Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)Carnap, Kuhn, and the History of Science: A Reply to Thomas Uebel.J. C. Pinto de Oliveira - 2015 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 46 (1):215-223.
    The purpose of this article is to respond to Thomas Uebel´s criticisms of my comments regarding the current revisionism of Carnap´s work and its relations to Kuhn. I begin by pointing out some misunderstandings in the interpretation of my article. I then discuss some aspects related to Carnap´s view of the history of science. First, I emphasize that it was not due to a supposed affinity between Kuhn´s conceptions and those of logical positivism that Kuhn was invited to write the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Psychoanalysis and Interdisciplinarity With Non-analytic Psychotherapeutic Approaches Through the Lens of Dialectics.Yael Peri Herzovich & Aner Govrin - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12:697506.
    Psychoanalysis, in its purist mainstream sense, tends to be considered as an isolationist discipline that steers clear of interdisciplinary connections with other psychotherapies. Its drive for purity does not open up to influences that cast as alien and a threat to its core principles. We refer to Hegelian dialectics in an attempt to offer an alternative approach to interdisciplinarity in clinical psychoanalysis. Psychoanalysis entertains a complex dialectical relationship with the major theories it opposes. In this dynamic, psychoanalysis begins by negating (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Context effects in the entropic theory of perception.Kenneth H. Norwich - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):578-579.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Content of Science Debate in the Historiography of the Scientific Revolution.John Nnaji & José Luis Luján - 2016 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 30 (2):99-109.
    The issue of internalism and externalism in historiography of science was intensely debated two decades ago. The conclusions of such debate on the ‘context of science’ appear to be a reinstatement of the positivist view of the ‘content of science’ as comprising only ideas and concepts uninfluenced by extra-scientific factors. The description of the roles of politics, economy, and socio-cultural factors in science was limited only within the ‘context of science’. This article seeks to resituate the ‘content of science’ debate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The evident object of inquiry.Keith K. Niall - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):578-578.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Epistemic Significance of Valid Inference – A Model-Theoretic Approach.Constantin C. Brîncuș - 2015 - In Sorin Costreie & Mircea Dumitru (eds.), Meaning and Truth. Pro Universitaria. pp. 11-36.
    The problem analysed in this paper is whether we can gain knowledge by using valid inferences, and how we can explain this process from a model-theoretic perspective. According to the paradox of inference (Cohen & Nagel 1936/1998, 173), it is logically impossible for an inference to be both valid and its conclusion to possess novelty with respect to the premises. I argue in this paper that valid inference has an epistemic significance, i.e., it can be used by an agent to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The History of Science as a Graveyard of Theories: A Philosophers’ Myth?Moti Mizrahi - 2016 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 30 (3):263-278.
    According to the antirealist argument known as the pessimistic induction, the history of science is a graveyard of dead scientific theories and abandoned theoretical posits. Support for this pessimistic picture of the history of science usually comes from a few case histories, such as the demise of the phlogiston theory and the abandonment of caloric as the substance of heat. In this article, I wish to take a new approach to examining the ‘history of science as a graveyard of theories’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Beauty in science: a new model of the role of aesthetic evaluations in science. [REVIEW]Ulianov Montano - 2013 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 3 (2):133-156.
    In Beauty and Revolution in Science, James McAllister advances a rationalistic picture of science in which scientific progress is explained in terms of aesthetic evaluations of scientific theories. Here I present a new model of aesthetic evaluations by revising McAllister’s core idea of the aesthetic induction. I point out that the aesthetic induction suffers from anomalies and theoretical inconsistencies and propose a model free from such problems. The new model is based, on the one hand, on McAllister’s original model and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Attributes or objects: A paradigm shift in psychophysics.John S. Monahan - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):577-577.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Louis-Bernard Guyton de Morveau e a revolução química das Luzes.Ronei Clécio Mocellin - 2012 - Scientiae Studia 10 (4):733-758.
    O objetivo deste artigo é investigar a concepção enciclopédica de revolução científica posta em prática pelo químico francês L.-B. Guyton de Morveau (1737-1816). Deslocando a análise do conhecimento químico das Luzes do programa traçado por Lavoisier (1743-1794), sugerimos uma concepção revolucionária republicana, proclamada como resultado do esforço de uma coletividade. Daremos destaque a três abordagens revolucionárias de Guyton de Morveau no âmbito da química. A primeira foi sua atuação no ensino dessa ciência, cuja pedagogia e métodos de ensino foram fundamentais (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Historical Inductions: New Cherries, Same Old Cherry-picking.Moti Mizrahi - 2015 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29 (2):129-148.
    In this article, I argue that arguments from the history of science against scientific realism, like the arguments advanced by P. Kyle Stanford and Peter Vickers, are fallacious. The so-called Old Induction, like Vickers's, and New Induction, like Stanford's, are both guilty of confirmation bias—specifically, of cherry-picking evidence that allegedly challenges scientific realism while ignoring evidence to the contrary. I also show that the historical episodes that Stanford adduces in support of his New Induction are indeterminate between a pessimistic and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • William Whewell's Conception of Scientific Revolutions.Frits Schipper - 1987 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 19 (1):43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Physicians and obligatory social activism.T. Forcht Dagi - 1988 - Journal of Medical Humanities 9 (1):50-59.
    This essay examines the claim that physicians have a special obligation to engage in social and political activism. Four ethical paradigms are considered. Two paradigms, the preventive medicine and the social medicine models, embody a limited professional obligation to advocate the priority of health in society; the justification for a more aggressive stance is limited by the failings of paternalism. The radical model and the heroic model speak to issues of personal virtue rather than professional obligation; they are not strictly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Scientists' Argumentative Reasoning.Hugo Mercier & Christophe Heintz - 2014 - Topoi 33 (2):513-524.
    Reasoning, defined as the production and evaluation of reasons, is a central process in science. The dominant view of reasoning, both in the psychology of reasoning and in the psychology of science, is of a mechanism with an asocial function: bettering the beliefs of the lone reasoner. Many observations, however, are difficult to reconcile with this view of reasoning; in particular, reasoning systematically searches for reasons that support the reasoner’s initial beliefs, and it only evaluates these reasons cursorily. By contrast, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • How important are dimensions to perception?Robert D. Melara - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):576-577.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The myth of the non-Darwinian revolution.Ernst Mayr - 1990 - Biology and Philosophy 5 (1):85-92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Five Decades of Structure.Juan V. Mayoral - 2012 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 27 (3):261-280.
    This paper is an introduction to the special issue commemorating the 50th anniversary of the publication of The Structure of Scientific Revolutions by Thomas Kuhn. It introduces some main ideas of Structure, as its change in historical perspective for the interpretation of scientific progress, the role and nature of scientificcommunities, the incommensurability concept, or the new-world problem, and summarizes some philosophical reactions. After this introduction, the special issue includes papers by Alexander Bird, Paul Hoyningen-Huene and George Reisch on different aspects (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Five Decades of Structure: A Retrospective View.Juan Vicente Mayoral - 2012 - Theoria 27 (3):261-280.
    This paper is an introduction to the special issue commemorating the 50th anniversary of the publication of _The Structure of Scientific Revolutions_ by Thomas Kuhn. It introduces some main ideas of _Structure_, as its change in historical perspective for the interpretation of scientific progress, the role and nature of scientific communities, the incommensurability concept, or the new-world problem, and summarizes some philosophical reactions. After this introduction, the special issue includes papers by Alexander Bird, Paul Hoyningen-Huene and George Reisch on different (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Psychophysics and quantitative perceptual laws.Sergio C. Masin - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):575-576.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The perplexing plurality of psychophysical processes.Lawrence E. Marks - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):574-575.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Jesuit Science After Galileo: The Cosmology of Gabriele Beati.Kerry V. Magruder - 2009 - Centaurus 51 (3):189-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Covert converging operations for multidimensional psychophysics.Neil A. Macmillan - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):573-574.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychophysical scaling: Judgments of attributes or objects?Gregory R. Lockhead - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):543-558.
    Psychophysical scaling models of the form R = f, with R the response and I some intensity of an attribute, all assume that people judge the amounts of an attribute. With simple biases excepted, most also assume that judgments are independent of space, time, and features of the situation other than the one being judged. Many data support these ideas: Magnitude estimations of brightness increase with luminance. Nevertheless, I argue that the general model is wrong. The stabilized retinal image literature (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Constancy in a changing world.Gregory R. Lockhead - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):587-600.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Science, magic and religion: a contextual reassessment of geography in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries.David N. Livingstone - 1988 - History of Science 26 (73):269-294.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Scientific change: Philosophical models and historical research.Larry Laudan, Arthur Donovan, Rachel Laudan, Peter Barker, Harold Brown, Jarrett Leplin, Paul Thagard & Steve Wykstra - 1986 - Synthese 69 (2):141 - 223.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  • Two categories of contextual variable in perception.Donald Laming - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):572-573.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Darwinian revolution as viewed by a philosophical biologist.Michael T. Ghiselin - 2005 - Journal of the History of Biology 38 (1):123-136.
    Darwin proclaimed his own work revolutionary. His revolution, however, is still in progress, and the changes that are going on are reflected in the contemporary historical and philosophical literature, including that written by scientists. The changes have taken place at different levels, and have tended to occur at the more superficial ones. The new ontology that arose as a consequence of the realization that species are individuals at once provides an analytical tool for explaining what has been happening and an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Will the real stimulus please step forward?Lester E. Krueger - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):570-572.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Wissenschaftliche Revolution und gesellschaftlicher Wandel.Wolfgang Krohn - 2010 - NTM Zeitschrift für Geschichte der Wissenschaften, Technik und Medizin 18 (3):329-335.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Novelty and revolution in art and science: The connection between Kuhn and Cavell.Vasso Kindi - 2010 - Perspectives on Science 18 (3):284-310.
    Both Kuhn and Cavell acknowledge their indebtedness to each other in their respective books of the 60s. Cavell in (Must We Mean What We Say (1969)) and Kuhn in (The Structure of Scientific Revolutions 1962). They were together at Berkeley where they had both moved in 1956 as assistant professors after their first encounter at the Society of Fellows at Harvard (Kuhn 2000d, p. 197). In Berkeley, Cavell and Kuhn discovered a mutual understanding and an intellectual affinity. They had regular (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Context effects: Pervasiveness and analysis.Donald L. King - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):570-570.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Psychophysics: Plus ça change ….Peter R. Killeen - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):569-569.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Pursuit of Magnetic Shadows: The Formal-Empirical Dipole Field of Early-Modern Geomagnetism.Art R. T. Jonkers - 2008 - Centaurus 50 (3):254-289.
    Abstract…observations of skylfull pylotts is the onlye waye to bring it in rule; for it passeth the reach of naturall philosophy. – Michael Gabriel, 1576 (Collinson, 1867, p. 30)Abstract The tension between empirical data and formal theory pervades the entire history of geomagnetism, from the Middle Ages up to the present day. This paper explores its early-modern history (1500–1800), using a hybrid approach: it applies a methodological framework used in modern geophysics to interpret early-modern developments, exploring to what extent formal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Thomas Kuhn and the chemical revolution.Paul Hoyningen-Huene - 2008 - Foundations of Chemistry 10 (2):101-115.
    The paper discusses how well Kuhn’s general theory of scientific revolutions fits the particular case of the chemical revolution. To do so, I first present condensed sketches of both Kuhn’s theory and the chemical revolution. I then discuss the beginning of the chemical revolution and compare it to Kuhn’s specific claims about the roles of anomalies, crisis and extraordinary science in scientific development. I proceed by comparing some features of the chemical revolution as a whole to Kuhn’s general account. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • The Darwinian Revolution Revisited.Sandra Herbert - 2005 - Journal of the History of Biology 38 (1):51 - 66.
    The "Darwinian revolution" remains an acceptable phrase to describe the change in thought brought about by the theory of evolution, provided that the revolution is seen as occurring over an extended period of time. The decades from the 1790s through the 1850s are at the focus of this article. Emphasis is placed on the issue of species extinction and on generational shifts in opinion.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • De-centring the ‘big picture’: The Origins of Modern Science and the modern origins of science.Andrew Cunningham & Perry Williams - 1993 - British Journal for the History of Science 26 (4):407-432.
    Like it or not, a big picture of the history of science is something which we cannot avoid. Big pictures are, of course, thoroughly out of fashion at the moment; those committed to specialist research find them simplistic and insufficiently complex and nuanced, while postmodernists regard them as simply impossible. But however specialist we may be in our research, however scornful of the immaturity of grand narratives, it is not so easy to escape from dependence – acknowledged or not – (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Resources for Research on Analogy: A Multi-disciplinary Guide.Marcello Guarini, Amy Butchart, Paul Simard Smith & Andrei Moldovan - 2009 - Informal Logic 29 (2):84-197.
    Work on analogy has been done from a number of disciplinary perspectives throughout the history of Western thought. This work is a multidisciplinary guide to theorizing about analogy. It contains 1,406 references, primarily to journal articles and monographs, and primarily to English language material. classical through to contemporary sources are included. The work is classified into eight different sections (with a number of subsections). A brief introduction to each section is provided. Keywords and key expressions of importance to research on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Walking in a psychophysical dustbowl creates a dustcloud.Robert A. M. Gregson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):568-569.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Scales falling from the eyes?Richard L. Gregory - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):567-568.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • I—European Philosophical History and Faith in God A Posteriori.Simon Glendinning - 2017 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 91 (1):63-82.
    Studies of Europe and European identity today are dominated by the methods of the social sciences. Europe is understood as a geographical region of a global totality, and treated in political-economic terms; and European identity is largely investigated through social surveys. This paper explores the possibility of a philosophical contribution to understanding Europe: an understanding based on the idea that Europe is itself a distinctively philosophical phenomenon, and that its modern geopolitical condition has an irreducibly geophilosophical significance.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Experience and Reason in Einstein's Epistemology.S. Glenn - 2012 - Metaphilosophy 43 (5):679-697.
    Albert Einstein insists that his epistemology made his discovery of relativity possible. He believed it was his understanding of the relationship of experience and reason that allowed him to reconsider certain “truths” of physics. Specifically, he believed that reality and thought were independent but related, and that conceptual systems are independent of but conditioned by experience. Failure to understand the relation between experience and reason had, Einstein believed, limited progress in science. His understanding of the relation, on the other hand, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Intersubjective probability and confirmation theory.Donald Gillies - 1991 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 42 (4):513-533.
    This paper introduces what is called the intersubjective interpretation of the probability calculus. Intersubjective probabilities are related to subjective probabilities, and the paper begins with a particular formulation of the familiar Dutch Book argument. This argument is then extended, in Section 3, to social groups, and this enables the concept of intersubjective probability to be introduced in Section 4. It is then argued that the intersubjective interpretation is the appropriate one for the probabilities which appear in confirmation theory whether of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Analytical chemistry and the ‘big’ scientific instrumentation revolution.Davis Baird - 1993 - Annals of Science 50 (3):267-290.
    By a close examination of changes in analytical chemistry between the years 1920 and 1950, I document the case that natural science has undergone and continues to undergo a major revolution. The central feature of this transformation is the rise in importance of scientific instrumentation. Prior to 1920, analytical chemists determined the chemical constitution of some unknown by treating it with a series of known compounds and observing the kind of reactions it underwent. After 1950, analytical chemists determined the chemical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The complexity and importance of the psychophysical scaling of sensory attributes.George A. Gescheider - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):567-567.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Deviant interdisciplinarity as philosophical practice: prolegomena to deep intellectual history.Steve Fuller - 2013 - Synthese 190 (11):1899-1916.
    Philosophy may relate to interdisciplinarity in two distinct ways On the one hand, philosophy may play an auxiliary role in the process of interdisciplinarity, typically through conceptual analysis, in the understanding that the disciplines themselves are the main epistemic players. This version of the relationship I characterise as ‘normal’ because it captures the more common pattern of the relationship, which in turn reflects an acceptance of the division of organized inquiry into disciplines. On the other hand, philosophy may be itself (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • More on revolutions in biology.Felix Friedberg & Jan A. Witkowski - 1997 - Bioessays 19 (2):181-182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Psychophysical invariance, perceptual invariance and the physicalistic trap.Hannes Eisler - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):566-567.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Can brightness be related to luminance by a meaningful function?Ehtibar N. Dzhafarov - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):565-566.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The “Conflict Thesis” and Positivist History of Science: A View From the Periphery.Miguel de Asúa - 2018 - Zygon 53 (4):1131-1148.
    The historiographic tradition of the history of science that originated with Auguste Comte bears all the marks of narratives with roots in the Enlightenment, such as a view of religion as an underdeveloped stage in the ascending road in humanity's quest for a more mature understanding. This article explores the development of the peripheral branch of a tradition that developed in Argentina by the mid‐twentieth century with authors such as the Italians Aldo Mieli, José Babini, and the Hungarian Desiderius Papp. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation