Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Towards a Semantic Characterization of Cut-Elimination.Kazushige Terui - 2006 - Studia Logica 82 (1):95-119.
    We introduce necessary and sufficient conditions for a (single-conclusion) sequent calculus to admit (reductive) cut-elimination. Our conditions are formulated both syntactically and semantically.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Logic and Majority Voting.Ryo Takemura - 2021 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 51 (2):347-382.
    To investigate the relationship between logical reasoning and majority voting, we introduce logic with groups Lg in the style of Gentzen’s sequent calculus, where every sequent is indexed by a group of individuals. We also introduce the set-theoretical semantics of Lg, where every formula is interpreted as a certain closed set of groups whose members accept that formula. We present the cut-elimination theorem, and the soundness and semantic completeness theorems of Lg. Then, introducing an inference rule representing majority voting to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The proof complexity of linear algebra.Michael Soltys & Stephen Cook - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 130 (1-3):277-323.
    We introduce three formal theories of increasing strength for linear algebra in order to study the complexity of the concepts needed to prove the basic theorems of the subject. We give what is apparently the first feasible proofs of the Cayley–Hamilton theorem and other properties of the determinant, and study the propositional proof complexity of matrix identities such as AB=I→BA=I.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • First-Degree Entailment and its Relatives.Yaroslav Shramko, Dmitry Zaitsev & Alexander Belikov - 2017 - Studia Logica 105 (6):1291-1317.
    We consider a family of logical systems for representing entailment relations of various kinds. This family has its root in the logic of first-degree entailment formulated as a binary consequence system, i.e. a proof system dealing with the expressions of the form \, where both \ and \ are single formulas. We generalize this approach by constructing consequence systems that allow manipulating with sets of formulas, either to the right or left of the turnstile. In this way, it is possible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Reverse-engineering Reverse Mathematics.Sam Sanders - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (5):528-541.
    An important open problem in Reverse Mathematics is the reduction of the first-order strength of the base theory from IΣ1IΣ1 to IΔ0+expIΔ0+exp. The system ERNA, a version of Nonstandard Analysis based on the system IΔ0+expIΔ0+exp, provides a partial solution to this problem. Indeed, weak Königʼs lemma and many of its equivalent formulations from Reverse Mathematics can be ‘pushed down’ into ERNA, while preserving the equivalences, but at the price of replacing equality with ‘≈’, i.e. infinitesimal proximity . The logical principle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • More infinity for a better finitism.Sam Sanders - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (12):1525-1540.
    Elementary Recursive Nonstandard Analysis, in short ERNA, is a constructive system of nonstandard analysis with a PRA consistency proof, proposed in around 1995 by Patrick Suppes and Richard Sommer. It is based on an earlier system developed by Rolando Chuaqui and Patrick Suppes. Here, we discuss the inherent problems and limitations of the classical nonstandard framework and propose a much-needed refinement of ERNA, called , in the spirit of Karel Hrbacek’s stratified set theory. We study the metamathematics of and its (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Sufficient conditions for cut elimination with complexity analysis.João Rasga - 2007 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 149 (1-3):81-99.
    Sufficient conditions for first-order-based sequent calculi to admit cut elimination by a Schütte–Tait style cut elimination proof are established. The worst case complexity of the cut elimination is analysed. The obtained upper bound is parameterized by a quantity related to the calculus. The conditions are general enough to be satisfied by a wide class of sequent calculi encompassing, among others, some sequent calculi presentations for the first order and the propositional versions of classical and intuitionistic logic, classical and intuitionistic modal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Incompleteness in the Finite Domain.Pavel Pudlák - 2017 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 23 (4):405-441.
    Motivated by the problem of finding finite versions of classical incompleteness theorems, we present some conjectures that go beyond NP ≠ coNP. These conjectures formally connect computational complexity with the difficulty of proving some sentences, which means that high computational complexity of a problem associated with a sentence implies that the sentence is not provable in a weak theory, or requires a long proof. Another reason for putting forward these conjectures is that some results in proof complexity seem to be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Length and structure of proofs.Rohit Parikh - 1998 - Synthese 114 (1):41-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Epsilon Calculus and Herbrand Complexity.Georg Moser & Richard Zach - 2006 - Studia Logica 82 (1):133-155.
    Hilbert's ε-calculus is based on an extension of the language of predicate logic by a term-forming operator εx. Two fundamental results about the ε-calculus, the first and second epsilon theorem, play a rôle similar to that which the cut-elimination theorem plays in sequent calculus. In particular, Herbrand's Theorem is a consequence of the epsilon theorems. The paper investigates the epsilon theorems and the complexity of the elimination procedure underlying their proof, as well as the length of Herbrand disjunctions of existential (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Strict Finitism and the Happy Sorites.Ofra Magidor - 2012 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 41 (2):471-491.
    Call an argument a ‘happy sorites’ if it is a sorites argument with true premises and a false conclusion. It is a striking fact that although most philosophers working on the sorites paradox find it at prima facie highly compelling that the premises of the sorites paradox are true and its conclusion false, few (if any) of the standard theories on the issue ultimately allow for happy sorites arguments. There is one philosophical view, however, that appears to allow for at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • El enfoque epistemológico de David Hilbert: el a priori del conocimiento y el papel de la lógica en la fundamentación de la ciencia.Rodrigo Lopez-Orellana - 2019 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 23 (2):279-308.
    This paper explores the main philosophical approaches of David Hilbert’s theory of proof. Specifically, it is focuses on his ideas regarding logic, the concept of proof, the axiomatic, the concept of truth, metamathematics, the a priori knowledge and the general nature of scientific knowledge. The aim is to show and characterize his epistemological approach on the foundation of knowledge, where logic appears as a guarantee of that foundation. Hilbert supposes that the propositional apriorism, proposed by him to support mathematics, sustains (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bounded linear-time temporal logic: A proof-theoretic investigation.Norihiro Kamide - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (4):439-466.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On theories of bounded arithmetic for NC 1.Emil Jeřábek - 2011 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (4):322-340.
    We develop an arithmetical theory and its variant , corresponding to “slightly nonuniform” . Our theories sit between and , and allow evaluation of log-depth bounded fan-in circuits under limited conditions. Propositional translations of -formulas provable in admit L-uniform polynomial-size Frege proofs.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A Sequent Calculus for a Negative Free Logic.Norbert Gratzl - 2010 - Studia Logica 96 (3):331-348.
    This article presents a sequent calculus for a negative free logic with identity, called N . The main theorem (in part 1) is the admissibility of the Cut-rule. The second part of this essay is devoted to proofs of soundness, compactness and completeness of N relative to a standard semantics for negative free logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Finitistic Arithmetic and Classical Logic.Mihai Ganea - 2014 - Philosophia Mathematica 22 (2):167-197.
    It can be argued that only the equational theories of some sub-elementary function algebras are finitistic or intuitive according to a certain interpretation of Hilbert's conception of intuition. The purpose of this paper is to investigate the relation of those restricted forms of equational reasoning to classical quantifier logic in arithmetic. The conclusion reached is that Edward Nelson's ‘predicative arithmetic’ program, which makes essential use of classical quantifier logic, cannot be justified finitistically and thus requires a different philosophical foundation, possibly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Slow reflection.Anton Freund - 2017 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (12):2103-2128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Short Proofs for Slow Consistency.Anton Freund & Fedor Pakhomov - 2020 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 61 (1):31-49.
    Let Con↾x denote the finite consistency statement “there are no proofs of contradiction in T with ≤x symbols.” For a large class of natural theories T, Pudlák has shown that the lengths of the shortest proofs of Con↾n in the theory T itself are bounded by a polynomial in n. At the same time he conjectures that T does not have polynomial proofs of the finite consistency statements Con)↾n. In contrast, we show that Peano arithmetic has polynomial proofs of Con)↾n, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Monstrous Content and the Bounds of Discourse.Thomas Macaulay Ferguson - 2022 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 52 (1):111-143.
    Bounds consequence provides an interpretation of a multiple-conclusion consequence relation in which the derivability of a sequent is understood as the claim that it is conversationally out-of-bounds to take a position in which each member of Γ is asserted while each member of Δ is denied. Two of the foremost champions of bounds consequence—Greg Restall and David Ripley—have independently indicated that the shape of the bounds in question is determined by conversational practice. In this paper, I suggest that the standard (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Note on the Unprovability of Consistency in Formal Theories of Truth.Kevin Davey - 2021 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 50 (6):1313-1340.
    Why is it that even strong formal theories of truth fail to prove their own consistency? Although Field has addressed this question for many theories of truth, I argue that there is an important and attractive class of theories of truth that he omitted in his analysis. Such theories cannot prove that all their axioms are true, though unlike many of the cases Field considers, they do not prove that any of their axioms are false or that any of their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Finitistic Consistency of Heck’s Predicative Fregean System.Luís Cruz-Filipe & Fernando Ferreira - 2015 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 56 (1):61-79.
    Frege’s theory is inconsistent. However, the predicative version of Frege’s system is consistent. This was proved by Richard Heck in 1996 using a model-theoretic argument. In this paper, we give a finitistic proof of this consistency result. As a consequence, Heck’s predicative theory is rather weak. We also prove the finitistic consistency of the extension of Heck’s theory to $\Delta^{1}_{1}$-comprehension and of Heck’s ramified predicative second-order system.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quantified propositional calculus and a second-order theory for NC1.Stephen Cook & Tsuyoshi Morioka - 2005 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 44 (6):711-749.
    Let H be a proof system for quantified propositional calculus (QPC). We define the Σqj-witnessing problem for H to be: given a prenex Σqj-formula A, an H-proof of A, and a truth assignment to the free variables in A, find a witness for the outermost existential quantifiers in A. We point out that the Σq1-witnessing problems for the systems G*1and G1 are complete for polynomial time and PLS (polynomial local search), respectively. We introduce and study the systems G*0 and G0, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Towards a Semantic Characterization of Cut-Elimination.Agata Ciabattoni & Kazushige Terui - 2006 - Studia Logica 82 (1):95-119.
    We introduce necessary and sufficient conditions for a (single-conclusion) sequent calculus to admit (reductive) cut-elimination. Our conditions are formulated both syntactically and semantically.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Conditional Heresies.Fabrizio Cariani & Simon Goldstein - 2018 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (2):251-282.
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, EarlyView.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Degrees of Relative Provability.Mingzhong Cai - 2012 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 53 (4):479-489.
    There are many classical connections between the proof-theoretic strength of systems of arithmetic and the provable totality of recursive functions. In this paper we study the provability strength of the totality of recursive functions by investigating the degree structure induced by the relative provability order of recursive algorithms. We prove several results about this proof-theoretic degree structure using recursion-theoretic techniques such as diagonalization and the Recursion Theorem.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Sharpened lower bounds for cut elimination.Samuel R. Buss - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (2):656-668.
    We present sharpened lower bounds on the size of cut free proofs for first-order logic. Prior lower bounds for eliminating cuts from a proof established superexponential lower bounds as a stack of exponentials, with the height of the stack proportional to the maximum depth d of the formulas in the original proof. Our results remove the constant of proportionality, giving an exponential stack of height equal to d — 0(1). The proof method is based on more efficiently expressing the Gentzen-Solovay (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the computational content of intuitionistic propositional proofs.Samuel R. Buss & Pavel Pudlák - 2001 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 109 (1-2):49-64.
    The paper proves refined feasibility properties for the disjunction property of intuitionistic propositional logic. We prove that it is possible to eliminate all cuts from an intuitionistic proof, propositional or first-order, without increasing the Horn closure of the proof. We obtain a polynomial time, interactive, realizability algorithm for propositional intuitionistic proofs. The feasibility of the disjunction property is proved for sequents containing Harrop formulas. Under hardness assumptions for NP and for factoring, it is shown that the intuitionistic propositional calculus does (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Paraconsistency, paracompleteness, Gentzen systems, and trivalent semantics.Arnon Avron - 2014 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 24 (1-2):12-34.
    A quasi-canonical Gentzen-type system is a Gentzen-type system in which each logical rule introduces either a formula of the form , or of the form , and all the active formulas of its premises belong to the set . In this paper we investigate quasi-canonical systems in which exactly one of the two classical rules for negation is included, turning the induced logic into either a paraconsistent logic or a paracomplete logic, but not both. We provide a constructive coherence criterion (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On Formally Measuring and Eliminating Extraneous Notions in Proofs.Andrew Arana - 2009 - Philosophia Mathematica 17 (2):189-207.
    Many mathematicians and philosophers of mathematics believe some proofs contain elements extraneous to what is being proved. In this paper I discuss extraneousness generally, and then consider a specific proposal for measuring extraneousness syntactically. This specific proposal uses Gentzen's cut-elimination theorem. I argue that the proposal fails, and that we should be skeptical about the usefulness of syntactic extraneousness measures.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • PROOF THEORY. Gödel and the metamathematical tradition.Jeremy Avigad - 2010 - In Kurt Gödel, Solomon Feferman, Charles Parsons & Stephen G. Simpson (eds.), Kurt Gödel: essays for his centennial. Association for Symbolic Logic.
    At the turn of the nineteenth century, mathematics exhibited a style of argumentation that was more explicitly computational than is common today. Over the course of the century, the introduction of abstract algebraic methods helped unify developments in analysis, number theory, geometry, and the theory of equations; and work by mathematicians like Dedekind, Cantor, and Hilbert towards the end of the century introduced set-theoretic language and infinitary methods that served to downplay or suppress computational content. This shift in emphasis away (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Dag Prawitz on Proofs and Meaning.Heinrich Wansing (ed.) - 2014 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
    This volume is dedicated to Prof. Dag Prawitz and his outstanding contributions to philosophical and mathematical logic. Prawitz's eminent contributions to structural proof theory, or general proof theory, as he calls it, and inference-based meaning theories have been extremely influential in the development of modern proof theory and anti-realistic semantics. In particular, Prawitz is the main author on natural deduction in addition to Gerhard Gentzen, who defined natural deduction in his PhD thesis published in 1934. The book opens with an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Argument of Mathematics.Andrew Aberdein & Ian J. Dove (eds.) - 2013 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    Written by experts in the field, this volume presents a comprehensive investigation into the relationship between argumentation theory and the philosophy of mathematical practice. Argumentation theory studies reasoning and argument, and especially those aspects not addressed, or not addressed well, by formal deduction. The philosophy of mathematical practice diverges from mainstream philosophy of mathematics in the emphasis it places on what the majority of working mathematicians actually do, rather than on mathematical foundations. -/- The book begins by first challenging the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Non-deductive Logic in Mathematics: The Probability of Conjectures.James Franklin - 2013 - In Andrew Aberdein & Ian J. Dove (eds.), The Argument of Mathematics. Springer. pp. 11--29.
    Mathematicians often speak of conjectures, yet unproved, as probable or well-confirmed by evidence. The Riemann Hypothesis, for example, is widely believed to be almost certainly true. There seems no initial reason to distinguish such probability from the same notion in empirical science. Yet it is hard to see how there could be probabilistic relations between the necessary truths of pure mathematics. The existence of such logical relations, short of certainty, is defended using the theory of logical probability (or objective Bayesianism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Necessity of Thought.Cesare Cozzo - 2015 - In Heinrich Wansing (ed.), Dag Prawitz on Proofs and Meaning. Springer. pp. 101-20.
    The concept of “necessity of thought” plays a central role in Dag Prawitz’s essay “Logical Consequence from a Constructivist Point of View” (Prawitz 2005). The theme is later developed in various articles devoted to the notion of valid inference (Prawitz, 2009, forthcoming a, forthcoming b). In section 1 I explain how the notion of necessity of thought emerges from Prawitz’s analysis of logical consequence. I try to expound Prawitz’s views concerning the necessity of thought in sections 2, 3 and 4. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations