Switch to: References

Citations of:

Word and Object

Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press (1960)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Translation and Relevance: Cognition and Context.Kirsten Malmkjaer - 1992 - Mind and Language 7 (3):298-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Second-generation AI theories of learning.David Kirsh - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):658-659.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Strict implication, supervenience, and physicalism.Robert Kirk - 1996 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (2):244-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Myślenie za pomocą reprezentacji zewnętrznych.David Kirsh - 2014 - Avant: Trends in Interdisciplinary Studies 5 (1):94-125.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The primate behavioral continuum: What are its limits?Barbara J. King - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):527-528.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Context effects: Pervasiveness and analysis.Donald L. King - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):570-570.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Reconsideration of the Relation Between Kuhnian Incommensurability and Translation.Vasso Kindi - 2017 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 31 (4):397-414.
    Up to the introduction of the term and concept of incommensurability by T. S. Kuhn and P. K. Feyerabend in the early 1960s, scientific texts were supposed to pose no problem as regards their translation, unlike literature, which was thought very difficult to translate. After the introduction of the term, translation of scientific language became equally problematic because, due to conceptual and perceptual incommensurability, there was no common observation basis to ground linguistic equivalences between languages of incommensurable paradigms. This article (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Psychophysics: Plus ça change ….Peter R. Killeen - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):569-569.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fictionalism about musical works.Anton Killin - 2018 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 48 (2):266-291.
    The debate concerning the ontological status of musical works is perhaps the most animated debate in contemporary analytic philosophy of music. In my view, progress requires a piecemeal approach. So in this article I hone in on one particular musical work concept – that of the classical Western art musical work; that is, the work concept that regulates classical art-musical practice. I defend a fictionalist analysis – a strategy recently suggested by Andrew Kania as potentially fruitful – and I develop (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Whorf and Wittgenstein. Language, world view and argumentation.M. Kienpointner - 1996 - Argumentation 10 (4):475-494.
    Whorf and Wittgenstein are perhaps the most famous names in linguistics and philosophy associated with the assumption that language plays a decisive role in shaping our view of reality. After a critical discussion of Whorf's linguistic relativity principle I conclude that it is not language as a system, but the use of language according to the rules of language games which connects language thought and world view, especially if some particular usage becomes the commonly accepted norm. This traditional norm also (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the aim of the theory of verisimilitude.I. A. Kieseppä - 1996 - Synthese 107 (3):421 - 438.
    J. P. Z. Bonilla's methodological approach to truthlikeness is evaluated critically. On a more general level, various senses in which the theory of truthlikeness could be seen as a theory concerned with methodology are distinguished, and it is argued that providing speical sciences with methodological tools is unrealistic as an aim of the theory of verisimilitude. Rather, when developing this theory, one should rest contnet with the more modest aim of conceptual analysis, or of providing explications for the relational concept (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Natural kinds, natural history and ecology.A. Ross Kiester - 1980 - Synthese 43 (2):331 - 342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Two concepts of concept.Muhammad ali KhAlidi - 1995 - Mind and Language 10 (4):402-22.
    Two main theories of concepts have emerged in the recent psychological literature: the Prototype Theory (which considers concepts to be self-contained lists of features) and the Theory Theory (which conceives of them as being embedded within larger theoretical networks). Experiments supporting the first theory usually differ substantially from those supporting the second, which suggests that these the· ories may be operating at different levels of explanation and dealing with different entities. A convergence is proposed between the Theory Theory and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Minds and Language: Social Cognition, Social Interaction and the Acquisition of Language.Kevin Durkin - 1987 - Mind and Language 2 (2):105-140.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Structuralism and the identity of indiscernibles.Jeffrey Ketland - 2006 - Analysis 66 (4):303-315.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Identity and indiscernibility.Jeffrey Ketland - 2011 - Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (2):171-185.
    The notion of strict identity is sometimes given an explicit second-order definition: objects with all the same properties are identical. Here, a somewhat different problem is raised: Under what conditions is the identity relation on the domain of a structure first-order definable? A structure may have objects that are distinct, but indiscernible by the strongest means of discerning them given the language (the indiscernibility formula). Here a number of results concerning the indiscernibility formula, and the definability of identity, are collected (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Quine on Objects: Realism or Anti-Realism?Antti Keskinen - 2012 - Theoria 78 (2):128-145.
    W. V. Quine describes himself as a “robust realist” about physical objects in the external world. This realism about objects is due to Quine's naturalism. On the other hand, Quine's naturalistic epistemology involves a conception of objects as posits that we introduce in our theories about the world. This conception of objects can be seen as anti-realist rather than realist. In this article, I discuss the questions whether there is a tension between Quine's realism and his epistemological conception of objects, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The communication desideratum and theories of indexical reference.Jonas Åkerman - 2015 - Mind and Language 30 (4):474–499.
    According to the communication desideratum (CD), a notion of semantic content must be adequately related to communication. In the recent debate on indexical reference, (CD) has been invoked in arguments against the view that intentions determine the semantic content of indexicals and demonstratives (intentionalism). In this paper, I argue that the interpretations of (CD) that these arguments rely on are questionable, and suggest an alternative interpretation, which is compatible with (strong) intentionalism. Moreover, I suggest an approach that combines elements of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On the de-naturalization of epistemology.András Kertész - 2002 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 33 (2):269-288.
    Starting from an overview of approaches to naturalized epistemology, the paper shows, firstly, that Quine's programme yields a sceptical paradox. This means that Quine's attempt to defeat scepticism itself yields a rather strong argument for scepticism and thus against his own programme of naturalized epistemology. Secondly, it is shown that this paradox can be solved by an approach called reflexive-heuristic naturalism. Finally, the paper also raises some fundamental problems which the solution proposed has to leave open.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Ethics and EBM: acknowledging bias, accepting difference and embracing politics.Ian Kerridge - 2010 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 16 (2):365-373.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Disagreement, Democracy, and the Goals of Science: Is a Normative Philosophy of Science Possible, If Ethical Inquiry Is Not?Arnon Keren - 2011 - Philosophy 86 (4):525-544.
    W.V.Quine and Philip Kitcher have both developed naturalistic approaches to the philosophy of science which are partially based on a skeptical view about the possibility of rational inquiry into certain questions of value. Nonetheless, both Quine and Kitcher do not wish to give up on the normative dimension of the philosophy of science. I argue that Kitcher's recent argument against the specification of the goal of science in terms of truth raises a problem for Quine's account of the normative dimensions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Social traits, self-observations, and other hypothetical constructs.Douglas T. Kenrick & Richard C. Keefe - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):561.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On 'Average'.Christopher Kennedy & Jason Stanley - 2009 - Mind 118 (471):583 - 646.
    This article investigates the semantics of sentences that express numerical averages, focusing initially on cases such as 'The average American has 2.3 children'. Such sentences have been used both by linguists and philosophers to argue for a disjuncture between semantics and ontology. For example, Noam Chomsky and Norbert Hornstein have used them to provide evidence against the hypothesis that natural language semantics includes a reference relation holding between words and objects in the world, whereas metaphysicians such as Joseph Melia and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Color, context, and compositionality.Christopher Kennedy & Louise Mcnally - 2010 - Synthese 174 (1):79-98.
    Color adjectives have played a central role in work on language typology and variation, but there has been relatively little investigation of their meanings by researchers in formal semantics. This is surprising given the fact that color terms have been at the center of debates in the philosophy of language over foundational questions, in particular whether the idea of a compositional, truth-conditional theory of natural language semantics is even coherent. The challenge presented by color terms is articulated in detail in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Quine: The challenge of naturalism.Gary Kemp - 2010 - European Journal of Philosophy 18 (2):283-295.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Pushing Wittgenstein and Quine Closer Together.Gary Kemp - 2014 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 2 (10).
    As against the view represented here by Peter Hacker and John Canfield, I urge that the philosophies of Quine and Wittgenstein can be reconciled. Both replace the orthodox view of language as resting on reference: Quine with the notion of linguistic disposition, Wittgenstein with the notions of grammar and forms of life. I argue that Wittgenstein's insistence, in the rule-following discussion, that at bottom these are matters of practice, of ‘what we do’, is not only compatible in a rough sort (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Quine: Underdetermination and Naturalistic Metaphysics.Gary Kemp - 2015 - Philosophical Topics 43 (1-2):179-188.
    Quine’s naturalism has no room for a point of view outside science from which one might criticize science, or a transcendental point of view from which one could ask questions about the adequacy of science with respect to reality (‘as it is in itself ’). Adrian Moore sniffs out some genuine tensions in this, arguing in effect that Quine is forced by his own views to admit those sorts of questions as legitimate. I venture that Quine, even if he would (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • ∈ : Formal concepts in a material world truthmaking and exemplification as types of determination.Philipp Keller - 2007 - Dissertation, University of Geneva
    In the first part ("Determination"), I consider different notions of determination, contrast and compare modal with non-modal accounts and then defend two a-modality theses concerning essence and supervenience. I argue, first, that essence is a a-modal notion, i.e. not usefully analysed in terms of metaphysical modality, and then, contra Kit Fine, that essential properties can be exemplified contingently. I argue, second, that supervenience is also an a-modal notion, and that it should be analysed in terms of constitution relations between properties. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Clarity, generality, and efficiency in models of learning: Wringing the MOP.Kevin T. Kelly - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):657-658.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Introduction: Vagueness and Ontology.Geert Keil - 2013 - Metaphysica 14 (2):149-164.
    The article introduces a special issue of the journal _Metaphysica_ on vagueness and ontology. The conventional view has it that all vagueness is semantic or representational. Russell, Dummett, Evans and Lewis, inter alia, have argued that the notion of “ontic” or “metaphysical” vagueness is not even intelligible. In recent years, a growing minority of philosophers have tried to make sense of the notion and have spelled it out in various ways. The article gives an overview and relates the idea of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Meaning Theory and Autistic Speakers.Kathrin Gluer & Peter Pagin - 2003 - Mind and Language 18 (1):23-51.
    Some theories of linguistic meaning, such as those of Paul Grice and David Lewis, make appeal to higher–order thoughts: thoughts about thoughts. Because of this, such theories run the risk of being empirically refuted by the existence of speakers who lack, completely or to a high degree, the capacity of thinking about thoughts. Research on autism during the past 15 years provides strong evidence for the existence of such speakers. Some persons with autism have linguistic abilities that qualify them as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Mental Magnitudes and Increments of Mental Magnitudes.Matthew Katz - 2013 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 4 (4):675-703.
    There is at present a lively debate in cognitive psychology concerning the origin of natural number concepts. At the center of this debate is the system of mental magnitudes, an innately given cognitive mechanism that represents cardinality and that performs a variety of arithmetical operations. Most participants in the debate argue that this system cannot be the sole source of natural number concepts, because they take it to represent cardinality approximately while natural number concepts are precise. In this paper, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Fodor's guide to cognitive psychology.Jerrold J. Katz - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):85-89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Issues Concerning a Nativist Theory of Numerical Knowledge.Karen Wynn - 1992 - Mind and Language 7 (4):367-381.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reading ‘On Denoting’ on its Centenary.David Kaplan - 2005 - Mind 114 (456):933-1003.
    Part 1 sets out the logical/semantical background to ‘On Denoting’, including an exposition of Russell's views in Principles of Mathematics, the role and justification of Frege's notorious Axiom V, and speculation about how the search for a solution to the Contradiction might have motivated a new treatment of denoting. Part 2 consists primarily of an extended analysis of Russell's views on knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description, in which I try to show that the discomfiture between Russell's semantical and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Hunger Hermeneutics.David M. Kaplan - 2020 - Topoi 40 (3):527-533.
    Hunger is both a natural and social phenomenon. On one hand, it is a natural, biological state that affects everyone, everywhere, in every historical time. On the other hand, our perceptions, attitudes, and experiences of hunger are far from uniform. We think about it differently in different contexts and settings depending on its causes and consequences. The same event—the same pangs, emptiness, and lack of energy associated with the desire for food—takes on different meanings depending on who is hungry, when, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A new problem for rules.Jeffrey Kaplan - 2023 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 107 (3):671-691.
    This paper presents a series of arguments aimed at showing that, for an important subclass of social rules—non‐summary rules—no adequate metaphysical account has been given, and it tentatively suggests that no such account can be given. The category of non‐summary rules is an important one, as it includes the rules of etiquette, fashion, chess, basketball, California state law, descriptive English grammar, and so on. This paper begins with behavioristic accounts of the conditions for the existence of such rules, and proceeds (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What makes cultural heredity unique? On action-types, intentionality and cooperation in imitation.Frank Kannetzky - 2007 - Mind and Language 22 (5):592–623.
    The exploration of the mechanisms of cultural heredity has often been regarded as the key to explicating human uniqueness. Particularly early imitative learning, which is explained as a kind of simulation that rests on the infant’s identification with other persons as intentional agents, has been stressed as the foundation of cumulative cultural transmission. But the question of what are the objects of this mechanism has not been given much attention. Although this is a pivotal point, it still remains obscure. I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Japanese Sound-Symbolism Facilitates Word Learning in English-Speaking Children.Katerina Kantartzis, Mutsumi Imai & Sotaro Kita - 2011 - Cognitive Science 35 (3):575-586.
    Sound-symbolism is the nonarbitrary link between the sound and meaning of a word. Japanese-speaking children performed better in a verb generalization task when they were taught novel sound-symbolic verbs, created based on existing Japanese sound-symbolic words, than novel nonsound-symbolic verbs (Imai, Kita, Nagumo, & Okada, 2008). A question remained as to whether the Japanese children had picked up regularities in the Japanese sound-symbolic lexicon or were sensitive to universal sound-symbolism. The present study aimed to provide support for the latter. In (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The elimination of de re formulas.Michael Kaminski - 1997 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 (4):411-422.
    It is shown that de re formulas are eliminable in the modal logic S5 extended with the axiom scheme □∃xφ ⊃ ∃x□φ.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Information Sources for Noun Learning.Edward Kako - 2005 - Cognitive Science 29 (2):223-260.
    Why are some words easier to learn than others? And what enables the eventual learning of the more difficult words? These questions were addressed for nouns using a paradigm in which adults were exposed to naturalistic maternal input that was manipulated to simulate access to several different information sources, both alone and in combination: observation of the extralinguistic contexts in which the target word was used, the words that co‐occurred with the target word, and the target word's syntactic context. Words (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Who shall be the arbiter of our intuitions?Daniel Kahneman - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):339-340.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Philosophical arguments, psychological experiments, and the problem of consistency.D. Kahneman - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):253-254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Implications of Fodor' methodological solipsism for psychological theories.Peter W. Jusczyk & Bruce Earhard - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):84-85.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward preparing students for change: A critical discussion of the contribution of the history of physics in physics teaching.Walter Jung - 1994 - Science & Education 3 (2):99-130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Toward a social history of qualitative research.Gordana Jovanović - 2011 - History of the Human Sciences 24 (2):1-27.
    There are plausible academic as well as social indicators that qualitative research has become an indispensable part of the methodological repertoire of the social sciences. Relying upon the tenets of the qualitative approach which require a priority of subject matter over method and a necessary socio-historical contextualization, I reconstruct some aspects of a social history that have shaped the quantitative—qualitative dichotomy and the quantitative imperative; these include modern individualism, monological rationality, manufacture operating on the grounds of common human labour, mechanics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The content of a representation also depends on the procedure interpreting it.A. K. Joshi - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):84-84.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Skepticism and psi: A personal view.Brian D. Josephson - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):594.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Inference to the best explanation is basic.John R. Josephson - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):477-478.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How to Power Encultured Minds.Vukov Joseph & Charles Lassiter - 2020 - Synthese 197:3507–3534.
    Cultural psychologists often describe the relationship between mind and culture as ‘dynamic.’ In light of this, we provide two desiderata that a theory about encultured minds ought to meet: the theory ought to reflect how cultural psychologists describe their own findings and it ought to be thoroughly naturalistic. We show that a realist theory of causal powers — which holds that powers are causally-efficacious and empirically-discoverable — fits the bill. After an introduction to the major concepts in cultural psychology and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations