Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Scientific Theories, Models and the Semantic Approach.Krause Décio & Bueno Otávio - 2007 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 11 (2):187-201.
    According to the semantic view, a theory is characterized by a class of models. In this paper, we examine critically some of the assumptions that underlie this approach. First, we recall that models are models of something. Thus we cannot leave completely aside the axiomatization of the theories under consideration, nor can we ignore the metamathematics used to elaborate these models, for changes in the metamathematics often impose restrictions on the resulting models. Second, based on a parallel between van Fraassen’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Scientific Theories.Hans Halvorson - 2016 - In Paul Humphreys (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Science. Oxford University Press USA. pp. 585-608.
    Since the beginning of the 20th century, philosophers of science have asked, "what kind of thing is a scientific theory?" The logical positivists answered: a scientific theory is a mathematical theory, plus an empirical interpretation of that theory. Moreover, they assumed that a mathematical theory is specified by a set of axioms in a formal language. Later 20th century philosophers questioned this account, arguing instead that a scientific theory need not include a mathematical component; or that the mathematical component need (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • The Model-Theoretic Approach in the Philosophy of Science.Newton C. A. Da Costa & Steven French - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (2):248 - 265.
    An introduction to the model-theoretic approach in the philosophy of science is given and it is argued that this program is further enhanced by the introduction of partial structures. It is then shown that this leads to a natural and intuitive account of both "iconic" and mathematical models and of the role of the former in science itself.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • On Suppes' Set Theoretical Predicates.Newton C. A. da Costa & Rolando Chuaqui - 1988 - Erkenntnis 29 (1):95-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Physics, inconsistency, and quasi-truth.Newton C. A. Da Costa & Décio Krause - 2014 - Synthese 191 (13):3041-3055.
    In this work, the first of a series, we study the nature of informal inconsistency in physics, focusing mainly on the foundations of quantum theory, and appealing to the concept of quasi-truth. We defend a pluralistic view of the philosophy of science, grounded on the existence of inconsistencies and on quasi-truth. Here, we treat only the ‘classical aspects’ of the subject, leaving for a forthcoming paper the ‘non-classical’ part.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Suppes' set theoretical predicates.Newton C. A. Costa & Rolando Chuaqui - 1988 - Erkenntnis 29 (1):95-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Functoriality of the Schmidt construction.Juan Climent Vidal & Enric Cosme Llópez - 2023 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 31 (5):822-893.
    After proving, in a purely categorial way, that the inclusion functor |$\textrm {In}_{\textbf {Alg}(\varSigma )}$| from |$\textbf {Alg}(\varSigma )$|⁠, the category of many-sorted |$\varSigma $|-algebras, to |$\textbf {PAlg}(\varSigma )$|⁠, the category of many-sorted partial |$\varSigma $|-algebras, has a left adjoint |$\textbf {F}_{\varSigma }$|⁠, the (absolutely) free completion functor, we recall, in connection with the functor |$\textbf {F}_{\varSigma }$|⁠, the generalized recursion theorem of Schmidt, which we will also call the Schmidt construction. Next, we define a category |$\textbf {Cmpl}(\varSigma )$|⁠, of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nothing matters too much, or Wright is wrong.R. Black - 2000 - Analysis 60 (3):229-237.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Withering Immortality of Nicolas Bourbaki: A Cultural Connector at the Confluence of Mathematics, Structuralism, and the Oulipo in France.David Aubin - 1997 - Science in Context 10 (2):297-342.
    The group of mathematicians known as Bourbaki persuasively proclaimed the isolation of its field of research – pure mathematics – from society and science. It may therefore seem paradoxical that links with larger French cultural movements, especially structuralism and potential literature, are easy to establish. Rather than arguing that the latter were a consequence of the former, which they were not, I show that all of these cultural movements, including the Bourbakist endeavor, emerged together, each strengthening the public appeal of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On Bourbaki’s axiomatic system for set theory.Maribel Anacona, Luis Carlos Arboleda & F. Javier Pérez-Fernández - 2014 - Synthese 191 (17):4069-4098.
    In this paper we study the axiomatic system proposed by Bourbaki for the Theory of Sets in the Éléments de Mathématique. We begin by examining the role played by the sign \(\uptau \) in the framework of its formal logical theory and then we show that the system of axioms for set theory is equivalent to Zermelo–Fraenkel system with the axiom of choice but without the axiom of foundation. Moreover, we study Grothendieck’s proposal of adding to Bourbaki’s system the axiom (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Remarkable Number “1”.G. Donald Allen - 2014 - Science & Education 23 (9):1845-1852.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pasch's empiricism as methodological structuralism.Dirk Schlimm - 2020 - In Erich H. Reck & Georg Schiemer (eds.), The Pre-History of Mathematical Structuralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 80-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The proper treatment of variables in predicate logic.Kai F. Wehmeier - 2018 - Linguistics and Philosophy 41 (2):209-249.
    In §93 of The Principles of Mathematics, Bertrand Russell observes that “the variable is a very complicated logical entity, by no means easy to analyze correctly”. This assessment is borne out by the fact that even now we have no fully satisfactory understanding of the role of variables in a compositional semantics for first-order logic. In standard Tarskian semantics, variables are treated as meaning-bearing entities; moreover, they serve as the basic building blocks of all meanings, which are constructed out of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On the existence of undistorted progressive waves (UPWs) of arbitrary speeds 0≤ϑ<∞ in nature.Waldyr A. Rodrigues & Jian-Yu Lu - 1997 - Foundations of Physics 27 (3):435-508.
    We present the theory, the experimental evidence and fundamental physical consequences concerning the existence of families of undistorted progressive waves (UPWs) of arbitrary speeds 0≤ϑ<∞, which are solutions of the homogeneuous wave equation, the Maxwell equations, and Dirac, Weyl, and Klein-Gordon equations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The last mathematician from Hilbert's göttingen: Saunders Mac Lane as philosopher of mathematics.Colin McLarty - 2007 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (1):77-112.
    While Saunders Mac Lane studied for his D.Phil in Göttingen, he heard David Hilbert's weekly lectures on philosophy, talked philosophy with Hermann Weyl, and studied it with Moritz Geiger. Their philosophies and Emmy Noether's algebra all influenced his conception of category theory, which has become the working structure theory of mathematics. His practice has constantly affirmed that a proper large-scale organization for mathematics is the most efficient path to valuable specific results—while he sees that the question of which results are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Saunders Mac Lane (1909–2005): His mathematical life and philosophical works.Colin McLarty - 2005 - Philosophia Mathematica 13 (3):237-251.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Sentences of Type Theory: The Only Sentences Preserved Under Isomorphisms.M. Victoria Marshall & Rolando Chuaqui - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (3):932-948.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Interactions Between Mathematics and Physics: The History of the Concept of Function—Teaching with and About Nature of Mathematics.Tinne Hoff Kjeldsen & Jesper Lützen - 2015 - Science & Education 24 (5-6):543-559.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Which Mathematical Logic is the Logic of Mathematics?Jaakko Hintikka - 2012 - Logica Universalis 6 (3-4):459-475.
    The main tool of the arithmetization and logization of analysis in the history of nineteenth century mathematics was an informal logic of quantifiers in the guise of the “epsilon–delta” technique. Mathematicians slowly worked out the problems encountered in using it, but logicians from Frege on did not understand it let alone formalize it, and instead used an unnecessarily poor logic of quantifiers, viz. the traditional, first-order logic. This logic does not e.g. allow the definition and study of mathematicians’ uniformity concepts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mathematical Inference and Logical Inference.Yacin Hamami - 2018 - Review of Symbolic Logic 11 (4):665-704.
    The deviation of mathematical proof—proof in mathematical practice—from the ideal of formal proof—proof in formal logic—has led many philosophers of mathematics to reconsider the commonly accepted view according to which the notion of formal proof provides an accurate descriptive account of mathematical proof. This, in turn, has motivated a search for alternative accounts of mathematical proof purporting to be more faithful to the reality of mathematical practice. Yet, in order to develop and evaluate such alternative accounts, it appears as a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Foundations of nominal techniques: logic and semantics of variables in abstract syntax.Murdoch J. Gabbay - 2011 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 (2):161-229.
    We are used to the idea that computers operate on numbers, yet another kind of data is equally important: the syntax of formal languages, with variables, binding, and alpha-equivalence. The original application of nominal techniques, and the one with greatest prominence in this paper, is to reasoning on formal syntax with variables and binding. Variables can be modelled in many ways: for instance as numbers (since we usually take countably many of them); as links (since they may `point' to a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Type theory.Thierry Coquand - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Logic is not Logic.Jean-Ives Béziau - 2010 - Abstracta 6 (1):73-102.
    In this paper we discuss the difference between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Scientific Theories, Models and the Semantic Approach.Otávio Bueno & Décio Krause - 2007 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 11 (2):187-201.
    According to the semantic view, a theory is characterized by a class of models. In this paper, we examine critically some of the assumptions that underlie this approach. First, we recall that models are models of something. Thus we cannot leave completely aside the axiomatization of the theories under consideration, nor can we ignore the metamathematics used to elaborate these models, for changes in the metamathematics often impose restrictions on the resulting models. Second, based on a parallel between van Fraassen’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Thoralf Skolem and the epsilon substitution method for predicate logic.Grigori Mints - 1996 - Nordic Journal of Philosophical Logic 1 (2):133-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations