Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Order Ethics: Bridging the Gap Between Contractarianism and Business Ethics.Christoph Luetge, Thomas Armbrüster & Julian Müller - 2016 - Journal of Business Ethics 136 (4):687-697.
    Contract-based approaches have been a focus of attention in business ethics. As one of the grand traditions in political philosophy, contractarianism is founded on the notion that we will never resolve deep moral disagreement. Classical philosophers like Hobbes and Locke, or recent ones like Rawls and Gaus, seek to solve ethical conflicts on the level of social rules and procedures. Recent authors in business ethics have sought to utilize contract-based approaches for their field and to apply it to concrete business (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Hegel and Capitalism.Andrew Buchwalter (ed.) - 2015 - Albany: State University of New York Press.
    Examines Hegel’s unique understanding and assessment of capitalism as an economic, social, and cultural phenomenon.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Stakeholder’s Preference and Rational Compliance: A Comment on Sacconi’s “CSR as a Model for Extended Corporate Governance II: Compliance, Reputation and Reciprocity”.Pedro Francés-Gómez & Ariel del Rio - 2008 - Journal of Business Ethics 82 (1):59-76.
    Lorenzo Sacconi's recent re-statement of his social contract account of business ethics is a major contribution to our understanding of the normative nature of CSR as the expression of a fair multi-party agreement supported by the economic rationality of each participant. However, at one crucial point in his theory, Sacconi introduces the concept of stakeholders' conformist preferences - their disposition to punish the firm if it defects from the agreement, refusing to abide by its own explicit CSR policies and norms. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Who is Rational Economic Man?Jennifer Roback Morse - 1997 - Social Philosophy and Policy 14 (1):179.
    There is, in Sarajevo, a man who comes out into the streets each day and plays his cello on the sidewalk. He does this at the same time each day, no matter how much shooting or shelling is going on, no matter how great the danger to himself. He describes himself as having decided to take a stand for beauty in the face of horror. Can the rational choice paradigm, as currently practiced in the various disciplines of economics, philosophy, political (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Property.Jeremy Waldron - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Ordo-Responsibility in the Sharing Economy: A Social Contracts Perspective.Stefan Hielscher, Sebastian Everding & Ingo Pies - 2022 - Business Ethics Quarterly 32 (3):404-437.
    Can private companies legitimately regulate sharing markets, and if yes, how? Whereas scholars have either criticized sharing platforms for expanding into private and public arenas or welcomed them to counterbalance encroaching government regulations, studies document their unbridled popularity. On the basis of a special version of social contracts theory pioneered by James Buchanan, we develop a heuristics that helps guide reasoning about the legitimacy of the sharing economy’s regulatory function. First, we discuss the conditions under which free and responsible individuals (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Contracting for Catastrophe:Legitimizing Emergency Constitutions by Drawing on Social Contract Theory.Stefan Voigt - 2021 - Res Publica 28 (1):149-172.
    States of emergency are declared frequently in all parts of the world. Their declaration routinely implies a suspension of basic constitutional rights. In the last half century, it has become the norm for constitutions to contain an explicit ‘emergency constitution’, i.e., the constitutionally safeguarded rules of operation for a state of emergency. In this paper, I ask whether inclusion of an emergency constitution can be legitimized by drawing on social contract theory. I argue that there are important arguments, both against (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Morals From Rationality Alone? Some Doubts.J. P. Messina & David Wiens - 2020 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 19 (3):248-273.
    Contractarians aim to derive moral principles from the dictates of instrumental rationality alone. But it is well-known that contractarian moral theories struggle to identify normative principles that are both uniquely rational and morally compelling. Michael Moehler's recent book, *Minimal Morality* seeks to avoid these difficulties by developing a novel "two-level" social contract theory, which restricts the scope of contractarian morality to cases of deep and persistent moral disagreement. Yet Moehler remains ambitious, arguing that a restricted version of Kant's categorical imperative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Adam Smith Problem Revisited: A Methodological Resolution.Sigmund Wagner-Tsukamoto - 2013 - Journal des Economistes Et des Etudes Humaines 19 (1):63-99.
    The Adam Smith problem refers to a claimed inconsistency between the Theory of Moral Sentiments and the Wealth of Nations, regarding the portrayal of human nature in these two books. Previous research predominantly resolved the claimed inconsistency by uncovering virtuous, less selfish character traits in the Wealth of Nations. This article voices caution. I acknowledge – on methodological grounds – fundamental differences regarding the portrayal of human nature in Smith’s behavioral ethics, i.e. the Theory of Moral Sentiments, as compared with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Legality of Self‐Constitution.Christoph Hanisch - 2015 - Ratio Juris 28 (4):452-469.
    An influential strand in recent action-theory employs constitutivist arguments in order to present accounts of individual agency and practical identity. I argue for an extension of this framework into the interpersonal realm, and suggest using it to reassess issues in jurisprudence. A legal system is an instantiation of the solution to the inescapable tasks of self-constituting action and identity-formation in the presence of other agents. Law's validity and normativity can be enlightened when the constitutivist approach considers the external prerequisites of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Property and capital in the person: Lockean and neoliberal self‐ownership.Niklas Angebauer - 2020 - Constellations 27 (1):50-62.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Rational Reconstruction of United Nations Human Rights Law.Gustavo Arosemena - 2017 - Ratio Juris 30 (3):372-386.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the logic of productive cooperation: a response to critics.Albert Weale - 2017 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 20 (2):251-267.
    This paper identifies and responds to four critiques of democratic contractarianism, as advocated in Democratic Justice and the Social Contract, to be found in this symposium. The first is that, as a contingent practice-dependent account of justice, democratic contractarianism lacks the capacity to explain civic cooperation. The second is that, despite its intentions, Democratic Justice does not lay out an authentic contractarian theory. The third is that the theory is incompatible with our considered judgements about justice. And the fourth is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tax Uniformity as a Requirement of Justice.Charles Delmotte - 2020 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 33 (1):59-83.
    Barbara Fried takes the view that uniform taxation—that is, a single rate applicable to all income levels—cannot be defended on any grounds of justice. She goes further by saying that, of all possible rate structures, it might be “the hardest one”? to ground in “a”? theory of fairness. Using the contractarian-constitutional perspective advanced by John Rawls and James Buchanan, this article argues that tax uniformity can be seen as a requirement of justice. After modelling how the political world realistically decides (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • HIV prevention clinical trials’ community engagement guidelines: inequality, and ethical conflicts.Morenike O. Folayan & Kristin Peterson - 2020 - Tandf: Global Bioethics 31 (1):47-66.
    Volume 31, Issue 1, December 2020, Page 47-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bernard Mandeville and the doctrine of laissez-faire.Renee Prendergast - 2016 - Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 9 (1):101.
    The view of Mandeville as a pioneer of laissez-faire is difficult to reconcile with his repeated insistence that private vices were turned into public benefits by the 'dexterous management of the skilful politician'. Even if references to the skilful politician are regarded as shorthand for a legal and institutional framework, there remains the question of whether such a framework is a spontaneous order or the product of purposeful experiment as Mandeville thought? Mandeville warned about the harmful effects of meddling but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The democratic boundary problem and social contract theory.Marco Verschoor - 2018 - European Journal of Political Theory 17 (1):3-22.
    How to demarcate the political units within which democracy will be practiced? Although recent years have witnessed a steadily increasing academic interest in this question concerning the boundary problem in democratic theory, social contract theory’s potential for solving it has largely been ignored. In fact, contract views are premised on the assumption of a given people and so presuppose what requires legitimization: the existence of a demarcated group of individuals materializing, as it were, from nowhere and whose members agree among (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Contra Anarcho-capitalism.Jordan Schneider - 2007 - Journal of Libertarian Studies 21 (1):101-110.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The international provision of pharmaceuticals: a comparison of two alternative argumentative strategies for global ethics.Ingo Pies & Stefan Hielscher - 2011 - Journal of Global Ethics 7 (1):73 - 89.
    Millions of people in the developing world lack access to curative drugs. Pogge identifies the cause of this problem as a lack of redistribution across borders. In contrast, this article shows that institutional shortcomings within developing countries are the main issue. These different explanations are the result of diverging analytic approaches to ethics: a cosmopolitan approach versus an ordonomic approach. This article compares both approaches with regard to how they conceptualize and propose to solve the problem of providing life-saving pharmaceuticals (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Capitalism and the Democratic Economy.Gary A. Dymski & John E. Elliott - 1988 - Social Philosophy and Policy 6 (1):140.
    Mainstream economics evaluates capitalism primarily from the perspective of efficiency. Social philosophy typically applies other or additional normative criteria, such as equality, democracy, and community. This essay examines the implications of these contrasting sets of criteria in the evaluation of capitalism. Its first two sections consider the criteria themselves, assuming that a trade-off exists between them. The last three sections question whether such a trade-off necessarily occurs, and explore the claim that improvements in nonefficiency dimensions of capitalist society may enhance, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Neoliberals’ economic liberalism: A checkered history.Roberto Romani - 2022 - Constellations 29 (3):359-374.
    Constellations, Volume 29, Issue 3, Page 359-374, September 2022.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Constructivism, representation, and stability: path-dependence in public reason theories of justice.John Thrasher - 2019 - Synthese 196 (1):429-450.
    Public reason theories are characterized by three conditions: constructivism, representation, and stability. Constructivism holds that justification does not rely on any antecedent moral or political values outside of the procedure of agreement. Representation holds that the reasons for the choice in the model must be rationally explicable to real agents outside the model. Stability holds that the principles chosen in the procedure should be stable upon reflection, especially in the face of diversity in a pluralistic society. Choice procedures that involve (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Economic Freedom and Government: A Conceptual Framework.Pal Czegledi & Judit Kapas - 2010 - Journal des Economistes Et des Etudes Humaines 16 (1).
    The aim of this paper is to contribute to the development of a theory of economic freedom. In this endeavor, we build our framework on the Hayekian notion of freedom because it explicitly embodies the obvious link between freedom and the state: freedom is an absence of state coercion except for that which enforces abstract, general rules known beforehand. We derive two propositions from this Hayekian thesis and elaborate on them, leading to a categorization of government actions from the viewpoint (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Marxian Freedom, Individual Liberty, and the End of Alienation.John Gray - 1986 - Social Philosophy and Policy 3 (2):160.
    It is a commonplace of academic conventional wisdom that Marxian theory is not to be judged by the historical experience of actually existing socialist societies. The reasons given in support of this view are familiar enough, but let us rehearse them. Born in adversity, encircled by hostile powers, burdened with the necessity of defending themselves against foreign enemies and with the massive task of educating backward and reactionary populations, the revolutionary socialist governments of this century were each of them denied (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Strategic Justice, Conventionalism, and Bargaining Theory.Michael Moehler - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3-4):8317-8334.
    Conventionalism as a distinct approach to the social contract received significant attention in the game-theoretic literature on social contract theory. Peter Vanderschraaf’s sophisticated and innovative theory of conventional justice represents the most recent contribution to this tradition and, in many ways, can be viewed as a culmination of this tradition. In this article, I focus primarily on Vanderschraaf’s defense of the egalitarian bargaining solution as a principle of justice. I argue that one particular formal feature of this bargaining solution, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Who Gets to Decide? The Role of Institutional Logics in Shaping Stakeholder Politics and Insurgency.Harry T. Hall James E. Mattingly - 2008 - Business and Society Review 113 (1):63-89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Self-interest and public interest: The motivations of political actors.Michael C. Munger - 2011 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 23 (3):339-357.
    ABSTRACT Self-Interest and Public Interest in Western Politics showed that the public, politicians, and bureaucrats are often public spirited. But this does not invalidate public-choice theory. Public-choice theory is an ideal type, not a claim that self-interest explains all political behavior. Instead, public-choice theory is useful in creating rules and institutions that guard against the worst case, which would be universal self-interestedness in politics. In contrast, the public-interest hypothesis is neither a comprehensive explanation of political behavior nor a sound basis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Welfare Theory, Public Action, and Ethical Values: Revisiting the History of Welfare Economics, Roger E. Backhouse, Antoinette Baujard and Tamotsu Nishizawa (Eds). Cambridge University Press, 2021, ix + 338 pages. [REVIEW]Cyril Hédoin - 2022 - Economics and Philosophy 38 (2):326-332.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Prisoner’s Dilemma: An Adequate Concept for Ethical Analysis in Healthcare? A Systematic Search and Critical Review.Wolf Rogowski & Oliver Lange - 2020 - Journal of Business Ethics 177 (1):63-77.
    Schools of economic ethics inspired by Buchanan propose viewing ethical conflicts as prisoners’ dilemmas to facilitate solutions based on Pareto-improving institutional changes. Given that healthcare is determined by complex institutional arrangements, it has been claimed that this approach is also suitable for business ethics in healthcare. To scrutinize this claim, this research systematically searched for studies reporting PD structures in healthcare. PubMed, EconLit, and EconBiz were searched to find articles in German and English. Study type, characteristics of the game, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Nozickian Case for Compulsory Employment Injury Insurance: The Example of Sweatshops.Damian Bäumlisberger - 2020 - Journal of Business Ethics 173 (1):13-27.
    Production in sweatshops entails an elevated risk of occupational injury and sickness due to accidents and exposure to dangerous working conditions. As most sweatshop locations lack basic social security systems, health problems have severe consequences for affected workers. Against this background, this article considers what obligations employers of sweatshop labor have to their workers, and how they should meet them. Based on core libertarian concepts, it shows that they are morally responsible for health problems caused by their management decisions, that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Public goods in Michael Oakeshott’s ‘world of pragmata’.Maurits de Jongh - 2019 - European Journal of Political Theory 21 (3):147488511989045.
    Michael Oakeshott’s account of political economy is claimed to have found its ‘apotheosis under Thatcherism’. Against critics who align him with a preference for small government, this article poin...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Who Gets to Decide? The Role of Institutional Logics in Shaping Stakeholder Politics and Insurgency.James E. Mattingly & Harry T. Hall - 2008 - Business and Society Review 113 (1):63-89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Feasibility Claims in the Debate over Anarchy versus the Minimal State.Brad Taylor - 2018 - Libertarian Papers 10.
    : Accusations of infeasibility or utopianism are common in debates over libertarian institutions, but exactly what we mean when we say an idea is “utopian” or “infeasible” is often left unspecified. After reviewing recent philosophical work attempting to clarify the concept of “feasibility,” I consider how the concept has been deployed in the debate among libertarians […].
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Globalización E imperio de la Ley. Algunas dudas westfalianas.Francisco J. Laporta - 2005 - Anales de la Cátedra Francisco Suárez 39:243-287.
    In his posthumous work Power and Prosperity , the economist Mancur Olson asked why the economies of many of those countries of the former Soviet Union and other emergent countries that had at last adapted to the theoretical and practical presuppositions of the market economy had not seen themselves, notwithstanding, recompensed with the prosperity that this economic model promises to all those who follow its rules. The core of the answer was in a long paragraph that is perhaps elemental to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ethical theory in German business ethics research.Lutz Preuss - 1999 - Journal of Business Ethics 18 (4):407 - 419.
    This article offers an overview over the wide scope business ethics has reached in German speaking countries; works which in their majority are not yet available in English translation. The proposed concepts range from a focus on the individual manager and a focus on moral education of managers, via the procedural model of discourse ethics to pressure group ethics and business ethics from a Christian point of view. Other authors suggest an economic theory of moral behaviour, or see ethics as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • For Humanistic Management and Against Economics.Sigmund Wagner-Tsukamoto - 2018 - Business and Society Review 123 (3):459-488.
    The paper critiques the relationship between personalist ethics and institutional economics, and accepts that institutional economics can be difficult to reconcile with humanistic management that builds on personalist ethics. Even so the paper connects impersonalist ethics with institutional economics. On this ground, the paper demonstrates how theory and practice of personalist humanist management can lean on impersonalist ethics, i.e., institutional economics. Three pathways are laid out for such leanings. It is argued that to understand these alignments is important to improve (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Independent electoral management bodies and international election observer missions: any impact on the observed level of democracy? A conceptual framework.Anne van Aaken - 2009 - Constitutional Political Economy 20 (3-4):296-322.
    What kind of institutions are needed to stabilize and foster democracy? Clearly elections are crucial and much of the institutional and legal surrounding of elections has been subject to research. Two institutional variables have been neglected though, specifically in empirical research: Electoral Management Bodies and International Observer Missions. Can EMBs and EOMs foster free and fair elections? If yes, under what conditions? And what kind of competences are needed for them? We hypothesize that both can become crucial institutions for free (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evaluation as institution: a contractarian argument for needs-based economic evaluation.Wolf H. Rogowski - 2018 - BMC Medical Ethics 19 (1):59.
    There is a gap between health economic evaluation methods and the value judgments of coverage decision makers, at least in Germany. Measuring preference satisfaction has been claimed to be inappropriate for allocating health care resources, e.g. because it disregards medical need. The existing methods oriented at medical need have been claimed to disregard non-consequentialist fairness concerns. The aim of this article is to propose a new, contractarian argument for justifying needs-based economic evaluation. It is based on consent rather than maximization (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Polycentric democracy: using and defusing disagreements.Julian F. Müller - 2017 - Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 10 (1):150-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Partial Equality.Colin M. MacLeod - 1998 - Dialogue 37 (4):775-798.
    Despite the diversity and important disagreement which characterizes theorizing in political philosophy, most contemporary theories of justice yield remarkably similar verdicts on the moral adequacy of current distributions of wealth, income, and opportunity. By almost any standard of justice defended today, we live in a profoundly unjust world. It is obvious, for instance, that utilitarianism, the difference principle, equality of resources, and even modest-sounding principles of equality of opportunity all condemn the yawning gulf which separates the rich and the poor (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book reviews. [REVIEW]Peter Lipton - 1992 - Mind 101 (401):171-175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Participation versus Consent: Should Corporations Be Run according to Democratic Principles?Stefan Hielscher, Markus Beckmann & Ingo Pies - 2014 - Business Ethics Quarterly 24 (4):533-563.
    ABSTRACT:The notion of “democracy” has become a much-debated concept in scholarship on business ethics, management, and organization studies. The strategy of this paper is to distinguish between a principle of organization that fosters participation (type I democracy) and a principle of legitimation that draws on consent (type II democracy). Based on this distinction, we highlight conceptual shortcomings of the literature on stakeholder democracy. We demonstrate that parts of the literature tend to confound ends with means. Many approaches employ type I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Public Goods, Mutual Benefits, and Majority Rule.Rutger Claassen - 2013 - Journal of Social Philosophy 44 (3):270-290.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Heterogeneous Moral Views in the Stateless Society.Ryan Murphy - 2015 - Libertarian Papers 7.
    A growing literature has explored the workability and efficacy of governance without the state. The difficulties typically raised in the context of these studies concern under which conditions cooperation or Hobbesian chaos would arise in the absence of a monopolist of coercion. This paper challenges the idea of the stateless society from another vantage point, arguing the institutions articulated by proponents of the stateless society would struggle at reconciling heterogeneous views regarding the rights of third parties. This is relevant for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark