptualisation of moral education underlying two recently published UK government documents on values education. The second is to develop a pluralistic prescriptive account of mature moral judgement, putatively as a point of reference for the educational promotion of moral development. Finally, Wringe presents his views on how certain perennially contested (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Nature of the Gift: Accountability and the Professor‐Student Relationship.Ana M. Martínez-Alemán - 2007 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 39 (6):574–591.
    In this paper I introduce the theory of gift giving as a possible means to reconcile the contradictions inherent in accountability measures of ‘faculty productivity’ in the American university. In this paper I sketch the theory of gift economies to show how, given the historical ideals that characterize the faculty‐student relationship, a theory of gift giving could help us better judge the labor of the faculty. I suggest that it is the relational character of teaching that frustrates accountability measures and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Spinoza's summum bonum.Michael Lebuffe - 2005 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86 (2):243–266.
    : As Spinoza presents it, the knowledge of God is knowledge, primarily, of oneself and, secondarily, of other things. Without this know‐ledge, a mind may not consciously desire to persevere in being. That is why Spinoza claims that the knowledge of God is the most useful thing to the mind at IVP28. He claims that the knowledge of God is the highest good, however, not because it is instrumental to perseverance, but because it is also the best among those goods (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Justified self-esteem.Kristján Kristjánsson - 2007 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 41 (2):247–261.
    This paper develops a thread of argument from previous contributions to this journal by Richard Smith and Ruth Cigman about the educational salience of self-esteem. It is argued—contra Smith and Cigman—that the social science conception of self-esteem does serve a useful educational function, most importantly in undermining the inflated self-help conception of self-esteem that has commonly been transposed to the educational arena. Recent findings about a lack of significant correlation between low global self-esteem and relevant educational variables help us to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • What makes practice educational?Pádraig Hogan - 1990 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 24 (1):15–27.
    Pádraig Hogan; What Makes Practice Educational?, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 24, Issue 1, 30 May 2006, Pages 15–26, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Work and human flourishing.Geoffrey Hinchliffe - 2004 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 36 (5):535–547.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Truth and the capability of learning.Geoffrey Hinchliffe - 2007 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 41 (2):221–232.
    This paper examines learning as a capability, taking as its starting point the work of Amartya Sen and Martha Nussbaum. The paper is concerned to highlight the relation between learning and truth, and it does so by examining the idea of a genealogy of truth and also Donald Davidson’s coherence theory. Thus the notion of truth is understood to be not only built into the capability of learning but also translated across into other capabilities.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Trust as an instance of asymmetrical reciprocity: An ethics perspective on corporate brand management.Clara Gustafsson - 2005 - Business Ethics, the Environment and Responsibility 14 (2):142–150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Trust as an instance of asymmetrical reciprocity: an ethics perspective on corporate brand management.Clara Gustafsson - 2005 - Business Ethics, the Environment and Responsibility 14 (2):142-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Managerial modes of accountability and practical knowledge: Reclaiming the practical.Jane Green - 2004 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 36 (5):549–562.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Three sorts of naturalism.Hans Fink - 2006 - European Journal of Philosophy 14 (2):202–221.
    In "Two sorts of Naturalism" John McDowell is sketching his own sort of naturalism in ethics as an alternative to "bald naturalism". In this paper I distinguish materialist, idealist and absolute conceptions of nature and of naturalism in order to provide a framework for a clearer understanding of what McDowell’s own naturalism amounts to. I argue that nothing short of an absolute naturalism will do for a number of McDowell's own purposes, but that it is far from obvious that this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Hippias major, version 1.0: Software for post-colonial, multicultural technology systems.Gene Fendt - 2003 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 37 (1):89–99.
    The first half of Plato’s Hippias Major exhibits the interfacing of the first teacher (Socrates) with the first version of a post-colonial, multi-cultural information technology system (Hippias). In this interface the purposes, results, and values of two contradictory types of operating system for educational servicing units are exhibited to, and can be discovered by, anyone who is not an information technologist.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The good life: A defense of attitudinal hedonism.Fred Feldman - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (3):604-628.
    The students and colleagues of Roderick Chisholm admired and respected Chisholm. Many were filled not only with admiration, but with affection and gratitude for Chisholm throughout the time we knew him. Even now that he is dead, we continue to wish him well. Under the circumstances, many of us probably think that that wish amounts to no more than this: we hope that things went well for him when he lived; we hope that he had a good life.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Intuitive hedonism.Joseph Endola - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 128 (2):441 - 477.
    The hoary philosophical tradition of hedonism – the view that pleasure is the basic ethical or normative value – suggests that it is at least reasonably and roughly intuitive. But philosophers no longer treat hedonism that way. For the most part, they think that they know it to be obviously false on intuitive grounds, much more obviously false on such grounds than familiar competitors. I argue that this consensus is wrong. I defend the intuitive cogency of hedonism relative to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Intuitive Hedonism.Joseph Endola - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 128 (2):441-477.
    The hoary philosophical tradition of hedonism – the view that pleasure is the basic ethical or normative value – suggests that it is at least reasonably and roughly intuitive. But philosophers no longer treat hedonism that way. For the most part, they think that they know it to be obviously false on intuitive grounds, much more obviously false on such grounds than familiar competitors. I argue that this consensus is wrong. I defend the intuitive cogency of hedonism relative to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Indirect learning and the aims-curricula fallacy.Jonathan E. Adler - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 27 (2):223–232.
    ABSTRACT I have two main theses. The first is that the inference from accepting an educational aim, especially an ideal aim such as self-realization or critical thinking, to a conclusion as to the content or structure of a curriculum is fallacious. The first thesis should not be controversial. But even if so, the aims-curricula fallacy is readily committed, and that calls for explanation. My second thesis is that the aims–curricula fallacy is often committed because the possibilities for realizing educational aims (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Virtue and contingent history: Possibilities for feminist epistemology.Laura Ruetsche - 2004 - Hypatia 19 (1):73-101.
    : Some feminist epistemologists make the radical claim that there are varieties of epistemically valid warrant that agents access only through having lived particular types of contingent history, varieties of epistemic warrant to which, moreover, the confirmation-theoretic accounts of warrant favored by some traditional epistemologists are inapplicable. I offer Aristotelian virtue as a model for warrant of this sort, and use loosely Aristotelian vocabulary to express, and begin to evaluate, a range of feminist epistemological positions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Virtue and Contingent History: Possibilities for Feminist Epistemology.Laura Ruetsche - 2004 - Hypatia 19 (1):73-101.
    Some feminist epistemologists make the radical claim that there are varieties of epistemically valid warrant that agents access only through having lived particular types of contingent history, varieties of epistemic warrant to which, moreover, the confirmation-theoretic accounts of warrant favored by some traditional epistemologists are inapplicable. I offer Aristotelian virtue as a model for warrant of this sort, and use loosely Aristotelian vocabulary to express, and begin to evaluate, a range of feminist epistemological positions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Terrorists, hostages, victims, and "the crisis team": A "who's who" puzzle.Nancy Potter - 1999 - Hypatia 14 (3):126-156.
    : This essay examines the relationship between nonviolence and trustworthiness. I focus on questions of accountability for people in midlevel positions of power, where multiple loyalties and responsibilities create conflicts and where policies can push people into actions that reinstate hegemonic relations. A case study from crisis counseling is presented in which the (mis)management of the case exacerbated previous violence done to a biracial female. The importance of resistance to dominant ideology is scrutinized.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Terrorists, Hostages, Victims, and “The Crisis Team”: A “Who's Who” Puzzle.Nancy Potter - 1999 - Hypatia 14 (3):126-156.
    This essay examines the relationship between nonviolence and trustworthiness. I focus on questions of accountability for people in midlevel positions of power, where multiple loyalties and responsibilities create conflicts and where policies can push people into actions that reinstate hegemonic relations. A case study from crisis counseling is presented in which the management of the case exacerbated previous violence done to a biracial female. The importance of resistance to dominant ideology is scrutinized.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Recognizing the passion in deliberation: Toward a more democratic theory of deliberative democracy.Cheryl Hall - 2007 - Hypatia 22 (4):81-95.
    : Critics have suggested that deliberative democracy reproduces inequalities of gender, race, and class by privileging calm rational discussion over passionate speech and action. Their solution is to supplement deliberation with such forms of emotional expression. Hall argues that deliberation already inherently involves passion, a point that is especially important to recognize in order to deconstruct the dichotomy between reason and passion that plays a central role in reinforcing inequalities of gender, race, and class in the first place.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Recognizing the Passion in Deliberation: Toward a More Democratic Theory of Deliberative Democracy.Cheryl Hall - 2007 - Hypatia 22 (4):81-95.
    Critics have suggested that deliberative democracy reproduces inequalities of gender, race, and class by privileging calm rational discussion over passionate speech and action. Their solution is to supplement deliberation with such forms of emotional expression. Hall argues that deliberation already inherently involves passion, a point that is especially important to recognize in order to deconstruct the dichotomy between reason and passion that plays a central role in reinforcing inequalities of gender, race, and class in the first place.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Recognizing the Passion in Deliberation: Toward a More Democratic Theory of Deliberative Democracy.Cheryl Hall - 2007 - Hypatia 22 (4):81-95.
    Critics have suggested that deliberative democracy reproduces inequalities of gender, race, and class by privileging calm rational discussion over passionate speech and action. Their solution is to supplement deliberation with such forms of emotional expression. Hall argues that deliberation already inherently involves passion, a point that is especially important to recognize in order to deconstruct the dichotomy between reason and passion that plays a central role in reinforcing inequalities of gender, race, and class in the first place.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Care ethics and virtue ethics.Raja Halwani - 2003 - Hypatia 18 (3):161-192.
    : The paper argues that care ethics should be subsumed under virtue ethics by construing care as an important virtue. Doing so allows us to achieve two desirable goals. First, we preserve what is important about care ethics (for example, its insistence on particularity, partiality, emotional engagement, and the importance of care to our moral lives). Second, we avoid two important objections to care ethics, namely, that it neglects justice, and that it contains no mechanism by which care can be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Care Ethics and Virtue Ethics.Raja Halwani - 2003 - Hypatia 18 (3):161-192.
    The paper argues that care ethics should be subsumed under virtue ethics by construing care as an important virtue. Doing so allows us to achieve two desirable goals. First, we preserve what is important about care ethics. Second, we avoid two important objections to care ethics, namely, that it neglects justice, and that it contains no mechanism by which care can be regulated so as not to be become morally corrupt.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Consequentialism and feminist ethics.Julia Driver - 2000 - Hypatia 20 (4):183-199.
    : This essay attempts to show that sophisticated consequentialism is able to accommodate the concerns that have traditionally been raised by feminist writers in ethics. Those concerns have primarily to do with the fact that consequentialism is seen as both too demanding of the individual and neglectful of the agent's special obligations to family and friends. Here, I argue that instrumental justification for partiality can be provided, for example, even though an attitude of partiality is not characterized itself in instrumental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The political structure of emotion: From dismissal to dialogue.Sylvia Burrow - 2000 - Hypatia 20 (4):27-43.
    : How much power does emotional dismissal have over the oppressed's ability to trust outlaw emotions, or to stand for such emotions before others? I discuss Sue Campbell 's view of the interpretation of emotion in light of the political significance of emotional dismissal. In response, I suggest that feminist conventions of interpretation developed within dialogical communities are best suited to providing resources for expressing, interpreting, defining, and reflecting on our emotions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Alief in Action (and Reaction).Tamar Szabó Gendler - 2008 - Mind and Language 23 (5):552--585.
    I introduce and argue for the importance of a cognitive state that I call alief. An alief is, to a reasonable approximation, an innate or habitual propensity to respond to an apparent stimulus in a particular way. Recognizing the role that alief plays in our cognitive repertoire provides a framework for understanding reactions that are governed by nonconscious or automatic mechanisms, which in turn brings into proper relief the role played by reactions that are subject to conscious regulation and deliberate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   157 citations  
  • Cracking the mirror: on Kierkegaard’s concerns about friendship.John Lippitt - 2007 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 61 (3):131-150.
    In this article, I offer a brief account of some of Kierkegaard's key concerns about friendship: its "preferential" nature and its being a form of self-love. Kierkegaard's endorsement of the ancient idea of the friend as "second self" involves a common but misguided assumption: that friendship depends largely upon likeness between friends. This focus obscures a vitally important element, highlighted by the so-called "drawing" view of friendship. Once this is emphasized, we can see a significant aspect - though by no (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • An ethical evaluation of product placement: a deceptive practice?Chris Hackley, Rungpaka Amy Tiwsakul & Lutz Preuss - 2008 - Business Ethics: A European Review 17 (2):109-120.
    Product placement, the practice of placing brands into non‐advertising media, is a growing marketing phenomenon, which has received relatively little attention from business ethicists. Such attention is timely because the UK regulatory framework for television product placement is under review at the time of writing. In this paper, we seek to locate product placement in relation to traditional frameworks of marketing ethics. We suggest that this location is problematic because product placement is a form of marketing communication in which the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Corporate Temperance a Business Virtue.Richard C. Warren - 2006 - Business Ethics, the Environment and Responsibility 3 (4):223-232.
    “There are strong temptations for those at the top of an organisational hierarchy to appropriate to themselves a disproportionate share of the resources of the organisation and to exercise too much power over the activities of other organisational members.” Hence the case for taking a cool look at executive remuneration and other possible breaches of applying the classical virtue of temperance to corporate behaviour. The author is Principal Lecturer in the Business Studies Department, Manchester Metropolitan University, Aytoun Building, Aytoun Street, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ethical codes, independence and the conservation of ambiguity.Michael Page & Laura F. Spira - 2005 - Business Ethics: A European Review 14 (3):301-316.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Kant’s View on the Parent-Child Relationship and Its Problems—Analyses from a Temporal Perspective as to the Creation and Rearing of a Being Endowed with Freedom.Xianglong Zhang - 2011 - Frontiers of Philosophy in China 6 (1):145-160.
    This article will probe into Kant’s viewpoints about parent-child relationship so as to demonstrate that they are inspiring on the one hand—for example on dealing with the relationship as that pertinent to the thing in itself, but on the other hand, there are many flaws. His strategy on avoiding the difficulty of creating by man a being endowed with freedom depends merely on an one-sided comprehension of time, because according to Kant himself, there is a difference as to the time (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is “ethicist” anything to call a philosopher?Richard M. Zaner - 1984 - Human Studies 7 (3-4):71 - 90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Virtues of a Good Fight: Assessing the Ethics of Fighting in the National Hockey League.Abe Zakhem - 2015 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 9 (1):32-46.
    Violence in sports is under intense public scrutiny. One hotly disputed issue concerns the acceptability of violent retaliation in sports, particular in the form of fighting in the National Hockey League. The question posed here is: Can fighting in the NHL be virtuous? Some think not, maintaining that fighting is undisciplined and ostensibly at odds with the virtues of good temper and justice. Contrary to this conclusion, this paper presents arguments that support the view that fighting in the NHL can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Economics and Interdisciplinary Exchange in Catholic Social Teaching and “Caritas in Veritate”.Andrew Yuengert - 2011 - Journal of Business Ethics 100 (S1):41-54.
    The social sciences, and particularly economics, play an important role in business. This article reviews the account of the interdisciplinary conversation between Catholic Social Teaching and the social sciences (especially economics) over the last century, and describes Benedict XVI’s development of this account in Caritas in Veritate . Over time the popes recognized that the technical approach of economics was a barrier to fruitful collaboration between economics and Catholic Social Teaching, both because the economic approach is reductionist, and because modern (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Republican Responsibility in Criminal Law.Ekow N. Yankah - 2015 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 9 (3):457-475.
    Retributivism so dominates criminal theory that lawyers, legal scholars and law students assert with complete confidence that criminal law is justified only in light of violations of another person’s rights. Yet the core tenet of retributivism views criminal law fundamentally through the lens of individual actors, rendering both offender and victim unrecognizably denuded from their social and civic context. Doing so means that retributivism is unable to explain even our most basic criminal law practices, such as why we punish recidivists (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Legal Vices and Civic Virtue: Vice Crimes, Republicanism and the Corruption of Lawfulness. [REVIEW]Ekow N. Yankah - 2013 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 7 (1):61-82.
    Vice crimes, crimes prohibited in part because they are viewed as morally corrupting, engage legal theorists because they reveal importantly contrasting views between liberals and virtue-centered theorists on the very limits of legitimate state action. Yet advocates and opponents alike focus on the role law can play in suppressing personal vice; the role of law is seen as suppressing licentiousness, sloth, greed etc. The most powerful advocates of the position that the law must nurture good character often draw on Aristotelian (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • How to Make Sense of the Claim “True Knowledge is What Constitutes Action”: A New Interpretation of Wang Yangming’s Doctrine of Unity of Knowledge and Action.Xiaomei Yang - 2009 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 8 (2):173-188.
    No one denies the importance of applying knowledge to actions. But claiming identity (unity) of knowledge and action is quite another thing. There seem to be two problems with the claim: (1) the identity claim implies that the sole cause for one to fail to act on what one judges to be right is ignorance, but it is obviously false that the sole cause of failure in moral actions is ignorance. (2) The identity statement implies non-separation of knowledge and action. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Case for Investment Advising as a Virtue-Based Practice.Keith D. Wyma - 2015 - Journal of Business Ethics 127 (1):231-249.
    Contemporary virtue ethics was revolutionized by Alasdair MacIntyre’s reconfiguration using practices as the starting point for understanding virtues. However, MacIntyre has very pointedly excluded the professions of the financial world from the reformulation. He does not count these professions as practices, and further charges that virtue would actually hinder or even rule out one’s pursuit of these professions. This paper addresses three tasks, in regard to the financial profession of investment advising. First, the paper lays out MacIntyre’s soon-to-be-published charges against (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Technicity of the body as part of the socio-technical system: The contributions of Mauss and Bourdieu.Ernst Wolff - 2010 - Theoria 76 (2):167-187.
    The aim of this article is to contribute to a philosophy of technics by proposing an answer to the following question: what is the nature of the human body as an element of technical systems? The argument focuses on an examination of the phenomenon of bodily technics. This examination is guided by the conviction that Pierre Bourdieu's social theory can be read as contributing significantly to an answer to the above question. However, since Bourdieu's project is not directly aimed at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation