Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Forgiveness as an Approach to the History of Philosophy.Yael Gazit - 2022 - Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 3 (1):147-169.
    In the past, Robert Brandom’s philosophy has provided fruitful grounds for the development of an approach to the history of philosophy. In A Spirit of Trust (2019), however, this approach takes a new form; one that corresponds to a shift of focus in Brandom’s philosophy, from his earlier inferentialism to its later developments in the thesis of rational recollection. This article aims to elucidate and explicate this new approach, which Brandom refers to as forgiveness. By looking into the thesis of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The case for cultural theory: Reply to Friedman.Richard J. Ellis - 1993 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 7 (1):81-128.
    In an essay in these pages, Jeffrey Friedman charged that Cultural Theory obscures the unity and uniqueness of modern egalitarian individualism; reduces culture to society; ignores history; is only applicable to contemporary, Western politics; provides an unsatisfactory account of preference formation and preference change; and leaves no place for the vitally important debate over what we should prefer. Although some of Friedman's criticisms stem from a misreading or strained reading of Cultural Theory, others raise vitally important questions not only about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What is critical history of philosophy?Stella Sandford - forthcoming - Southern Journal of Philosophy.
    In the past half‐century critical historiographies of philosophy have challenged the exclusionist Eurocentric and masculinist presumptions of “history of philosophy,” and we have witnessed the multiplication of philosophical worlds in the relation of indigenous to Western scholarship and in critical philosophical anthropologies. Does this mean that there is, or can be, no unity to the history of philosophy? In this article, I argue that these challenges are not incompatible with our thinking the unity of the history of philosophy, so long (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Practical Origins of Ideas: Genealogy as Conceptual Reverse-Engineering (Open Access).Matthieu Queloz - 2021 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Why did such highly abstract ideas as truth, knowledge, or justice become so important to us? What was the point of coming to think in these terms? This book presents a philosophical method designed to answer such questions: the method of pragmatic genealogy. Pragmatic genealogies are partly fictional, partly historical narratives exploring what might have driven us to develop certain ideas in order to discover what these do for us. The book uncovers an under-appreciated tradition of pragmatic genealogy which cuts (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • III. Some Problems in the Analysis of Political Thought and Action.Quentin Skinner - 1974 - Political Theory 2 (3):277-303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Some problems in the analysis of political thought and action.Quentin Skinner - 1974 - Political Theory 2 (3):277-303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Der 'intentionale fehlschluß' — ein dogma?Lutz Danneberg & Hans-Harald Müller - 1983 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 14 (1):103-137.
    Our examination of the controversy surrounding the intentionalist conception of textual interpretation shows that the critics of this approach to questions of meaning and interpretation have so far failed to prove their case. The standard objections to intentionalism, on grounds of logical or empirical fallacy, cannot be maintained. We reconstruct the objections which have been raised in the literature against the intentional conception and discuss them as criticism of a conception hold to be inadequate with respect to the problem of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mind and method in the history of ideas.Mark Bevir - 1997 - History and Theory 36 (2):167–189.
    J. G. A. Pocock and Quentin Skinner have led a recent onslaught on the alleged "myth of coherence" in the history of ideas. But their criticisms depend on mistaken views of the nature of mind: respectively, a form of social constructionism, and a focus on illocutionary intentions at the expense of beliefs. An investigation of the coherence constraints that do operate on our ascriptions of belief shows historians should adopt a presumption of coherence, concern themselves with coherence, and proceed to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On the meaning of progress and providence in the fourth century.Christopher J. Berry - 1977 - Heythrop Journal 18 (3):257–270.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Meaning of Progress and Providence in the Fourth Century.Christopher J. Berry - 1977 - Heythrop Journal 18 (3):257-270.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Framed in the Public Sphere: Tools for the Conceptual History of “Applied Science” — A Review Paper.Robert Bud - 2013 - History of Science 51 (4):413-433.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Heródoto y Protágoras: una recepción polémica de los conceptos de νόμος y φύσις.Sergio Barrionuevo - 2018 - Anales Del Seminario de Historia de la Filosofía 35 (2):303-322.
    The objective of this paper is to identify, from a historical perspective, the presence of elements of the protagorean thought in the Herodotus’ Histories. I realize an analysis of the passages in which Herodotus refers to νόμος and φύσις, which constitute a conceptual antithesis within the framework of the fifth century a.C. From this analysis I will try to show that Herodotus retakes the intellectual discussions of the fifth century BC, but makes a controversial reception of these concepts highlighting the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Metaphysical and Historical Claims in The Birth of Tragedy.Katherine Harloe - 2008 - In Manuel Dries (ed.), Nietzsche on Time and History. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Rethinking Politicisation.Kari Palonen, Claudia Wiesner, Veith Selk, Niilo Kauppi, Hans-Jörg-Trenz, Claire Dupuy, Virginie Van Ingelgom & Philip Liste - 2019 - Contemporary Political Theory 18 (2):248-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theorizing the Normative Significance of Critical Histories for International Law.Damian Cueni & Matthieu Queloz - 2022 - Journal of the History of International Law 24 (4):561-587.
    Though recent years have seen a proliferation of critical histories of international law, their normative significance remains under-theorized, especially from the perspective of general readers rather than writers of such histories. How do critical histories of international law acquire their normative significance? And how should one react to them? We distinguish three ways in which critical histories can be normatively significant: (i) by undermining the overt or covert conceptions of history embedded within present practices in support of their authority; (ii) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Principle of Plenitude and Natural Theology in Nineteenth-Century Britain.Richard R. Yeo - 1986 - British Journal for the History of Science 19 (3):263-282.
    In his classic study,The Great Chain of Being, Arthur Lovejoy delineated a complex set of concepts and assumptions which referred to the perfection of God and the fullness of creation. In attempting to distil the basic or ‘unit idea’ which constituted this pattern of thought, he focused on the assumption that ‘the universe is aplenum formarumin which the range of conceivable diversity ofkindsof living things is exhaustively exemplified’. He called this the ‘principle of plenitude’. Lovejoy argued that this idea implied (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is a Penny a Month a Basic Income? A Historiography of the Concept of a Threshold in Basic Income: Winner of the 2021 BIS essay contest.Toru Yamamori - 2022 - Basic Income Studies 17 (1):29-51.
    Does a penny per month constitute a Basic Income? Were that penny to be paid individually, universally, and unconditionally, the answer would be ‘yes’, following the definition of Basic Income given by some of its leading advocates, be it organisations like the Basic Income Earth Network or prominent scholars such as Philippe Van Parijs. Some might be puzzled as to how this could be ‘a capitalist road to communism’, or give us ‘freedom as the power to say no’, both of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Carl Schmitt, amigo de Weimar. Notas en torno a la Verfassungslehre como teoría y doctrina de la constitución.Tomás Wieczorek - 2022 - Isonomía. Revista de Teoría y Filosofía Del Derecho 56.
    El artículo aborda la Teoría de la Constitución de Carl Schmitt, atendiendo a su doble acepción de teoría general de la constitución moderna y cuerpo de doctrina acerca de la constitución de Weimar. El primer apartado presenta la sistemática de la teoría positiva de la constitución moderna, reponiendo sus dos elementos estructurantes: la forma política resultante de la aplicación de los principios político-formales de identidad y representación, y las formas de legislación y gobierno propias del Estado de derecho burgués. La (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Darwin’s missing links.John S. Warren - 2017 - History of European Ideas 43 (8):929-1001.
    ABSTRACTThe historical process underlying Darwin’s Origin of Species did not play a significant role in the early editions of the book, in spite of the particular inductivist scientific methodology it espoused. Darwin’s masterpiece did not adequately provide his sources or the historical perspective many contemporary critics expected. Later editions yielded the ‘Historical Sketch’ lacking in the earlier editions, but only under critical pressure. Notwithstanding the sources he provided, Darwin presented the Origin as an ‘abstract’ in order to avoid giving sources; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Histories and freedom of the present: Foucault and Skinner.Naja Vucina, Claus Drejer & Peter Triantafillou - 2011 - History of the Human Sciences 24 (5):0952695111415176.
    This article compares the ways in which Michel Foucault’s and Quentin Skinner’s historical analyses seek to unsettle the limits on present forms of freedom. We do so by comparing their ways of analysing discourse, rationality and agency. The two authors differ significantly in the ways they deal with these three phenomena. The most significant difference lies in their ways of addressing agency and its relationship to power. Notwithstanding these differences, the historical analyses of both authors seek to problematize the ways (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Early Modern Protestant Virtuosos and Scientists: Some Comments.Kaspar von Greyerz - 2016 - Zygon 51 (3):698-717.
    The following essay is divided in three parts. First, while sharing in principle Harrison's hypothesis of an affinity between the sixteenth‐century Reformation and early modern science, it questions the connection between the latter and the Weberian “disenchantment of the world.” Second, it suggests a broader group of possible actors than that envisaged by Harrison in referring to virtuoso collectors and their cabinets of curiosities who are rather marginalized in Harrison's narrative. And third, it highlights (in agreement with Harrison) the physico‐theology (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gadamer’s Logic of Question and Answer and the Difference Between the History of Philosophy and the History of Ideas.David Vessey - 2014 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 8 (3):360-379.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Corruption as systemic political decay.Camila Vergara - 2021 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 47 (3):322-346.
    By offering an analysis of different conceptions of corruption connected to the political regime and contingency in which they developed, the article retrieves a systemic meaning of political corruption. Through the works of Plato, Aristotle, Polybius and Machiavelli, it reconstructs a dimension of political corruption particular to popular governments and also engages with recent neo-republican and institutionalist attempts at redefining political corruption. The article concludes that we still lack a proper conception of systemic corruption comparable to the one of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Corruption as systemic political decay.Camila Vergara - 2021 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 47 (3):322-346.
    By offering an analysis of different conceptions of corruption connected to the political regime and contingency in which they developed, the article retrieves a systemic meaning of political corruption. Through the works of Plato, Aristotle, Polybius and Machiavelli, it reconstructs a dimension of political corruption particular to popular governments and also engages with recent neo-republican and institutionalist attempts at redefining political corruption. The article concludes that we still lack a proper conception of systemic corruption comparable to the one of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Working Out Marx: Marxism and the End of the Work Society.Frédéric Vandenberghe - 2002 - Thesis Eleven 69 (1):21-46.
    Reading the Communist Manifesto against the contemporary background of massive unemployment, the author argues that Marx's theory of work is no longer adequate to tackle the problem of `workers without work' and suggests that it has to be reformulated in such a way that its normative intuitions and its critical impulses can be maintained. In the first part, he presents a philosophical critique of Marxism that is inspired by Jürgen Habermas and Hannah Arendt. In the second part, he presents a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reading as a source of knowledge.René van Woudenberg - 2021 - Synthese 198 (1):723-742.
    This paper argues that reading is a source of knowledge. Epistemologists have virtually ignored reading as a source of knowledge. This paper argues, first, that reading is not to be equated with attending to testimony, and second that it cannot be reduced to perception. Next an analysis of reading is offered and the source of knowledge that reading is further delineated. Finally it is argued that the source that reading is, can be both transmissive and generative, is non-basic, once was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Working Out Marx: Marxism and the End of the Work Society.Frédéric Vandenberghe - 2002 - Thesis Eleven 69 (1):21-46.
    Reading the Communist Manifesto against the contemporary background of massive unemployment, the author argues that Marx's theory of work is no longer adequate to tackle the problem of `workers without work' and suggests that it has to be reformulated in such a way that its normative intuitions and its critical impulses can be maintained. In the first part, he presents a philosophical critique of Marxism that is inspired by Jürgen Habermas and Hannah Arendt. In the second part, he presents a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Philosophy of History and History of Philosophy of Science.Thomas Uebel - 2017 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 7 (1):1-30.
    hilosophy of history and history of philosophy of science make for an interesting case of “mutual containment”: the former is an object of inquiry for the latter, and the latter is subject to the demands of the former. This article discusses a seminal turn in past philosophy of history with an eye to the practice of historians of philosophy of science. The narrative turn by Danto and Mink represents both a liberation for historians and a new challenge to the objectivity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Performativity and the Intellectual Historian's Re-enactment of Written Works.Colin Tyler - 2009 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 3 (2):167-186.
    This article develops and defends a performative conception of historical re-enactment as a fruitful method by which intellectual historians can interpret texts. Specifically, it argues that, in order to understand properly any given text, the intellectual historian should re-enact the performative activities of the writer of that text. The first section analyses one of the most influential and powerful theories of historical re-enactment, namely that found in the later writings of Robin George Collingwood. Drawing on Wittgenstein's theory of family resemblances, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Teaching Subtlety of Thought: The Lessons of `Contextualism'. [REVIEW]Stephen Turner - 2001 - Argumentation 15 (1):77-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Meaning without Theory.Stephen Turner - 2011 - Journal of the Philosophy of History 5 (3):352-369.
    There is a core conflict between conventional ideas about “meaning“ and the phenomenon of meaning and meaning change in history. Conventional accounts are either atemporal or appeal to something fixed that bestows meaning, such as a rule or a convention. This produces familiar problems over change. Notions of rule and convention are metaphors for something tacit. They are unhelpful in accounting for change: there are no rule-givers or convenings in history. Meanings are in flux, and are part of a web (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Many approaches, but few arrivals: Merton and the columbia model of theory construction.Stephen Turner - 2009 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 39 (2):174-211.
    Robert Merton's essays on theories of the middle range and his essays on functional explanation and the structural approach are among the most influential in the history of sociology. But their import is a puzzle. He explicitly allied himself with some of the most extreme scientistic formalists and contributed to and endorsed the Columbia model of theory construction. But Merton never responded to criticisms by Ernest Nagel of his arguments or acknowledged the rivalry between Lazarsfeld and Herbert Simon, rarely cited (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Descriptive Accuracy in History: The Case of Narrative Explanations.Leonidas Tsilipakos - 2020 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 50 (4):283-312.
    This article discusses the issue of the conceptual accuracy of descriptions of social life, which, although fundamental for the social sciences, has in fact been neglected. I approach this task via an examination of Paul Roth’s recent work, which recapitulates reflection in analytic philosophy of history and sets out a view of the past as indeterminate until retrospectively constructed in historical narratives. I argue that Roth’s position embraces an overly restricted notion of historical significance and underestimates how anachronistic descriptions vitiate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Science, truth and history, Part I. Historiography, relativism and the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge.Nick Tosh - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37 (4):675-701.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Science, truth and history, part I. historiography, relativism and the sociology of scientific knowledge.Nick Tosh - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37 (4):675-701.
    Recently, many historians of science have chosen to present their historical narratives from the ‘actors’-eye view’. Scientific knowledge not available within the actors’ culture is not permitted to do explanatory work. Proponents of the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge purport to ground this historiography on epistemological relativism. I argue that they are making an unnecessary mistake: unnecessary because the historiographical genre in question can be defended on aesthetic and didactic grounds; and a mistake because the argument from relativism is in any (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Anachronism and retrospective explanation: in defence of a present-centred history of science.Nick Tosh - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (3):647-659.
    This paper defends the right of historians to make use of their knowledge of the remote consequences of past actions. In particular, it is argued that the disciplinary cohesion of the history of science relies crucially upon our ability to target, for further investigation, those past activities ancestral to modern science. The history of science is not limited to the study of those activities but it is structured around them. In this sense, the discipline is inherently ‘present-centred’: its boundaries are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Mysticism in Early Modern England.Liam Peter Temple - 2019 - Boydell & Brewer.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Review Article: Edmund Burke and the Importance of Context.Ben J. Taylor - 2010 - European Journal of Political Theory 9 (3):357-366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why spontaneity matters: Rosa Luxemburg and democracies of grief.Paulina Tambakaki - 2021 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 47 (1):83-101.
    The article seeks to explain why spontaneity, a concept that political theorists have given scant attention to, matters. It argues that it matters because it delivers a capacity for producing democratic change that is urgent to reflect on amidst a prevailing mood of grief over a democracy lost. To stimulate this reflection, the article engages with Rosa Luxemburg’s work, showing how her understanding of spontaneity as an initiative that delivers something for democracy lays the groundwork for a theoretical orientation that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards a reflexive intelligence of emerging sociology in France around 1900.Martin Strauss - 2021 - Revue de Synthèse 142 (3-4):516-579.
    Recent years have seen a proliferation of publications reconsidering the emergence of sociology in France. The present review discusses and compares three of these works: S. Mosbah-Natanson’s bibliometric study on the fashion of sociology around 1900 (2017a); Th. Hirsch’s history of the idea of social time from the Durkheimians to Les Annales (2016a); and M. Joly’s enquiry into a purported sociological revolution in France and Germany at around the same time (2017a). Pushing respectively for a sociological, a historical and an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Petrified Intelligence: Nature in Hegel’s Philosophy.Alison Stone - 2012 - SUNY Press.
    _A critical introduction to Hegel's metaphysics and philosophy of nature._.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Plus ça change: continuity in the theory and representation of monarchy in Dante and Bagehot.Glenn A. Steinberg - forthcoming - History of European Ideas.
    The constitutional monarchy of present-day Britain hardly seems the same sort of institution as fourteenth-century feudal kingdoms, but Dante’s Monarchia (c. 1313) and Walter Bagehot’s The English Constitution (1872) share fundamental assumptions about what the purpose and strengths of monarchy are. In the Monarchia, Dante lays out the essential attributes of monarchy that endure even today: authority, impartiality, and unity. Dante values and promotes monarchy as final arbiter of conflicts, sole just judge without cupidity, and unifying will. More than 550 (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Why and How Do I Write the History of Science?Roger Smith - 2013 - Science in Context 26 (4):611-625.
    I make a large claim for the intellectual and institutional centrality of the history of science as critical reason. The reality on the ground, of course, does not always exhibit this. I trace the vicissitudes of my own way of thought in relation to developments in the field, leading to an interest, first, in relating intellectual history (with its philosophical orientation) to mainstream (evidence based) history, and second, to finding a place for the human sciences in the history of science. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Thinking Through Things in Texts: A Seventeenth-Century Example.Olivia Smith - 2014 - Paragraph 37 (1):112-125.
    What is the cognitive role of things — sometimes but not always expressed as nouns — that appear in texts? What kind of literary affordances are the material furnishings that appear in a piece of literary writing? These questions are explored in this essay through the example of John Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding, a long work of literary philosophy that plays with the evolving conventions of its genre. Fusing methodologies borrowed from anthropology and linguistics, this essay reveals the extent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Morality and method in the work of Barrington Moore.Dennis Smith - 1984 - Theory and Society 13 (2):151-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does the history of psychology have a subject?Roger Smith - 1988 - History of the Human Sciences 1 (2):147-177.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The species problem and history. [REVIEW]Phillip R. Sloan - 2013 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 44 (2):237-241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Adam Ferguson and the Idea of Civil Society: Moral Science in the Scottish Enlightenment, by Craig Smith.Max Skjönsberg - 2019 - Intellectual History Review 29 (2):364-368.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wu Song’s Killing of His Sister-in-law: An Ethical Analysis.William Sin - 2018 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 17 (2):231-246.
    The Water Margin is a great Chinese classical novel; Wu Song’s 武松 killing of his sister-in-law, Pan Jinlian 潘金蓮, is one of the most popular episodes of the novel. It depicts Wu as the hero and defender of traditional values, and Pan as the adulterous woman. In contemporary discussion, there has been a dearth of ethical analyses regarding Wu’s killing of Pan. How should we judge the moral status of his action? Does the killing signify Wu Song’s ethical achievement or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mannheim's sociology of knowledge as a hermeneutic method.A. P. Simonds - 1975 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 3 (1):81-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations