Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Traversing the conceptual divide between biological and statistical epistasis: systems biology and a more modern synthesis.Jason H. Moore & Scott M. Williams - 2005 - Bioessays 27 (6):637-646.
    Epistasis plays an important role in the genetic architecture of common human diseases and can be viewed from two perspectives, biological and statistical, each derived from and leading to different assumptions and research strategies. Biological epistasis is the result of physical interactions among biomolecules within gene regulatory networks and biochemical pathways in an individual such that the effect of a gene on a phenotype is dependent on one or more other genes. In contrast, statistical epistasis is defined as deviation from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The role of convention in the communication of private events.Chris Moore - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):656-657.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Behaviorism, introspection and the mind's I.Jay Moore - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):657-658.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pigeons as communicators and thinkers: Mon oncle d'Amerique deux?Robert W. Mitchell - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):655-656.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Model organisms in evo-devo: promises and pitfalls of the comparative approach.Alessandro Minelli & Jan Baedke - 2014 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 36 (1):42-59.
    Evolutionary developmental biology is a rapidly growing discipline whose ambition is to address questions that are of relevance to both evolutionary biology and developmental biology. This field has been increasingly progressing as a new and independent comparative science. However, we argue that evo-devo’s comparative approach is challenged by several metaphysical, methodological and socio-disciplinary issues related to the foundation of heuristic functions of model organisms and the possible criteria to be adopted for their selection. In addition, new tools have to be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Eclipsing the Eclipse?: A Neo-Darwinian Historiography Revisited.Max Meulendijks - 2021 - Journal of the History of Biology 54 (3):403-443.
    Julian Huxley’s eclipse of Darwinism narrative has cast a long shadow over the historiography of evolutionary theory around the turn of the nineteenth century. It has done so by limiting who could be thought of as Darwinian. Peter Bowler used the eclipse to draw attention to previously understudied alternatives to Darwinism, but maintained the same flaw. In his research on the Non-Darwinian Revolution, he extended this problematic element even further back in time. This paper explores how late nineteenth-century neo-Darwinian conceptualizations (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is Non-genetic Inheritance Just a Proximate Mechanism? A Corroboration of the Extended Evolutionary Synthesis.Alex Mesoudi, Simon Blanchet, Anne Charmantier, Étienne Danchin, Laurel Fogarty, Eva Jablonka, Kevin N. Laland, Thomas J. H. Morgan, Gerd B. Müller, F. John Odling-Smee & Benoît Pujol - 2013 - Biological Theory 7 (3):189-195.
    What role does non-genetic inheritance play in evolution? In recent work we have independently and collectively argued that the existence and scope of non-genetic inheritance systems, including epigenetic inheritance, niche construction/ecological inheritance, and cultural inheritance—alongside certain other theory revisions—necessitates an extension to the neo-Darwinian Modern Synthesis (MS) in the form of an Extended Evolutionary Synthesis (EES). However, this argument has been challenged on the grounds that non-genetic inheritance systems are exclusively proximate mechanisms that serve the ultimate function of calibrating organisms (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • J. B. S. Haldane's Darwinism in its religious context.Gordon McOuat & Mary P. Winsor - 1995 - British Journal for the History of Science 28 (2):227-231.
    Early in this century, only a few biologists accepted that natural selection was the chief cause of evolution, until the independent calculations of John Burdon Sanderson Haldane (1892–1964), Sewall Wright and R. A. Fisher demonstrated that ideal populations subject to Mendel's laws could behave as Darwin had said they would. Evolutionary theorist John Maynard Smith, a student of Haldane's, has raised the question of why Haldane, who was no naturalist, took up the subject of evolution, and he suggests that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A developmental look at grooming, grunting and group cohesion.Lorraine McCune - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):716-717.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Victoria institute, biblical criticism, and the fundamentals.Stuart Mathieson - 2021 - Zygon 56 (1):254-274.
    The Victoria Institute was established in London in 1865. Although billed as an anti-evolutionary organization, and stridently anti-Darwinian in its rhetoric, it spent relatively little time debating the theory of natural selection. Instead, it served as a haven for a specific set of intellectual commitments. Most important among these was the Baconian scientific methodology, which prized empiricism and induction, and was suspicious of speculation. Darwin's use of hypotheses meant that the Victoria Institute members were unconvinced that his work was truly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Kuhnian revolution in molecular biology: Most genes in complex organisms express regulatory RNAs.John S. Mattick - 2023 - Bioessays 45 (9):2300080.
    Thomas Kuhn described the progress of science as comprising occasional paradigm shifts separated by interludes of ‘normal science’. The paradigm that has held sway since the inception of molecular biology is that genes (mainly) encode proteins. In parallel, theoreticians posited that mutation is random, inferred that most of the genome in complex organisms is non‐functional, and asserted that somatic information is not communicated to the germline. However, many anomalies appeared, particularly in plants and animals: the strange genetic phenomena of paramutation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Comparative studies, phylogenies and predictions of coevolutionary relationships.Emília P. Martins - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):714-716.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Species and individual differences in communication based on private states.David Lubinski & Travis Thompson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):627-642.
    The way people come to report private stimulation arising within their own bodies is not well understood. Although the Darwinian assumption of biological continuity has been the basis of extensive animal modeling for many human biological and behavioral phenomena, few have attempted to model human communication based on private stimulation. This target article discusses such an animal model using concepts and methods derived from the study of discriminative stimulus effects of drugs and recent research on interanimal communication. We discuss how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Animal models: Nature made us, but was the mold broken?David Lubinski & Travis Thompson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):664-680.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How Future Depends on Past and Rare Events in Systems of Life.Giuseppe Longo - 2018 - Foundations of Science 23 (3):443-474.
    The dependence on history of both present and future dynamics of life is a common intuition in biology and in humanities. Historicity will be understood in terms of changes of the space of possibilities as well as by the role of diversity in life’s structural stability and of rare events in history formation. We hint to a rigorous analysis of “path dependence” in terms of invariants and invariance preserving transformations, as it may be found also in physics, while departing from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • DNA Dispose, but Subjects Decide. Learning and the Extended Synthesis.Markus Lindholm - 2015 - Biosemiotics 8 (3):443-461.
    Adaptation by means of natural selection depends on the ability of populations to maintain variation in heritable traits. According to the Modern Synthesis this variation is sustained by mutations and genetic drift. Epigenetics, evodevo, niche construction and cultural factors have more recently been shown to contribute to heritable variation, however, leading an increasing number of biologists to call for an extended view of speciation and evolution. An additional common feature across the animal kingdom is learning, defined as the ability to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Evolutionary Progress: Stephen Jay Gould’s Rejection and Its Critique.Jianhui Li - 2019 - Philosophy Study 9 (6).
    In evolutionary theory, we generally believe that the evolution of life is from simple to complex, from single to diverse, and from lower to higher. Thus, the idea of evolutionary progress appears obvious. However, in contemporary academic circles, some biologists and philosophers challenge this idea. Among them, Gould is the most influential. This paper first describes Gould’s seven arguments against evolutionary progress, i.e., the human arrogance argument, anthropocentric argument, no inner thrust argument, no biological base argument, extreme contingency argument, statistical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What's biological about the continuity?Justin Leiber - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):654-655.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • We can reliably report psychological states because they are neither internal nor private.James D. Laird - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):654-654.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Animal modeling in psychopharmacological contexts.Hugh LaFollette & Niall Shanks - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):653-654.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Pigeons and the problem of other minds.Aarre Laakso - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):652-653.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The struggle for life and adaptation by natural selection.Adam Krashniak - 2021 - Biology and Philosophy 36 (3):1-16.
    While the struggle for life played an important role in the process of natural selection as it was conceived by Darwin, natural selection is commonly characterized today as a process which does not necessarily involve struggle. Nevertheless, there have been some attempts to show the importance of struggle to the process of natural selection. The present paper aims to continue these attempts and clarify the precise evolutionary role of struggle. The paper focuses on a recent dispute regarding the role of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Punctuated equilibria and phyletic gradualism: Even partners can be good friends.J. C. Von Vaupel Klein - 1994 - Acta Biotheoretica 42 (1):15-48.
    The allegedly alternative theories of Phyletic Gradualism and Punctuated Equilibria are examined as regards the nature of their differences. The explanatory value of both models is determined by establishing their actual connection with reality. It is concluded that they are to be considered complementary rather than mutually exclusive at all levels of infraspecific, specific, and supraspecific evolution. So, in order to be described comprehensively, the pathways of evolution require at least two distinct models, each based on a discrete range of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Phyletic Gradualism versus Punctuated Equilibria: Why case histories do not suffice.J. C. Von Vaupel Klein - 1995 - Acta Biotheoretica 43 (3):259-278.
    Many attempts have been made at supporting either one of the allegedly complementary divergence models Phyletic Gradualism and Punctuated Equilibria by patterns found in specific fossil sequences. However, assessing each model's connection with reality via such “individual case histories” appears not to constitute a relevant approach. Instead, in order to correctly establish the possible merits of both concepts, the claims of each have to be verified against general evolutionary theory. This is being pointed out herein by analyzing cladogenesis at the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Group size, language and evolutionary mechanisms.Harold Kincaid - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):713-714.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cause and effect in evolution.Michael J. Katz - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):492-492.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The role of genes in life.H. Kalmus - 1959 - Acta Biotheoretica 13 (2-3):107-114.
    Cette étude critique deux notions très répandues: 1° que les genes chromosomes forment les unités fondamentales du mécanisme biologique: 2° que les organismes sont des conséquences d'ensembles de genes ‘libres’.Il est suggéré que 3° l'information codée dans les chromosomes est plutôt comparable aux indications données par un livret d'instructions et que 4° des actions fondamentales des cellules ont pu précéder les instructions qui les concernent de même façon que les techniques humaines ont précédé des textes qui les analysent.Cette analogie est (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The architects of the evolutionary synthesis in national socialist germany: Science and politics. [REVIEW]Thomas Junker & Uwe Hoßfeld - 2002 - Biology and Philosophy 17 (2):223-249.
    The Synthetic Theory of Evolution (SyntheticDarwinism) was forged between 1925 and 1950.Several historians of science have pointed outthat this synthesis was a joint venture ofSoviet, German, American and Britishbiologists: A fascinating example of scientificcooperation, considering the fact that theevolutionary synthesis emerged during thedecades in which these countries were engagedin fierce political, military and ideologicalconflicts. The ideological background of itsAnglo-American representatives has beenanalyzed in the literature. We have examinedthe scientific work and ideological commitmentsof the German Darwinians during the ThirdReich. We based (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Synthesizing disciplinary narratives: George gaylord Simpson's tempo and mode in evolution.Debra Journet - 1995 - Social Epistemology 9 (2):113 – 150.
    (1995). Synthesizing disciplinary narratives: George Gaylord Simpson's tempo and mode in evolution. Social Epistemology: Vol. 9, Boundary Rhetorics and the Work of Interdisciplinarity, pp. 113-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Number our days: Quantifying social evolution.Harry J. Jerison - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):712-713.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hunter-gatherer sociospatial organization and group size.Robert Jarvenpa - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):712-712.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Primate group size, brains and communication: A New World perspective.Charles H. Janson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):711-712.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sizing up social groups.Bob Jacobs & Michael J. Raleigh - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):710-711.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Size of human groups during the Paleolithic and the evolutionary significance of increased group size.Michael E. Hyland - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):709-710.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Evolution and nursing.Trevor Hussey - 2002 - Nursing Philosophy 3 (3):240-251.
    Evolutionary theory has been a very popular topic in recent years and it has been claimed that it can make a major contribution to the advance of several sciences such as medicine, psychology, psychopathology and sociology: even providing them with new paradigms. This paper explores the possibility that nursing could benefit similarly by adopting an evolutionary perspective. After sketching the scientific and philosophical background to the recent developments concerning evolution, and briefly mentioning the chief features of evolutionary theory, the paper (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Behaviorism is alive and well.Lloyd G. Humphreys - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):651-652.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The molecular and mathematical basis of Waddington's epigenetic landscape: A framework for post‐Darwinian biology?Sui Huang - 2012 - Bioessays 34 (2):149-157.
    The Neo‐Darwinian concept of natural selection is plausible when one assumes a straightforward causation of phenotype by genotype. However, such simple 1:1 mapping must now give place to the modern concepts of gene regulatory networks and gene expression noise. Both can, in the absence of genetic mutations, jointly generate a diversity of inheritable randomly occupied phenotypic states that could also serve as a substrate for natural selection. This form of epigenetic dynamics challenges Neo‐Darwinism. It needs to incorporate the non‐linear, stochastic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Pluralizing Darwin: Making Counter-Factual History of Science Significant.Thierry Hoquet - 2021 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 52 (1):115-134.
    In the wake of recent attempts at alternate history (Bowler 2013), this paper suggests several avenues for a pluralistic approach to Charles Darwin and his role in the history of evolutionary theory. We examine in what sense Darwin could be described as a major driver of theoretical change in the history of biology. First, this paper examines how Darwin influenced the future of biological science: not merely by stating the fact of evolution or by bringing evidence for it; but by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the stabilization of behavioral selection.Werner K. Honig - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):491-492.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Another primate brain fiction: Brain (cortex) weight and homogeneity.Ralph L. Holloway - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):707-708.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Difference without discontinuity.Max Hocutt - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):651-651.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A promissory note is paid, but has this bought into an illusion?Philip N. Hineline - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):650-651.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The invention of the psychosocial: An introduction.Rhodri Hayward - 2012 - History of the Human Sciences 25 (5):3-12.
    Although the compound adjective ‘psychosocial’ was first used by academic psychologists in the 1890s, it was only in the interwar period that psychiatrists, psychologists and social workers began to develop detailed models of the psychosocial domain. These models marked a significant departure from earlier ideas of the relationship between society and human nature. Whereas Freudians and Darwinians had described an antagonistic relationship between biological instincts and social forces, interwar authors insisted that individual personality was made possible through collective organization. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The functions of grooming and language: The present need not reflect the past.Marc Hauser, Leah Gardner, Tony Goldberg & Adrian Treves - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):706-707.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Communication versus discrimination.Valerie Gray Hardcastle - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):649-650.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Brains, grouping and language.A. H. Harcourt - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):706-706.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Organic selection: Proximate environmental effects on the evolution of morphology and behaviour. [REVIEW]Brian K. Hall - 2001 - Biology and Philosophy 16 (2):215-237.
    Organic selection (the Baldwin Effect) by which an environmentally elicitedphenotypic adaptation comes under genotypic control following selectionwas proposed independently in 1896 by the psychologists James Baldwinand Conwy Lloyd Morgan and by the paleontologist Henry Fairfield Osborn.Modified forms of organic selection were proposed as autonomization bySchmalhausen in 1938, as genetic assimilation by Waddington in 1942, andas an explanation for evolution in changing environments or for speciationby Matsuda and West-Eberhard in the 1980s. Organic selection as amechanism mediating proximate environmental effects on the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Fitting culture into a Skinner box.C. R. Hallpike - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):489-490.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Instinct in the ‘50s: The British Reception of Konrad Lorenz’s Theory of Instinctive Behavior.Paul E. Griffiths - 2004 - Biology and Philosophy 19 (4):609-631.
    At the beginning of the 1950s most students of animal behavior in Britain saw the instinct concept developed by Konrad Lorenz in the 1930s as the central theoretical construct of the new ethology. In the mid 1950s J.B.S. Haldane made substantial efforts to undermine Lorenz''s status as the founder of the new discipline, challenging his priority on key ethological concepts. Haldane was also critical of Lorenz''s sharp distinction between instinctive and learnt behavior. This was inconsistent with Haldane''s account of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The history of ideas revisited.John C. Greene - 1986 - Revue de Synthèse 107 (3):201-227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations