Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Perspectival content of visual experiences.Błażej Skrzypulec - forthcoming - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy.
    The usual visual experiences possess a perspectival phenomenology as they seem to present objects from a certain perspective. Nevertheless, it is not obvious how to characterise experiential content determining such phenomenology. In particular, while there are many works investigating perspectival properties of experienced objects, a question regarding how subject is represented in visual perspectival experiences attracted less attention. In order to address this problem, I consider four popular phenomenal intuitions regarding perspectival experiences and argue that the major theories of perspectival (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Tactile temporal order judgment during rubber hand illusion: Distinct modulation of the point of subjective simultaneity and temporal resolution.Satoshi Shibuya, Hiroki Oosone & Yukari Ohki - 2022 - Consciousness and Cognition 105 (C):103402.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Body and the Senses in Spatial Experience: The Implications of Kinesthetic and Synesthetic Perceptions for Design Thinking.Jain Kwon & Alyssa Iedema - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    Human perception has long been a critical subject of design thinking. While various studies have stressed the link between thinking and acting, particularly in spatial experience, the term “design thinking” seems to disconnect conceptual thinking from physical expression or process. Spatial perception is multimodal and fundamentally bound to the body that is not a mere receptor of sensory stimuli but an active agent engaged with the perceivable environment. The body apprehends the experience in which one’s kinesthetic engagement and knowledge play (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The role of affective touch in whole-body embodiment remains equivocal.Mark Carey, Laura Crucianelli, Catherine Preston & Aikaterini Fotopoulou - 2021 - Consciousness and Cognition 87 (C):103059.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How Does Embodying a Transgender Narrative Influence Social Bias? An Explorative Study in an Artistic Context.Marte Roel Lesur, Sonia Lyn & Bigna Lenggenhager - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Virtual reality protocols inducing illusory embodiment of avatars have shown a positive impact in participants’ perception of outgroup members, in line with the idea that the simulation of another’s sensorimotor states might underlie pro-social behaviour. These studies, however, have been mostly confined to laboratory settings with student populations, and the use of artificial avatars. In an interdisciplinary effort benefiting from the heterogeneous sample within a museum, we aimed at quantifying changes in interpersonal perception induced by embodying a transgender man narrating (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Effect of External Force on Agency in Physical Human-Machine Interaction.Satoshi Endo, Jakob Fröhner, Selma Musić, Sandra Hirche & Philipp Beckerle - 2020 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Explicit and Implicit Own's Body and Space Perception in Painful Musculoskeletal Disorders and Rheumatic Diseases: A Systematic Scoping Review.Antonello Viceconti, Eleonora Maria Camerone, Deborah Luzzi, Debora Pentassuglia, Matteo Pardini, Diego Ristori, Giacomo Rossettini, Alberto Gallace, Matthew R. Longo & Marco Testa - 2020 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Getting closer: Synchronous interpersonal multisensory stimulation increases closeness and attraction toward an opposite-sex other in female participants.Virginie Quintard, Stéphane Jouffre, Maria-Paola Paladino & Cédric A. Bouquet - 2020 - Consciousness and Cognition 77:102849.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Manipulating body representations with virtual reality: Clinical implications for anorexia nervosa.Stephen Gadsby - 2019 - Philosophical Psychology 32 (6):898-922.
    Anorexia nervosa patients exhibit distorted body-representations. Specifically, they represent their bodies as larger than reality. Given that this distortion likely exacerbates the condition, there is an obligation to further understand and, if possible, rectify it. In pursuit of this, experimental paradigms are needed which manipulate the spatial content of these representations. In this essay, I discuss how virtual reality technology that implements full-body variants of the rubber-hand illusion may prove useful in this regard, and I discuss some issues related to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Tool Embodiment: The Tool’s Output Must Match the User’s Input.Veronica Weser & Dennis R. Proffitt - 2019 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Architectonic Experience of Body and Space in Augmented Interiors.Isabella Pasqualini, Maria Laura Blefari, Tej Tadi, Andrea Serino & Olaf Blanke - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Distorted body representations in anorexia nervosa.Stephen Gadsby - 2017 - Consciousness and Cognition 51:17-33.
    In this paper, I discuss empirical evidence regarding anorexic patients’ distorted body representations. I fit this evidence into a broader framework for understanding how the spatial content of the body is tracked and represented. This framework is motivated by O’Shaughnessy’s (1980) long-term body image hypothesis. This hypothesis posits a representation that tracks changes in the spatial content of the body and supplies this content to other body representations. I argue that a similar kind of body representation might exist and, in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Subjectivity of the Anomalous Sense of Self Is Represented in Gray Matter Volume in the Brain.Noriaki Kanayama, Tomohisa Asai, Takashi Nakao, Kai Makita, Ryutaro Kozuma, Takuto Uyama, Toshiyuki Yamane, Hiroshi Kadota & Shigeto Yamawaki - 2017 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Effect of Visual, Spatial and Temporal Manipulations on Embodiment and Action.Ratcliffe Natasha & Newport Roger - 2017 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Embodied prosthetic arm stabilizes body posture, while unembodied one perturbs it.Shu Imaizumi, Tomohisa Asai & Shinichi Koyama - 2016 - Consciousness and Cognition 45:75-88.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Effects of Tai Chi Practice on Intermuscular Beta Coherence and the Rubber Hand Illusion.Catherine E. Kerr, Uday Agrawal & Sandeep Nayak - 2016 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Representation of Patients’ Hand Modulates Fear Reactions of Patients with Spider Phobia in Virtual Reality.Henrik M. Peperkorn, Julia E. Diemer, Georg W. Alpers & Andreas Mühlberger - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Why are dreams interesting for philosophers? The example of minimal phenomenal selfhood, plus an agenda for future research.Thomas Metzinger - 2013 - Frontiers in Psychology 4:746.
    This metatheoretical paper develops a list of new research targets by exploring particularly promising interdisciplinary contact points between empirical dream research and philosophy of mind. The central example is the MPS-problem. It is constituted by the epistemic goal of conceptually isolating and empirically grounding the phenomenal property of “minimal phenomenal selfhood,” which refers to the simplest form of self-consciousness. In order to precisely describe MPS, one must focus on those conditions that are not only causally enabling, but strictly necessary to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Can you tickle yourself if you swap bodies with someone else?George Van Doorn, Jakob Hohwy & Mark Symmons - 2014 - Consciousness and Cognition 23:1-11.
    The effect of the body transfer illusion on the perceived strength of self- and externally-generated “tickle” sensations was investigated. As expected, externally generated movement produced significantly higher ratings of tickliness than those associated with self-generated movements. Surprisingly, the body transfer illusion had no influence on the ratings of tickliness, suggesting that highly surprising, and therefore hard to predict, experiences of body image and first-person perspective do not abolish the attenuation of tickle sensations. In addition, evidence was found that a version (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Spatial limits on the nonvisual self-touch illusion and the visual rubber hand illusion: Subjective experience of the illusion and proprioceptive drift.Anne M. Aimola Davies, Rebekah C. White & Martin Davies - 2013 - Consciousness and Cognition 22 (2):613-636.
    The nonvisual self-touch rubber hand paradigm elicits the compelling illusion that one is touching one’s own hand even though the two hands are not in contact. In four experiments, we investigated spatial limits of distance and alignment on the nonvisual self-touch illusion and the well-known visual rubber hand illusion. Common procedures and common assessment methods were used. Subjective experience of the illusion was assessed by agreement ratings for statements on a questionnaire and time of illusion onset. The nonvisual self-touch illusion (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Active and passive-touch during interpersonal multisensory stimulation change self–other boundaries.Ana Tajadura-Jiménez, Ludovica Lorusso & Manos Tsakiris - 2013 - Consciousness and Cognition 22 (4):1352-1360.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Developing the Sense of Agency Rating Scale (SOARS): An empirical measure of agency disruption in hypnosis.Vince Polito, Amanda J. Barnier & Erik Z. Woody - 2013 - Consciousness and Cognition 22 (3):684-696.
    Two experiments report on the construction of the Sense of Agency Rating Scale (SOARS), a new measure for quantifying alterations to agency. In Experiment 1, 370 participants completed a preliminary version of the scale following hypnosis. Factor analysis revealed two underlying factors: Involuntariness and Effortlessness. In Experiment 2, this two factor structure was confirmed in a sample of 113 low, medium and high hypnotisable participants. The two factors, Involuntariness and Effortlessness, correlated significantly with hypnotisability and pass rates for ideomotor, challenge (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Merging second-person and first-person neuroscience.Matthew R. Longo & Manos Tsakiris - 2013 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (4):429-430.
    Schilbach et al. contrast second-person and third-person approaches to social neuroscience. We discuss relations between second-person and first-person approaches, arguing that they cannot be studied in isolation. Contingency is central for converging first- and second-person approaches. Studies of embodiment show how contingencies scaffold first-person perspective and how the transition from a third- to a second-person perspective fundamentally involves first-person contributions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The person in the mirror: using the enfacement illusion to investigate the experiential structure of self-identification.Manos Tsakiris Ana Tajadura-Jiménez, Matthew R. Longo, Rosie Coleman - 2012 - Consciousness and Cognition 21 (4):1725.
    How do we acquire a mental representation of our own face? Recently, synchronous, but not asynchronous, interpersonal multisensory stimulation between one’s own and another person’s face has been used to evoke changes in self-identification . We investigated the conscious experience of these changes with principal component analyses that revealed that while the conscious experience during synchronous IMS focused on resemblance and similarity with the other’s face, during asynchronous IMS it focused on multisensory stimulation. Analyses of the identified common factor structure (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Embodiment, ownership and disownership.Frédérique de Vignemont - 2011 - Consciousness and Cognition 20 (1):1-12.
    There are two main pathways to investigate the sense of body ownership, (i) through the study of the conditions of embodiment for an object to be experienced as one's own and (ii) through the analysis of the deficits in patients who experience a body part as alien. Here, I propose that E is embodied if some properties of E are processed in the same way as the properties of one's body. However, one must distinguish among different types of embodiment, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Experiencing ownership over a dark-skinned body reduces implicit racial bias.Lara Maister, Natalie Sebanz, Günther Knoblich & Manos Tsakiris - 2013 - Cognition 128 (2):170-178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Beyond the colour of my skin: How skin colour affects the sense of body-ownership.Harry Farmer, Ana Tajadura-Jiménez & Manos Tsakiris - 2012 - Consciousness and Cognition 21 (3):1242-1256.
    Multisensory stimulation has been shown to alter the sense of body-ownership. Given that perceived similarity between one’s own body and those of others is crucial for social cognition, we investigated whether multisensory stimulation can lead participants to experience ownership over a hand of different skin colour. Results from two studies using introspective, behavioural and physiological methods show that, following synchronous visuotactile stimulation, participants can experience body-ownership over hands that seem to belong to a different racial group. Interestingly, a baseline measure (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The mark of bodily ownership.F. de Vignemont - 2013 - Analysis 73 (4):643-651.
    I am aware that this hand is my own. But is the sense of ownership of my hand manifested to me in a more primitive form than judgements? On the deflationary view recently defended by Martin and Bermúdez in their works, the sense of bodily ownership has no counterpart at the experiential level. Here I present a series of cases that the deflationary account cannot easily accommodate, including belief-independent illusions of ownership and experiences of disownership despite the presence of bodily (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Searching for the neural realizers of ownership unity.Rex Welshon - 2013 - Philosophical Psychology 26 (6):839 - 862.
    An argument is developed for the conclusion that certain neurological conditions and disorders are directly relevant for understanding the self?'s embodiment and the ownership of conscious experience enjoyed by such an embodied self. Since these neurological conditions and disorders provide evidence that there can be shifts of, and compromises to, ownership, they help identify neural substrates and realizers of such ownership. However, even if recent neuroimaging and neuropsychological nominees for neural substrates of ownership unity are core realizers of ownership, they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Two hands are better than one: A new assessment method and a new interpretation of the non-visual illusion of self-touch.Rebekah C. White, Anne M. Aimola Davies & Martin Davies - 2011 - Consciousness and Cognition 20 (3):956-964.
    A simple experimental paradigm creates the powerful illusion that one is touching one’s own hand even when the two hands are separated by 15 cm. The participant uses her right hand to administer stimulation to a prosthetic hand while the Examiner provides identical stimulation to the participant’s receptive left hand. Change in felt position of the receptive hand toward the prosthetic hand has previously led to the interpretation that the participant experiences self-touch at the location of the prosthetic hand, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Inverse effectiveness, multisensory integration, and the bodily self: Some statistical considerations.Nicholas P. Holmes - 2009 - Consciousness and Cognition 18 (3):762-765.
    A recent report in Consciousness and Cognition provided evidence from a study of the rubber hand illusion that supports the multisensory principle of inverse effectiveness . I describe two methods of assessing the principle of inverse effectiveness , and discuss how the post-hoc method is affected by the statistical artefact of ‘regression towards the mean’. I identify several cases where this artefact may have affected particular conclusions about the PoIE, and relate these to the historical origins of ‘regression towards the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Body-extension versus body-incorporation: Is there a need for a body-model? [REVIEW]Helena De Preester & Manos Tsakiris - 2009 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8 (3):307-319.
    This paper investigates the role of a pre-existing body-model that is an enabling constraint for the incorporation of objects into the body. This body-model is also a basis for the distinction between body extensions (e.g., in the case of tool-use) and incorporation (e.g., in the case of successful prosthesis use). It is argued that, in the case of incorporation, changes in the sense of body-ownership involve a reorganization of the body-model, whereas extension of the body with tools does not involve (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • The person in the mirror: Using the enfacement illusion to investigate the experiential structure of self-identification.Ana Tajadura-Jiménez, Matthew R. Longo, Rosie Coleman & Manos Tsakiris - 2012 - Consciousness and Cognition 21 (4):1725-1738.
    How do we acquire a mental representation of our own face? Recently, synchronous, but not asynchronous, interpersonal multisensory stimulation between one’s own and another person’s face has been used to evoke changes in self-identification. We investigated the conscious experience of these changes with principal component analyses that revealed that while the conscious experience during synchronous IMS focused on resemblance and similarity with the other’s face, during asynchronous IMS it focused on multisensory stimulation. Analyses of the identified common factor structure revealed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Bodily sense and structural content.Błażej Skrzypulec - 2023 - Synthese 202 (5):1-21.
    Bodily awareness seems to present the body as a topologically connected whole, composed of many parts. In consequence, the source of topological and mereological content of bodily awareness comes into question. In particular, it may be asked whether (a) such content is provided by the bodily sense, i.e., sensory mechanisms which, like proprioception, presents the body “from the inside,” or (b) it is a product of “exteroceptive” elements of bodily awareness, which represents the body “from the outside” in a similar (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Owning a virtual body entails owning the value of its actions in a detection-of-deception procedure.Maria Pyasik & Lorenzo Pia - 2021 - Cognition 212 (C):104693.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Immersive Virtual Reality and Virtual Embodiment for Pain Relief.Marta Matamala-Gomez, Tony Donegan, Sara Bottiroli, Giorgio Sandrini, Maria V. Sanchez-Vives & Cristina Tassorelli - 2019 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 13.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Multisensory stimulation with other-race faces and the reduction of racial prejudice.Alejandro J. Estudillo & Markus Bindemann - 2016 - Consciousness and Cognition 42:325-339.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Timing disownership experiences in the rubber hand illusion.Lane Timothy - 2017 - Cognitive Research: Principles and Implications 2 (4):1-14.
    Some investigators of the rubber hand illusion (RHI) have suggested that when standard RHI induction procedures are employed, if the rubber hand is experienced by participants as owned, their corresponding biological hands are experienced as disowned. Others have demurred: drawing upon a variety of experimental data and conceptual considerations, they infer that experience of the RHI might include the experience of a supernumerary limb, but that experienced disownership of biological hands does not occur. Indeed, some investigators even categorically deny that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The ‘not-so-strange’ body in the mirror: A principal components analysis of direct and mirror self-observation.Paul M. Jenkinson & Catherine Preston - 2017 - Consciousness and Cognition 48:262-272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Sliding perspectives: dissociating ownership from self-location during full body illusions in virtual reality.Antonella Maselli & Mel Slater - 2014 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Minimal self-models and the free energy principle.Jakub Limanowski & Felix Blankenburg - 2013 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Mental Activity & the Sense of Ownership.Adrian Alsmith - 2015 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6 (4):881-896.
    I introduce and defend the notion of a cognitive account of the sense of ownership. A cognitive account of the sense of ownership holds that one experiences something as one's own only if one thinks of something as one's own. By contrast, a phenomenal account of the sense of ownership holds that one can experience something as one's own without thinking about anything as one's own. I argue that we have no reason to favour phenomenal accounts over cognitive accounts, that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Movement under uncertainty: The effects of the rubber-hand illusion vary along the nonclinical autism spectrum.Colin Palmer, Bryan Paton, Jakob Hohwy & Peter Enticott - forthcoming - Neuropsychologia.
    Recent research has begun to investigate sensory processing in relation to nonclinical variation in traits associated with the autism spectrum disorders (ASD). We propose that existing accounts of autistic perception can be augmented by considering a role for individual differences in top-down expectations for the precision of sensory input, related to the processing of state-dependent levels of uncertainty. We therefore examined ASD-like traits in relation to the rubber-hand illusion: an experimental paradigm that typically elicits crossmodal integration of visual, tactile, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Technology and the Body: the (Im)Possibilities of Re-embodiment. [REVIEW]Helena De Preester - 2011 - Foundations of Science 16 (2-3):119-137.
    This article argues for a more rigorous distinction between body extensions on the one hand and incorporation of non-bodily objects into the body on the other hand. Real re-embodiment would be a matter of taking things (most often technologies) into the body, i.e. of incorporation of non-bodily items into the body. This, however, is a difficult process often limited by a number of conditions of possibility that are absent in the case of ‘mere’ body extensions. Three categories are discussed: limb (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • The Reflected Face as a Mask of the Self: An Appraisal of the Psychological and Neuroscientific Research About Self-face Recognition.Gabriele Volpara, Andrea Nani & Franco Cauda - 2022 - Topoi 41 (4):715-730.
    This study reviews research about the recognition of one’s own face and discusses scientific techniques to investigate differences in brain activation when looking at familiar faces compared to unfamiliar ones. Our analysis highlights how people do not possess a perception of their own face that corresponds precisely to reality, and how the awareness of one’s face can also be modulated by means of the enfacement illusion. This illusion allows one to maintain a sense of self at the expense of a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Relationship Between Referral of Touch and the Feeling of Ownership in the Rubber Hand Illusion.Arran T. Reader, Victoria S. Trifonova & H. Henrik Ehrsson - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    The rubber hand illusion is one of the most commonly used paradigms to examine the sense of body ownership. Touches are synchronously applied to the real hand, hidden from view, and a false hand in an anatomically congruent position. During the illusion one may perceive that the feeling of touch arises from the false hand, and that the false hand is one's own. The relationship between referral of touch and body ownership in the illusion is unclear, and some articles average (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Embodied cognition: So flexible as to be “disembodied”?Francesco Ianì - 2021 - Consciousness and Cognition 88 (C):103075.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Changing Body Representation Through Full Body Ownership Illusions Might Foster Motor Rehabilitation Outcome in Patients With Stroke.Marta Matamala-Gomez, Clelia Malighetti, Pietro Cipresso, Elisa Pedroli, Olivia Realdon, Fabrizia Mantovani & Giuseppe Riva - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Active control as evidence in favor of sense of ownership in the moving Virtual Hand Illusion.Victòria Brugada-Ramentol, Ivar Clemens & Gonzalo G. de Polavieja - 2019 - Consciousness and Cognition 71:123-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Subjective embodiment during the rubber hand illusion predicts severity of premonitory sensations and tics in Tourette Syndrome.Charlotte L. Rae, Dennis E. O. Larsson, Jessica A. Eccles, Jamie Ward & Hugo D. Critchley - 2018 - Consciousness and Cognition 65 (C):368-377.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation