Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Perception Of The Visual World

Boston: Houghton Mifflin (1950)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Perspectival shapes are viewpoint-dependent relational properties.Tony Cheng, Yi Lin & Chen-Wei Wu - 2022 - Psychological Review (1):307-310.
    Recently, there is a renewed debate concerning the role of perspective in vision. Morales et al. (2020) present evidence that, in the case of viewing a rotated coin, the visual system is sensitive to what has often been called “perspectival shapes.” It has generated vigorous discussions, including an online symposium by Morales and Cohen, an exchange between Linton (2021) and Morales et al. (2021), and most recently, a fierce critique by Burge and Burge (2022), in which they launch various conceptual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards a Phenomenological Ontology: Synthetic A Priori Reasoning and the Cosmological Anthropic Principle.James Schofield - 2022 - Journal of Mind and Behavior 43 (1):1-24.
    The purpose of this paper is to analyze the theoretical commitments of autopoietic enactivism in relation to Errol E Harris’s dialectical holism in the interest of establishing a common metaphysical ground. This will be undertaken in three stages. First, it is argued that Harris’s reasoning provides a means of developing enactivist ontology beyond discussions limited to cognitive science and into domains of metaphysics that have traditionally been avoided by phenomenologists. Here, I maintain enactivist commitments are consistent with Harris’s reasoning from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sensory Fields: the Visual and the Bodily.Carlota Serrahima - 2023 - Philosophical Studies 180 (2):679-700.
    Philosophers of perception have been readier to postulate the existence of a visual field than to acknowledge sensory fields in other modalities. In this paper, I argue that the set of phenomenal features that philosophers have relied on when positing a visual field aptly characterise, mutatis mutandis, bodily sensation. I argue, in particular, that in localised bodily sensations we experience the body as a sensory field. I first motivate this claim for the case of haptic touch, and then generalise it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mental states follow quantum mechanics during perception and cognition of ambiguous figures.Elio Conte - 2009 - In Krzysztof Stefanski (ed.), Open Systems and Information Dynamics. World scientific publishing company. pp. 1-17.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Possible roles for a predictor plus comparator mechanism in human episodic recognition memory and imitative learning.Simon Dennis & Michael Humphreys - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):678-679.
    This commentary is divided into two parts. The first considers a possible role for Gray's predictor plus comparator mechanism in human episodic recognition memory. It draws on the computational specifications of recognition outlined in Humphreys et al. to demonstrate how the logically necessary components of recognition tasks might be mapped onto the mechanism. The second part demonstrates how the mechanism outlined by Gray might be implicated in a form of imitative learning suitable for the acquisition of complex tasks.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Eliminate the middletoad!Daniel Dennett - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):372-374.
    Philosophical controversy about the mind has flourished in the thin air of our ignorance about the brain. The humble toad, it now seems, may provide our first instance of a creature whose whole brain is within the reach of our scientific understanding. What will happen to the traditional philosophical issues as our theoretical and factual ignorance recedes? Discussion of the issues explored in the target article is, as Ewert says, "often too theoretical, sometimes philosophical and even [as if that weren't (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Hunting for consciousness in the brain: What is (the name of) the game?José-Luis Díaz - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):679-680.
    Robust theories concerning the connection between consciousness and brain function should derive not only from empirical evidence but also from a well grounded inind-body ontology. In the case of the comparator hypothesis, Gray develops his ideas relying extensively on empirical evidence, but he bounces irresolutely among logically incompatible metaphysical theses which, in turn, leads him to excessively skeptical conclusions concerning the naturalization of consciousness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • What is self-induced motor activity adapting to?R. H. Day - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):66-67.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Images, depth cues, and cross-cultural differences in perception.R. H. Day - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):78-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Direct perception theory needs to include computational reasoning, not extraretinal information.Niels da Vitoria Lobo - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):318-318.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Just how different are perceptual and visuomotor localization abilities?Paul Dassonville, John Schlag & Madeleine Schlag-Rey - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):258-259.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Stability by degrees: conceptions of constancy from the history of perceptual psychology.Louise Daoust - 2021 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 43 (1):1-22.
    Do the physical facts of the viewed environment account for the ordinary experiences we have of that environment? According to standard philosophical views, distal facts do account for our experiences, a phenomenon explained by appeal to perceptual constancy, the phenomenal stability of objects and environmental properties notwithstanding physical changes in proximal stimulation. This essay reviews a significant but neglected research tradition in experimental psychology according to which percepts systematically do not correspond to mind-independent distal facts. Instead, stability of percept values (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Variations in pictorial culture.Arthur C. Danto - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):77-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Grossberg's “cells” considered as cell assemblies.G. J. Dalenoort - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (4):662.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Direct judgments: Sensation or stimulus correlate?Dwight W. Curtis - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):191-192.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Information and cognitive agents.Robert Cummins - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):68-69.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Segmentalized consciousness in schizophrenia.Andrew Crider - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):676-677.
    Segmentalized consciousness in schizophrenia reflects a loss of the normal Gestalt organization and contextualization of perception. Grays model explains such segmentalization in terms of septohippocampal dysfunction, which is consistent with known neuropsychological impairment in schizophrenia. However, other considerations suggest that everyday perception and its failure in schizophrenia also involve prefrontal executive mechanisms, which are only minimally elaborated by Gray.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A stationary subject does perceive curvature when wearing a prism in a spotted drum.Brian Craske - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):66-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When “filling in” fails.Stanley Coren - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (4):661.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The determinants of perceived brightness are complicated, but not hopelessly so.Thomas R. Corwin - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):564-565.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychophysical scaling: Context and illusion.Stanley Coren - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):563-564.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Cross-cultural studies of visual illusions: The physiological confound.Stantley Coren - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):76-77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sensorimotor functions: What is a command, that a code may yield it?Christopher M. Comer - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):372-372.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Phase-space representation and coordinate transformation: A general paradigm for neural computation.Paul M. Churchland - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):93-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Content: Semantic and information-theoretic.Paul M. Churchland & Patricia S. Churchland - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):67-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Is there a role for extraretinal factors in the maintenance of stability in a structured environment?Eugene Chekaluk - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):258-258.
    The calibration solution to the stability of the world despite eye movements depends, according to Bridgeman et al., upon a combination of three factors which presumably all need to operate to achieve the goal of stability. Although the authors admit (sect. 4.3, para. 5) that the relative contributions of retinal and extraretinal factors will depend on the particular viewing situation, Figure 5 (sect. 4.3) makes it clear in its representation that the role of perceptual factors is relatively minor compared to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • The Differentiation of Self-Motion From External Motion Is a Prerequisite for Postural Control: A Narrative Review of Visual-Vestibular Interaction.Shikha Chaudhary, Nicola Saywell & Denise Taylor - 2022 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 16.
    The visual system is a source of sensory information that perceives environmental stimuli and interacts with other sensory systems to generate visual and postural responses to maintain postural stability. Although the three sensory systems; the visual, vestibular, and somatosensory systems work concurrently to maintain postural control, the visual and vestibular system interaction is vital to differentiate self-motion from external motion to maintain postural stability. The visual system influences postural control playing a key role in perceiving information required for this differentiation. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reconciling simplicity and likelihood principles in perceptual organization.Nick Chater - 1996 - Psychological Review 103 (3):566-581.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Is pictorial space “perceived” as real space?Josiane Caron-Pargue - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):75-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How is a toad not like a bug?Jeffrey M. Camhi - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):371-372.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Universal coding and network structures for vision: Is Grossberg correct?Terry Caelli - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (4):660.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • AI and Ethics When Human Beings Collaborate With AI Agents.José J. Cañas - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    The relationship between a human being and an AI system has to be considered as a collaborative process between two agents during the performance of an activity. When there is a collaboration between two people, a fundamental characteristic of that collaboration is that there is co-supervision, with each agent supervising the actions of the other. Such supervision ensures that the activity achieves its objectives, but it also means that responsibility for the consequences of the activity is shared. If there is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The “neuroethological revolution” in unit studies.Jan Bureš - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):497-498.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Adaptation to curvature in the absence of contour.Clarke A. Burnham - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):65-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Functional and computational aspects of perception.Hans Buffart - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (4):659.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The problem of perceptual invariance.Alessandra Buccella - 2021 - Synthese 199 (5-6):13883-13905.
    It is a familiar experience to perceive a material object as maintaining a stable shape even though it projects differently shaped images on our retina as we move with respect to it, or as maintaining a stable color throughout changes in the way the object is illuminated. We also perceive sounds as maintaining constant timbre and loudness when the context and the spatial relations between us and the sound source change over time. But where does this perceptual invariance ‘come from’? (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Accounting for an old inconsistency in the psychophysics of Plateau and Delboeuf.Marc Brysbaert - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):562-563.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Could three frames suffice?Roger A. Browse & Brian E. Butler - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (2):290-291.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • After the sensory analysers: Problems with concepts and terminology.D. M. Broom - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):370-371.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Isomorphism is where you find it.Bruce Bridgeman - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (4):658.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How our world remains stable despite disturbing influences.Bruce Bridgeman, A. H. C. Van der Heijden & Boris M. Velichkovsky - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):282-292.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Extending reference signal theory to rapid movements.Bruce Bridgeman & Jean Blouin - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):315-316.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Direct perception and a call for primary perception.Bruce Bridgeman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):382-383.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Adaptation and the two-visual-systems hypothesis.Bruce Bridgeman - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):64-65.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Symmetry-breaking dynamics in development.Noah Moss Brender - 2017 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 16 (4):585-596.
    Recognition of the plasticity of development — from gene expression to neuroplasticity — is increasingly undermining the traditional distinction between structure and function, or anatomy and behavior. At the same time, dynamic systems theory — a set of tools and concepts drawn from the physical sciences — has emerged as a way of describing what Maurice Merleau-Ponty calls the “dynamic anatomy” of the living organism. This article surveys and synthesizes dynamic systems models of development from biology, neuroscience, and psychology in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Direct perception: an opponent and a precursor of computational theories.O. J. Braddick - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):381-382.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychophysical scaling: To describe relations or to uncover a law?Gunnar Borg - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):561-562.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Recognition of objects by physical attributes.D. A. Booth - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):759-760.
    [Comment, pp 759-780] Lockhead (1992) [Target Article] is undoubtedly right to attack so-called intensity scaling or the estimation of subjective magnitudes as an invalid perversion of tasks requiring quantitative judgments of aspects of objects, stuffs, and situations. He goes too far, however, in claiming that feature scales do not exist... ... A perceived physical pattern (sensory feature or channel) and the cognitive process that integrates it with its context are characterized by determining to which particular combination of specified stimulus patterns (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Determining what is perceived.Radu J. Bogdan - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):66-67.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • O'Keefe & Nadel's three-stage model for hippocampal representation of space.T. V. P. Bliss - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):496-497.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark